26831 lines
1.8 MiB
26831 lines
1.8 MiB
A Thousand Plateaus
|
||
This page intentionally left blank
|
||
A THOUSAND
|
||
PLATEAUS
|
||
Capitalism and
|
||
Schizophrenia
|
||
|
||
Gilles Deleuze
|
||
Felix Guattari
|
||
Translation and Foreword by Brian Massumi
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
University of Minnesota Press
|
||
Minneapolis
|
||
London
|
||
The University of Minnesota Press gratefully
|
||
acknowledges translation assistance provided for this
|
||
book by the French Ministry of Culture and by the
|
||
National Endowment for the Humanities, an
|
||
independent federal agency.
|
||
|
||
Copyright © 1987 by the University of Minnesota Press
|
||
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced,
|
||
stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any
|
||
means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or
|
||
otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher.
|
||
Published by the University of Minnesota Press
|
||
111 Third Avenue South, Suite 290, Minneapolis, MN 55401-2520
|
||
http://www.upress.umn.edu
|
||
Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper
|
||
Eleventh printing 2005
|
||
|
||
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
|
||
Deleuze, Gilles.
|
||
[Mille plateaux. English]
|
||
A thousand plateaus: capitalism and schizophrenia/Gilles
|
||
Deleuze, Felix Guattari; translation and foreword by Brian
|
||
Massumi.
|
||
p. cm.
|
||
Translation of: Mille plateaux, v. 2 of Capitalisme et
|
||
schizophrénie.
|
||
A companion volume to Anti-Oedipus: capitalism and
|
||
schizophrenia.
|
||
Bibliography: p.
|
||
Includes index.
|
||
ISBN 0-8166-1401-6
|
||
ISBN 0-8166-1402-4 (pbk.)
|
||
1. Philosophy. I. Guattari, Félix. II. Title
|
||
B77.D413 1987
|
||
194-dcl9 87-18623
|
||
|
||
Originally published as Mille Plateaux, volume 2 of Capitalisme et
|
||
Schizophrénie © 1980 by Les Editions de Minuit, Paris.
|
||
|
||
Photo of Sylvano Bussoti, Five Pieces for Piano for David Tudor,
|
||
reproduced by permission of G. Ricordi, Milan, copyright © 1970
|
||
by G. Ricordi E.G. SPA; photo of Fernand Léger, Men in the
|
||
Cities, 1919, copyright © 1987 by ARS, N.Y./SPADEM; photo of
|
||
Paul Klee, Twittering Machine, 1922, reproduced by permission
|
||
of The Museum of Modern Art, N.Y., copyright © 1987 by
|
||
Cosmopress, Geneva.
|
||
|
||
The University of Minnesota
|
||
is an equal-opportunity
|
||
educator and employer.
|
||
Contents
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Translator's Foreword: Pleasures of Philosophy Brian Massumi ix
|
||
Notes on the Translation and Acknowledgments xvi
|
||
Author's Note xx
|
||
1. Introduction: Rhizome 3
|
||
Root, radicle, and rhizome—Issues concerning books—The One and
|
||
the Multiple—Tree and rhizome—The geographical directions,
|
||
Orient, Occident, America—The misdeeds of the tree—What is a
|
||
plateau?
|
||
2. 1914: One or Several Wolves? 26
|
||
Neurosis and psychosis—For a theory of multiplicities—Packs—The
|
||
unconscious and the molecular
|
||
3. 10,000 B.C.: The Geology of Morals (Who Does the Earth Think
|
||
It Is?) 39
|
||
Strata—Double articulation (segmentarity)—What constitutes the
|
||
unity of a stratum—Milieus—The diversity within a stratum: forms
|
||
and substances, epistrata and parastrata—Content and expression—
|
||
The diversity among strata—The molar and the molecular—Abstract
|
||
machine and assemblage: their comparative states—Metastrata
|
||
4. November 20, 1923: Postulates of Linguistics 75
|
||
The order-word—Indirect discourse—Order-words, acts, and incor-
|
||
V
|
||
vi D CONTENTS
|
||
|
||
poreal transformations—Dates—Content and expression, and their
|
||
respective variables—The aspects of the assemblage—Constants, var-
|
||
iables, and continuous variation—Music—Style—Major and minor
|
||
—Becoming—Death and escape, figure and metamorphosis
|
||
5. 5 87 B.C.-A.D. 70: On Several Regimes of Signs 111
|
||
The signifying despotic regime—The passional subjective regime—
|
||
The two kinds of delusion and the problem of psychiatry—The
|
||
ancient history of the Jewish people—The line of flight and the
|
||
prophet—The face, turning away, and betrayal—The Book—The sys-
|
||
tem of subjectivity: consciousness and passion, Doubles—Domestic
|
||
squabble and office squabble—Redundancy—The figures of deter-
|
||
ritorialization—Abstract machine and diagram—The generative, the
|
||
transformational, the diagrammatic, and the machinic
|
||
6. November 28, 1947: How Do You Make Yourself a Body
|
||
Without Organs? 149
|
||
The body without organs, waves and intensities—The egg—
|
||
Masochism, courtly love, and the Tao—The strata and the plane of
|
||
consistency—Antonin Artaud—The art of caution—The three-body
|
||
problem—Desire, plane, selection, and composition
|
||
7. Year Zero: Faciality 167
|
||
White wall, black hole—The abstract machine of faciality—Body,
|
||
head, and face—Face and landscape—The courtly novel—Theorems
|
||
of deterritorialization—The face and Christ—The two figures of the
|
||
face: frontal view and profile, the turning away—Dismantling the face
|
||
8. 1874: Three Novellas, or "What Happened?" 192
|
||
The novella and the tale: the secret—The three lines—Break, crack,
|
||
and rupture—The couple, the double, and the clandestine
|
||
9. 1933: Micropolitics and Segmentarity 208
|
||
Segmentarity, primitive and civilized—The molar and the molec-
|
||
ular—Fascism and totalitarianism—The segmented line and the
|
||
quantum flow—Gabriel Tarde—Masses and classes—The abstract
|
||
machine: mutation and overcoding—What is a power center?—The
|
||
three lines and the dangers of each—Fear, clarity, power, and death
|
||
10. 1730: Becoming-Intense, Becoming-Animal, Becoming-
|
||
Imperceptible . .. 232
|
||
Becoming—Three aspects of sorcery: multiplicity; the Anomalous, or
|
||
the Outsider; transformations—Individuation and Haecceity: five
|
||
o'clock in the evening—Longitude, latitude, and the plane of
|
||
consistency—The two planes, or the two conceptions of the plane—
|
||
CONTENTS D vii
|
||
|
||
Becoming-woman, becoming-child, becoming-animal, becoming-
|
||
molecular: zones of proximity—Becoming imperceptible—The
|
||
secret—Majority, minority, minoritarian—The minoritarian charac-
|
||
ter and dissymmetry of becoming: double becoming—Point and line,
|
||
memory and becoming—Becoming and block—The opposition
|
||
between punctual systems and multilinear systems—Music, painting,
|
||
and becomings—The refrain—Theorems of deterritorialization con-
|
||
tinued—Becoming versus imitation
|
||
11. 1837: Of the Refrain 310
|
||
In the dark, at home, toward the world—Milieus and rhythm—The
|
||
placard and the territory—Expression as style: rhythmic faces,
|
||
melodic landscapes—Bird song—Territoriality, assemblages, and
|
||
interassemblages—The territory and the earth, the Natal—The prob-
|
||
lem of consistency—Machinic assemblage and abstract machine—
|
||
Classicism and milieus—Romanticism, the territory, the earth, and
|
||
the people—Modern art and the cosmos—Form and substance, forces
|
||
and material—Music and refrains; the great and the small refrain
|
||
12. 1227: Treatise on Nomadology:—The War Machine 351
|
||
The two poles of the State—The irreducibility and exteriority of the
|
||
war machine—The man of war—Minor and major: the minor
|
||
sciences—The body and esprit de corps—Thought, the State, and
|
||
nomadology—First aspect: the war machine and nomad space—
|
||
Second aspect: the war machine and the composition of people, the
|
||
nomad number—Third aspect: the war machine and nomad affects
|
||
—Free action and work—The nature of assemblages: tools and signs,
|
||
arms and jewelry—Metallurgy, itinerancy, and nomadism—The
|
||
machinic phylum and technological lineages—Smooth space, stri-
|
||
ated space, holey space—The war machine and war: the complexities
|
||
of the relation
|
||
13. 7000 B.C.: Apparatus of Capture 424
|
||
The paleolithic State—Primitive groups, towns, States, and world-
|
||
wide organizations—Anticipate, ward off—The meaning of the word
|
||
"last" (marginalism)—Exchange and stock—Capture: landownership
|
||
(rent), fiscal organization (taxation), public works (profit)—The prob-
|
||
lem of violence—The forms of the State and the three ages of Law—
|
||
Capitalism and the State—Subjection and enslavement—Issues in
|
||
axiomatics
|
||
14. 1440: The Smooth and the Striated 474
|
||
The technological model (textile)—The musical model—The mari-
|
||
viii D CONTENTS
|
||
|
||
time model—The mathematical model (multiplicities)—The physi-
|
||
cal model—The aesthetic model (nomad art)
|
||
15. Conclusion: Concrete Rules and Abstract Machines 501
|
||
Notes 517
|
||
Bibliography (compiled by Brian Massumi) 579
|
||
Index 587
|
||
List of Illustrations 611
|
||
Translator's Foreword:
|
||
Pleasures of Philosophy
|
||
Brian Massumi
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
This is a book that speaks of many things, of ticks and quilts and fuzzy sub-
|
||
sets and noology and political economy. It is difficult to know how to
|
||
approach it. What do you do with a book that dedicates an entire chapter to
|
||
music and animal behavior—and then claims that it isn't a chapter? That
|
||
presents itself as a network of "plateaus" that are precisely dated, but can
|
||
be read in any order? That deploys a complex technical vocabulary drawn
|
||
from a wide range of disciplines in the sciences, mathematics, and the
|
||
humanities, but whose authors recommend that you read it as you would
|
||
listen to a record?1
|
||
"Philosophy, nothing but philosophy."2 Of a bastard line.
|
||
The annals of official philosophy are populated by "bureaucrats of pure
|
||
reason" who speak in "the shadow of the despot" and are in historical com-
|
||
plicity with the State.3 They invent "a properly spiritual... absolute State that
|
||
... effectively functions in the mind." Theirs is the discourse of sovereign
|
||
judgment, of stable subjectivity legislated by "good" sense, of rocklike iden-
|
||
tity, "universal" truth, and (white male) justice. "Thus the exercise of their
|
||
thought is in conformity with the aims of the real State, with the dominant sig-
|
||
nifications, and with the requirements of the established order."4
|
||
Gilles Deleuze was schooled in that philosophy. The titles of his earliest
|
||
ix
|
||
x D TRANSLATOR'S FOREWORD
|
||
|
||
books read like a Who's Who of philosophical giants. "What got me by dur-
|
||
ing that period was conceiving of the history of philosophy as a kind of ass-
|
||
fuck, or, what amounts to the same thing, an immaculate conception. I
|
||
imagined myself approaching an author from behind and giving him a child
|
||
that would indeed be his but would nonetheless be monstrous."5 Hegel is
|
||
absent, being too despicable to merit even a mutant offspring.6 To Kant he
|
||
dedicated an affectionate study of "an enemy." Yet much of positive value
|
||
came of Deleuze's flirtation with the greats. He discovered an orphan line of
|
||
thinkers who were tied by no direct descendance but were united in their
|
||
opposition to the State philosophy that would nevertheless accord them
|
||
minor positions in its canon. Between Lucretius, Hume, Spinoza,
|
||
Nietzsche, and Bergson there exists a "secret link constituted by the critique
|
||
of negativity, the cultivation of joy, the hatred of interiority, the exteriority of
|
||
forces and relations, the denunciation of power."7 Deleuze's first major
|
||
statements written in his own voice, Difference et repetition (1968) and
|
||
Logique du sens (1969), cross-fertilized that line of "nomad" thought with
|
||
contemporary theory. The ferment of the student-worker revolt of May 1968
|
||
and the reassessment it prompted of the role of the intellectual in society8 led
|
||
him to disclaim the "ponderous academic apparatus"9 still in evidence in
|
||
those works. However, many elements of the "philosophy of difference" they
|
||
elaborated were transfused into a continuing collaboration, of which A
|
||
Thousand Plateaus is the most recent product.
|
||
Felix Guattari is a practicing psychoanalyst and lifelong political activ-
|
||
ist. He has worked since the mid-1950s at La Borde, an experimental psy-
|
||
chiatric clinic founded by Lacanian analyst Jean Oury. Guattari himself
|
||
was among Lacan's earliest trainees, and although he never severed his ties
|
||
with Lacan's Freudian School the group therapy practiced at La Borde
|
||
took him in a very different direction. The aim at La Borde was to abolish
|
||
the hierarchy between doctor and patient in favor of an interactive group
|
||
dynamic that would bring the experiences of both to full expression in such
|
||
a way as to produce a collective critique of the power relations in society as
|
||
a whole. "The central perspective i s . . . to promote human relations that do
|
||
not automatically fall into roles or stereotypes but open onto fundamental
|
||
relations of a metaphysical kind that bring out the most radical and basic
|
||
alienations of madness or neurosis"10 and channel them into revolutionary
|
||
practice. Guattari collaborated beginning in 1960 on group projects dedi-
|
||
cated to developing this radical "institutional psychotherapy,"11 and later
|
||
entered an uneasy alliance with the international antipsychiatry move-
|
||
ment spearheaded by R.D. Laing in England and Franco Basaglia in Italy.12
|
||
As Lacanian schools of psychoanalysis gained ground against psychiatry,
|
||
the contractual Oedipal relationship between the analyst and the transfer-
|
||
ence-bound analysand became as much of a target for Guattari as the legal
|
||
TRANSLATOR'S FOREWORD D xi
|
||
|
||
bondage of the institutionalized patient in the conventional State hospital.
|
||
He came to occupy the same position in relation to psychoanalysis as he
|
||
had all along in relation to the parties of the left: an ultra-opposition within
|
||
the opposition. His antihierarchical leanings made him a precursor to the
|
||
events of May 1968 and an early partisan of the social movements that
|
||
grew from them, including feminism and the gay rights movement. ^Anti-
|
||
Oedipus (1972),u his first book with Deleuze, gave philosophical weight to
|
||
his convictions and created one of the intellectual sensations of postwar
|
||
France with its spirited polemics against State-happy or pro-party versions
|
||
of Marxism and school-building strains of psychoanalysis, which sepa-
|
||
rately and in various combinations represented the dominant intellectual
|
||
currents of the time (in spite of the fundamentally anarchist nature of the
|
||
spontaneous popular uprisings that had shaken the world in 1968). "The
|
||
most tangible result of Anti-Oedipus was that it short-circuited the connec-
|
||
tion between psychoanalysis and the far left parties," in which he and
|
||
Deleuze saw the potential for a powerful new bureaucracy of analytic
|
||
reason.15
|
||
For many French intellectuals, the hyperactivism of post-May gave way
|
||
to a mid-seventies slump, then a return to religion (Tel Quel) or political
|
||
conservatism (the Nouveaux Philosophes) in a foreshadowing of the
|
||
Reagan eighties. Deleuze and Guattari never recanted. Nor did they sim-
|
||
ply revive the polemics. A Thousand Plateaus (1980), written over a seven-
|
||
year period, was billed as a sequel to Anti-Oedipus and shares its subtitle,
|
||
Capitalism and Schizophrenia. But it constitutes a very different project. It
|
||
is less a critique than a positive exercise in the affirmative "nomad"
|
||
thought called for in Anti-Oedipus.
|
||
"State philosophy" is another word for the representational thinking
|
||
that has characterized Western metaphysics since Plato, but has suffered
|
||
an at least momentary setback during the last quarter century at the hands
|
||
of Jacques Derrida, Michel Foucault, and poststructuralist theory gener-
|
||
ally. As described by Deleuze,16 it reposes on a double identity: of the think-
|
||
ing subject, and of the concepts it creates and to which it lends its own
|
||
presumed attributes of sameness and constancy. The subject, its concepts,
|
||
and also the objects in the world to which the concepts are applied have a
|
||
shared, internal essence: the self-resemblance at the basis of identity. Rep-
|
||
resentational thought is analogical; its concern is to establish a correspon-
|
||
dence between these symmetrically structured domains. The faculty of
|
||
judgment is the policeman of analogy, assuring that each of the three terms
|
||
is honestly itself, and that the proper correspondences obtain. In thought
|
||
its end is truth, in action justice. The weapons it wields in their pursuit are
|
||
limitative distribution (the determination of the exclusive set of properties
|
||
possessed by each term in contradistinction to the others: logos, law) and
|
||
xii D TRANSLATOR'S FOREWORD
|
||
|
||
hierarchical ranking (the measurement of the degree of perfection of a
|
||
term's self-resemblance in relation to a supreme standard, man, god, or
|
||
gold: value, morality). The modus operandi is negation: x = x = noiy. Iden-
|
||
tity, resemblance, truth, justice, and negation. The rational foundation for
|
||
order. The established order, of course: philosophers have traditionally
|
||
been employees of the State. The collusion between philosophy and the
|
||
State was most explicitly enacted in the first decade of the nineteenth cen-
|
||
tury with the foundation of the University of Berlin, which was to become
|
||
the model for higher learning throughout Europe and in the United States.
|
||
The goal laid out for it by Wilhelm von Humboldt (based on proposals by
|
||
Fichte and Schleiermacher) was the "spiritual and moral training of the
|
||
nation," to be achieved by "deriving everything from an original principle"
|
||
(truth), by "relating everything to an ideal" (justice), and by "unifying this
|
||
principle and this ideal in a single Idea" (the State). The end product would
|
||
be "a fully legitimated subject of knowledge and society"17—each mind an
|
||
analogously organized mini-State morally unified in the supermind of the
|
||
State. Prussian mind-meld.18 More insidious than the well-known practi-
|
||
cal cooperation between university and government (the burgeoning mili-
|
||
tary funding of research) is its philosophical role in the propagation of the
|
||
form of representational thinking itself, that "properly spiritual absolute
|
||
State" endlessly reproduced and disseminated at every level of the social
|
||
fabric. Deconstruction-influenced feminists such as Helene Cixous and
|
||
Luce Irigaray have attacked it under the name "phallogocentrism" (what
|
||
the most privileged model of rocklike identity is goes without saying). In
|
||
the introduction to A Thousand Plateaus, Deleuze and Guattari describe it
|
||
as the "arborescent model" of thought (the proudly erect tree under whose
|
||
spreading boughs latter-day Platos conduct their class).
|
||
"Nomad thought" does not immure itself in the edifice of an ordered
|
||
interiority; it moves freely in an element of exteriority. It does not repose
|
||
on identity; it rides difference. It does not respect the artificial division
|
||
between the three domains of representation, subject, concept, and being;
|
||
it replaces restrictive analogy with a conductivity that knows no bounds.
|
||
The concepts it creates do not merely reflect the eternal form of a legislat-
|
||
ing subject, but are defined by a communicable force in relation to which
|
||
their subject, to the extent that they can be said to have one, is only secon-
|
||
dary. They do not reflect upon the world but are immersed in a changing
|
||
state of things. A concept is a brick. It can be used to build the courthouse of
|
||
reason. Or it can be thrown through the window. What is the subject of the
|
||
brick? The arm that throws it? The body connected to the arm? The brain
|
||
encased in the body? The situation that brought brain and body to such a
|
||
juncture? All and none of the above. What is its object? The window? The
|
||
edifice? The laws the edifice shelters? The class and other power relations
|
||
TRANSLATOR'S FOREWORD D xiii
|
||
|
||
encrusted in the laws? All and none of the above. "What interests us are the
|
||
circumstances."19 Because the concept in its unrestrained usage is a set of
|
||
circumstances, at a volatile juncture. It is a vector: the point of application
|
||
of a force moving through a space at a given velocity in a given direction.
|
||
The concept has no subject or object other than itself. It is an act. Nomad
|
||
thought replaces the closed equation of representation, x = x = noty (I = I
|
||
= not you) with an open equation:.. . + y + z + a + ...(...+ arm + brick +
|
||
window + . . .). Rather than analyzing the world into discrete components,
|
||
reducing their manyness to the One of identity, and ordering them by rank,
|
||
it sums up a set of disparate circumstances in a shattering blow. It synthe-
|
||
sizes a multiplicity of elements without effacing their heterogeneity or hin-
|
||
dering their potential for future rearranging (to the contrary). The modus
|
||
operandi of nomad thought is affirmation, even when its apparent object is
|
||
negative. Force is not to be confused with power. Force arrives from outside
|
||
to break constraints and open new vistas. Power builds walls.
|
||
The space of nomad thought is qualitatively different from State space.
|
||
Air against earth. State space is "striated," or gridded. Movement in it is
|
||
confined as by gravity to a horizontal plane, and limited by the order of
|
||
that plane to preset paths between fixed and identifiable points. Nomad
|
||
space is "smooth," or open-ended. One can rise up at any point and move
|
||
to any other. Its mode of distribution is the nomos: arraying oneself in an
|
||
open space (hold the street), as opposed to the logos of entrenching oneself
|
||
in a closed space (hold the fort).
|
||
A Thousand Plateaus is an effort to construct a smooth space of
|
||
thought. It is not the first such attempt. Like State philosophy, nomad
|
||
thought goes by many names. Spinoza called it "ethics." Nietzsche called
|
||
it the "gay science." Artaud called it "crowned anarchy." To Maurice
|
||
Blanchot, it is the "space of literature." To Foucault, "outside thought."20
|
||
In this book, Deleuze and Guattari employ the terms "pragmatics" and
|
||
"schizoanalysis," and in the introduction describe a rhizome network
|
||
strangling the roots of the infamous tree. One of the points of the book is
|
||
that nomad thought is not confined to philosophy. Or that the kind of phi-
|
||
losophy it is comes in many forms. Filmmakers and painters are philo-
|
||
sophical thinkers to the extent that they explore the potentials of their
|
||
respective mediums and break away from the beaten paths.21 On a strictly
|
||
formal level, it is mathematics and music that create the smoothest of the
|
||
smooth spaces.22 In fact, Deleuze and Guattari would probably be more
|
||
inclined to call philosophy music with content than music a rarefied form
|
||
of philosophy.
|
||
Which returns to our opening question. How should A Thousand Pla-
|
||
teaus be played? When you buy a record there are always cuts that leave you
|
||
cold. You skip them. You don't approach a record as a closed book that you
|
||
xiv D TRANSLATOR'S FOREWORD
|
||
|
||
have to take or leave. Other cuts you may listen to over and over again. They
|
||
follow you. You find yourself humming them under your breath as you go
|
||
about your daily business.
|
||
A Thousand Plateaus is conceived as an open system.23 It does not pre-
|
||
tend to have the final word. The authors' hope, however, is that elements of
|
||
it will stay with a certain number of its readers and will weave into the mel-
|
||
ody of their everyday lives.
|
||
Each "plateau" is an orchestration of crashing bricks extracted from a
|
||
variety of disciplinary edifices. They carry traces of their former emplace-
|
||
ment, which give them a spin defining the arc of their vector. The vectors
|
||
are meant to converge at a volatile juncture, but one that is sustained, as an
|
||
open equilibrium of moving parts each with its own trajectory. The word
|
||
"plateau" comes from an essay by Gregory Bateson on Balinese culture, in
|
||
which he found a libidinal economy quite different from the West's orgas-
|
||
mic orientation.24 In Deleuze and Guattari, a plateau is reached when cir-
|
||
cumstances combine to bring an activity to a pitch of intensity that is not
|
||
automatically dissipated in a climax. The heightening of energies is sus-
|
||
tained long enough to leave a kind of afterimage of its dynamism that can
|
||
be reactivated or injected into other activities, creating a fabric of intensive
|
||
states between which any number of connecting routes could exist. Each
|
||
section of A Thousand Plateaus tries to combine conceptual bricks in such
|
||
a way as to construct this kind of intensive state in thought. The way the
|
||
combination is made is an example of what Deleuze and Guattari call
|
||
consistency—not in the sense of a homogeneity, but as a holding together
|
||
of disparate elements (also known as a "style").25 A style in this sense, as a
|
||
dynamic holding together or mode of composition, is not something lim-
|
||
ited to writing. Filmmakers, painters, and musicians have their styles,
|
||
mathematicians have theirs, rocks have style, and so do tools, and technol-
|
||
ogies, and historical periods, even—especially—punctual events. Each
|
||
section is dated, because each tries to reconstitute a dynamism that has
|
||
existed in other mediums at other times. The date corresponds to the point
|
||
at which that particular dynamism found its purest incarnation in matter,
|
||
the point at which it was freest from interference from other modes and
|
||
rose to its highest degree of intensity. That never lasts more than a flash,
|
||
because the world rarely leaves room for uncommon intensity, being in
|
||
large measure an entropic trashbin of outworn modes that refuse to die.
|
||
Section 12, for example, the "Treatise on Nomadology," is dated 1227 A.D.
|
||
because that is when the nomad war machine existed for a moment in its
|
||
pure form on the vacant smooth spaces of the steppes of Inner Asia.
|
||
The reader is invited to follow each section to the plateau that rises from
|
||
the smooth space of its composition, and to move from one plateau to the
|
||
next at pleasure. But it is just as good to ignore the heights. You can take a
|
||
TRANSLATOR'S FOREWORD D xv
|
||
|
||
concept that is particularly to your liking and jump with it to its next
|
||
appearance. They tend to cycle back. Some might call that repetitious.
|
||
Deleuze and Guattari call it a refrain.
|
||
Most of all, the reader is invited to lift a dynamism out of the book
|
||
entirely, and incarnate it in a foreign medium, whether it be painting or
|
||
politics. The authors steal from other disciplines with glee, but they are
|
||
more than happy to return the favor. Deleuze's own image for a concept is
|
||
not a brick, but a "tool box."26 He calls his kind of philosophy "pragmatics"
|
||
because its goal is the invention of concepts that do not add up to a system
|
||
of belief or an architecture of propositions that you either enter or you
|
||
don't, but instead pack a potential in the way a crowbar in a willing hand
|
||
envelops an energy of prying.
|
||
The best way of all to approach the book is to read it as a challenge: to pry
|
||
open the vacant spaces that would enable you to build your life and those of
|
||
the people around you into a plateau of intensity that would leave afterim-
|
||
ages of its dynamism that could be reinjected into still other lives, creating
|
||
a fabric of heightened states between which any number, the greatest num-
|
||
ber, of connecting routes would exist. Some might call that promiscuous.
|
||
Deleuze and Guattari call it revolution.
|
||
The question is not: is it true? But: does it work? What new thoughts
|
||
does it make it possible to think? What new emotions does it make it possi-
|
||
ble to feel? What new sensations and perceptions does it open in the body?
|
||
The answer for some readers, perhaps most, will be "none." If that hap-
|
||
pens, it's not your tune. No problem. But you would have been better off
|
||
buying a record.
|
||
Notes on the Translation
|
||
and
|
||
Acknowledgments
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
AFFECT/AFFECTION. Neither word denotes a personal feeling (sentiment
|
||
in Deleuze and Guattari). L 'affect (Spinoza's affectus) is an ability to affect
|
||
and be affected. It is a prepersonal intensity corresponding to the passage
|
||
from one experiential state of the body to another and implying an
|
||
augmentation or diminution in that body's capacity to act. L'affection
|
||
(Spinoza's affectio) is each such State considered as an encouner between
|
||
the affected body and a second, affecting, body (with body taken in its
|
||
broadest possible sense to include "mental" or ideal bodies).
|
||
DRAW. In A Thousand Plateaus, to draw is an act of creation. What is
|
||
drawn (the Body without Organs, the plane of consistency, a line of flight)
|
||
does not preexist the act of drawing. The French word tracer captures this
|
||
better: It has all the graphic connotations of "to draw" in English, but can
|
||
also mean to blaze a trail or open a road. "To trace" (d'ecalquer), on the
|
||
other hand, is to copy something from a model.
|
||
FLIGHT/ESCAPE. Both words translate fuite, which has a different range
|
||
of meanings than either of the English terms. Fuite covers not only the act
|
||
of fleeing or eluding but also flowing, leaking, and disappearing into the
|
||
distance (the vanishing point in a painting is a point de fuite). It has no rela-
|
||
tion to flying.
|
||
xvi
|
||
NOTES ON THE TRANSLATION AND ACKNOWLEDGMENTS D xvii
|
||
|
||
MILIEU. In French, milieu means "surroundings," "medium" (as in
|
||
chemistry), and "middle." In the philosophy of Deleuze and Guattari,
|
||
"milieu" should be read as a technical term combining all three meanings.
|
||
PLANE. The word plan designates both a "plane" in the geometrical sense
|
||
and a "plan." The authors use it primarily in the first sense. Where both
|
||
meanings seem to be present (as in discussions of the plan d'organisatori)
|
||
"plan(e)" has been used in the translation.
|
||
POWER. Two words for "power" exist in French, puissance and pouvoir.
|
||
In Deleuze and Guattari, they are associated with very different concepts
|
||
(although the terminological distinction is not consistently observed).
|
||
Puissance refers to a range of potential. It has been defined by Deleuze as a
|
||
"capacity for existence," "a capacity to affect or be affected," a capacity to
|
||
multiply connections that may be realized by a given "body" to varying
|
||
degrees in different situations. It may be thought of as a scale of intensity or
|
||
fullness of existence (or a degree on such a scale), analogous to the capacity
|
||
of a number to be raised to a higher "power." It is used in the French trans-
|
||
lation of Nietzsche's term "will to power." Like its English counterpart, it
|
||
has an additional mathematical usage, designating the number of elements
|
||
in a finite or infinite set. Here, puissance pertains to the virtual (the plane
|
||
of consistency), pouvoir to the actual (the plane of organization). The
|
||
authors use pouvoir in a sense very close to Foucault's, as an instituted and
|
||
reproducible relation offeree, a selective concretization of potential. Both
|
||
puissance and pouvoir have been translated here as "power," since the dis-
|
||
tinction between the concepts is usually clear from the context. The French
|
||
terms have been added in parentheses where confusion might arise, and in
|
||
occasional passages where puissance is rendered as "potential."
|
||
PROCESS/PROCEEDING. The authors employ two words normally trans-
|
||
lated as "process." Processus in their usage is the more general of the two,
|
||
covering both the stratified and destratified dimensions of an occurrence.
|
||
Proces pertains only to the stratification. In standard French, proces also
|
||
means "trial" (as in the title of the Kafka novel). Deleuze and Guattari
|
||
exploit this polysemy as a way of emphasizing the role of organizations of
|
||
social power and regimes of signs in operations constitutive of the subject,
|
||
or proces de subjectivation. Proces is usually (once again, there is slippage in
|
||
their usage) translated as "proceeding," despite the occasional awkward-
|
||
ness this produces in English, in an attempt to preserve both associations: a
|
||
process, or way of proceeding, and a legal proceeding, or trial. Processus is
|
||
always "process."
|
||
SELF. Both Moi and Soi have usually been translated as "Self," with the
|
||
French in brackets. Soi is the self in its broadest sense, but as a neuter third-
|
||
person pronoun implies an impersonality at the basis of the self. Moi is a
|
||
xviii D NOTES ON THE TRANSLATION AND ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
|
||
|
||
more restricted concept: the "me" as subject of enunciation for the "I" (je)
|
||
as subj ect of the statement. It is also the French term for the Freudian ego.
|
||
SIGNIFIANCE/INTERPRETANCE. I have followed the increasingly com-
|
||
mon practice of importing signifiance and interpretanceinto English with-
|
||
out modification. In Deleuze and Guattari these terms refer respectively to
|
||
the syntagmatic and paradigmatic processes of language as a "signifying
|
||
regime of signs." They are borrowed from Benveniste ("signifying capac-
|
||
ity" and "interpretative capacity" are the English translations used in
|
||
Benveniste's work).
|
||
STATEMENT. Enonce (often "utterance") has been translated here as
|
||
"statement," in keeping with the choice of the English translators of
|
||
Foucault, to whose conception Deleuze and Guattari's is closest. "Enunci-
|
||
ation" is used for enonciation.
|
||
TRAIT. The word trait has a range of meanings not covered by any single
|
||
word in English. Literally, it refers to a graphic drawing, and to the act of
|
||
drawing a line. Abstractly, it is the purely graphic element. Figuratively, it
|
||
is an identifying mark (a feature, or trait in the English sense), or any act
|
||
constituting a mark or sign. In linguistics, "distinctive features" (traits
|
||
distinctifs or traits pertinents) are the elementary units of language that
|
||
combine to form a phoneme. Trait also refers to a projectile, especially an
|
||
arrow, and to the act of throwing a projectile. Here, "trait" has been
|
||
retained in all but narrowly linguistic contexts.
|
||
GENDER-BIASED USAGE has been largely eliminated through plural-
|
||
ization or the use of male and female pronouns. However, where Deleuze
|
||
and Guattari seem deliberately to be using "man" to designate a socially
|
||
constructed, patriarchal standard of human behavior applied to both men
|
||
and women, the masculine generic has been retained.
|
||
|
||
|
||
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS. I would like to express my gratitude to the
|
||
National Endowment for the Humanities and the French Ministry of Cul-
|
||
ture for their generous assistance, without which this translation would not
|
||
have been possible, and to the authors for their patience in answering my
|
||
questions. Winnie Berman, Ken Dean, Nannie Doyle, Shoshana Felman,
|
||
Jim Fleming, Robert Hurley, Fredric Jameson, Sylvere Lotringer, Susan
|
||
McClary, Giorgio Passerone, Paul Patton, Dana Polan, Mary Quaintance,
|
||
Michael Ryan, Lianne Sullivan, Susan Yazijian, and Caveh Zahedi pro-
|
||
vided much-appreciated aid and advice. Glenn Hendler likes to see his
|
||
name in print.
|
||
I consulted the following translations: "Rhizome" (first version), trans.
|
||
Paul Foss and Paul Patton, Ideology and Consciousness, no. 8 (Spring 1981,
|
||
NOTES ON THE TRANSLATION AND ACKNOWLEDGMENTS D xix
|
||
|
||
pp. 49-71); "Rhizome" (final version), trans. John Johnston in Deleuze
|
||
and Guattari, On the Line (New York: Semiotext[e], 1983); "One or Sev-
|
||
eral Wolves?" (first version), trans. Mark Seem, Semiotext(e), vol. 2, no. 3,
|
||
pp. 137-147 (1977); "How to Make Yourself a Body without Organs" (first
|
||
version, abridged), trans. Suzanne Guerlac, Semiotext(e) vol. 4, no. 1
|
||
(1981), pp. 265-270.
|
||
Portions of this translation have appeared previously. "Treatise on
|
||
Nomadology" was published as a separate book entitled Nomad Machine
|
||
(New York: Semiotext(e), 1986). Extracts from "Becoming-Intense ..."
|
||
appeared under the title "Becoming-Woman" in Subjects/Objects, no. 3
|
||
(Spring 1985), pp. 24-32, and from "The Smooth and the Striated" under
|
||
the title "Nomad Art" mArtandText, no. 19(Oct.-Nov. 1985), pp. 16-23.
|
||
Authors' Note
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
This book is the companion volume to Anti-Oedipus (paperback ed., Uni-
|
||
versity of Minnesota Press, 1983). Together they make up Capitalism and
|
||
Schizophrenia.
|
||
It is composed not of chapters but of "plateaus." We will try to explain
|
||
why later on (and also why the texts are dated). To a certain extent, these
|
||
plateaus may be read independently of one another, except the conclusion,
|
||
which should be read at the end.
|
||
A Thousand Plateaus
|
||
This page intentionally left blank
|
||
1. Introduction: Rhizome
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
The two of us wrote Anti-Oedipus together. Since each of us was several,
|
||
there was already quite a crowd. Here we have made use of everything that
|
||
came within range, what was closest as well as farthest away. We have
|
||
assigned clever pseudonyms to prevent recognition. Why have we kept our
|
||
own names? Out of habit, purely out of habit. To make ourselves unrecog-
|
||
nizable in turn. To render imperceptible, not ourselves, but what makes us
|
||
act, feel, and think. Also because it's nice to talk like everybody else, to say
|
||
the sun rises, when everybody knows it's only a manner of speaking. To
|
||
reach, not the point where one no longer says I, but the point where it is no
|
||
longer of any importance whether one says I. We are no longer ourselves.
|
||
Each will know his own. We have been aided, inspired, multiplied.
|
||
A book has neither object nor subject; it is made of variously formed
|
||
matters, and very different dates and speeds. To attribute the book to a
|
||
subject is to overlook this working of matters, and the exteriority of their
|
||
relations. It is to fabricate a beneficent God to explain geological move-
|
||
ments. In a book, as in all things, there are lines of articulation or
|
||
segmentarity, strata and territories; but also lines of flight, movements of
|
||
deterritorialization and destratification. Comparative rates of flow on
|
||
3
|
||
4 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
these lines produce phenomena of relative slowness and viscosity, or, on
|
||
the contrary, of acceleration and rupture. All this, lines and measurable
|
||
speeds, constitutes an assemblage. A book is an assemblage of this kind,
|
||
and as such is unattributable. It is a multiplicity—but we don't know yet
|
||
what the multiple entails when it is no longer attributed, that is, after it has
|
||
been elevated to the status of a substantive. One side of a machinic assem-
|
||
blage faces the strata, which doubtless make it a kind of organism, or signi-
|
||
fying totality, or determination attributable to a subject; it also has a side
|
||
facing a body without organs, which is continually dismantling the organ-
|
||
ism, causing asignifying particles or pure intensities to pass or circulate,
|
||
and attributing to itself subjects that it leaves with nothing more than a
|
||
name as the trace of an intensity. What is the body without organs of a
|
||
book? There are several, depending on the nature of the lines considered,
|
||
their particular grade or density, and the possibility of their converging on
|
||
a "plane of consistency" assuring their selection. Here, as elsewhere, the
|
||
units of measure are what is essential: quantify writing. There is no differ-
|
||
ence between what a book talks about and how it is made. Therefore a book
|
||
also has no object. As an assemblage, a book has only itself, in connection
|
||
with other assemblages and in relation to other bodies without organs. We
|
||
will never ask what a book means, as signified or signifier; we will not look
|
||
for anything to understand in it. We will ask what it functions with, in con-
|
||
nection with what other things it does or does not transmit intensities, in
|
||
which other multiplicities its own are inserted and metamorphosed, and
|
||
with what bodies without organs it makes its own converge. A book exists
|
||
only through the outside and on the outside. A book itself is a little
|
||
machine; what is the relation (also measurable) of this literary machine to a
|
||
war machine, love machine, revolutionary machine, etc.—and an abstract
|
||
machine that sweeps them along? We have been criticized for overquoting
|
||
literary authors. But when one writes, the only question is which other
|
||
machine the literary machine can be plugged into, must be plugged into in
|
||
order to work. Kleist and a mad war machine, Kafka and a most extraordi-
|
||
nary bureaucratic machine . . . (What if one became animal or plant
|
||
through literature, which certainly does not mean literarily? Is it not first
|
||
through the voice that one becomes animal?) Literature is an assemblage.
|
||
It has nothing to do with ideology. There is no ideology and never has been.
|
||
All we talk about are multiplicities, lines, strata and segmentarities,
|
||
lines of flight and intensities, machinic assemblages and their various
|
||
types, bodies without organs and their construction and selection, the
|
||
plane of consistency, and in each case the units of measure. Stratometers,
|
||
deleometers, BwO units of density, BwO units of convergence: Not only do
|
||
these constitute a quantification of writing, but they define writing as
|
||
always the measure of something else. Writing has nothing to do with
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 5
|
||
|
||
signifying. It has to do with surveying, mapping, even realms that are yet to
|
||
come.
|
||
A first type of book is the root-book. The tree is already the image of the
|
||
world, or the root the image of the world-tree. This is the classical book, as
|
||
noble, signifying, and subjective organic interiority (the strata of the book).
|
||
The book imitates the world, as art imitates nature: by procedures specific
|
||
to it that accomplish what nature cannot or can no longer do. The law of the
|
||
book is the law of reflection, the One that becomes two. How could the law
|
||
of the book reside in nature, when it is what presides over the very division
|
||
between world and book, nature and art? One becomes two: whenever we
|
||
encounter this formula, even stated strategically by Mao or understood in
|
||
the most "dialectical" way possible, what we have before us is the most clas-
|
||
sical and well reflected, oldest, and weariest kind of thought. Nature
|
||
doesn't work that way: in nature, roots are taproots with a more multiple,
|
||
lateral, and circular system of ramification, rather than a dichotomous
|
||
one. Thought lags behind nature. Even the book as a natural reality is a tap-
|
||
root, with its pivotal spine and surrounding leaves. But the book as a spiri-
|
||
tual reality, the Tree or Root as an image, endlessly develops the law of the
|
||
One that becomes two, then of the two that become four. . . Binary logic is
|
||
the spiritual reality of the root-tree. Even a discipline as "advanced" as lin-
|
||
guistics retains the root-tree as its fundamental image, and thus remains
|
||
wedded to classical reflection (for example, Chomsky and his grammatical
|
||
trees, which begin at a point S and proceed by dichotomy). This is as much
|
||
as to say that this system of thought has never reached an understanding of
|
||
multiplicity: in order to arrive at two following a spiritual method it must
|
||
assume a strong principal unity. On the side of the object, it is no doubt pos-
|
||
sible, following the natural method, to go directly from One to three, four,
|
||
or five, but only if there is a strong principal unity available, that of the piv-
|
||
otal taproot supporting the secondary roots. That doesn't get us very far.
|
||
The binary logic of dichotomy has simply been replaced by biunivocal rela-
|
||
tionships between successive circles. The pivotal taproot provides no bet-
|
||
ter understanding of multiplicity than the dichotomous root. One operates
|
||
in the object, the other in the subject. Binary logic and biunivocal relation-
|
||
ships still dominate psychoanalysis (the tree of delusion in the Freudian
|
||
interpretation of Schreber's case), linguistics, structuralism, and even
|
||
information science.
|
||
The radicle-system, or fascicular root, is the second figure of the book,
|
||
to which our modernity pays willing allegiance. This time, the principal
|
||
root has aborted, or its tip has been destroyed; an immediate, indefinite
|
||
multiplicity of secondary roots grafts onto it and undergoes a flourishing
|
||
development. This time, natural reality is what aborts the principal root,
|
||
but the root's unity subsists, as past or yet to come, as possible. We must ask
|
||
6 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
if reflexive, spiritual reality does not compensate for this state of things by
|
||
demanding an even more comprehensive secret unity, or a more extensive
|
||
totality. Take William Burroughs's cut-up method: the folding of one text
|
||
onto another, which constitutes multiple and even adventitious roots (like
|
||
a cutting), implies a supplementary dimension to that of the texts under
|
||
consideration. In this supplementary dimension of folding, unity contin-
|
||
ues its spiritual labor. That is why the most resolutely fragmented work can
|
||
also be presented as the Total Work or Magnum Opus. Most modern meth-
|
||
ods for making series proliferate or a multiplicity grow are perfectly valid
|
||
in one direction, for example, a linear direction, whereas a unity of
|
||
totalization asserts itself even more firmly in another, circular or cyclic,
|
||
dimension. Whenever a multiplicity is taken up in a structure, its growth is
|
||
offset by a reduction in its laws of combination. The abortionists of unity
|
||
are indeed angel makers, doctores angelici, because they affirm a properly
|
||
angelic and superior unity. Joyce's words, accurately described as having
|
||
"multiple roots," shatter the linear unity of the word, even of language,
|
||
only to posit a cyclic unity of the sentence, text, or knowledge. Nietzsche's
|
||
aphorisms shatter the linear unity of knowledge, only to invoke the cyclic
|
||
unity of the eternal return, present as the nonknown in thought. This is as
|
||
much as to say that the fascicular system does not really break with dual-
|
||
ism, with the complementarity between a subject and an object, a natural
|
||
reality and a spiritual reality: unity is consistently thwarted and obstructed
|
||
in the object, while a new type of unity triumphs in the subject. The world
|
||
has lost its pivot; the subject can no longer even dichotomize, but accedes
|
||
to a higher unity, of ambivalence or overdetermination, in an always sup-
|
||
plementary dimension to that of its object. The world has become chaos,
|
||
but the book remains the image of the world: radicle-chaosmos rather than
|
||
root-cosmos. A strange mystification: a book all the more total for being
|
||
fragmented. At any rate, what a vapid idea, the book as the image of the
|
||
world. In truth, it is not enough to say, "Long live the multiple," difficult as
|
||
it is to raise that cry. No typographical, lexical, or even syntactical clever-
|
||
ness is enough to make it heard. The multiple must be made, not by always
|
||
adding a higher dimension, but rather in the simplest of ways, by dint of
|
||
sobriety, with the number of dimensions one already has available—
|
||
always n - 1 (the only way the one belongs to the multiple: always sub-
|
||
tracted). Subtract the unique from the multiplicity to be constituted; write
|
||
at n - 1 dimensions. A system of this kind could be called a rhizome. A rhi-
|
||
zome as subterranean stem is absolutely different from roots and radicles.
|
||
Bulbs and tubers are rhizomes. Plants with roots or radicles may be
|
||
rhizomorphic in other respects altogether: the question is whether plant
|
||
life in its specificity is not entirely rhizomatic. Even some animals are, in
|
||
their pack form. Rats are rhizomes. Burrows are too, in all of their func-
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 7
|
||
|
||
tions of shelter, supply, movement, evasion, and breakout. The rhizome
|
||
itself assumes very diverse forms, from ramified surface extension in all
|
||
directions to concretion into bulbs and tubers. When rats swarm over each
|
||
other. The rhizome includes the best and the worst: potato and couchgrass,
|
||
or the weed. Animal and plant, couchgrass is crabgrass. We get the distinct
|
||
feeling that we will convince no one unless we enumerate certain approxi-
|
||
mate characteristics of the rhizome.
|
||
1 and 2. Principles of connection and heterogeneity: any point of a rhi-
|
||
zome can be connected to anything other, and must be. This is very differ-
|
||
ent from the tree or root, which plots a point, fixes an order. The linguistic
|
||
tree on the Chomsky model still begins at a point S and proceeds by dichot-
|
||
omy. On the contrary, not every trait in a rhizome is necessarily linked to a
|
||
linguistic feature: semiotic chains of every nature are connected to very
|
||
diverse modes of coding (biological, political, economic, etc.) that bring
|
||
into play not only different regimes of signs but also states of things of dif-
|
||
fering status. Collective assemblages of enunciation function directly
|
||
within machinic assemblages; it is not impossible to make a radical break
|
||
between regimes of signs and their objects. Even when linguistics claims to
|
||
confine itself to what is explicit and to make no presuppositions about lan-
|
||
guage, it is still in the sphere of a discourse implying particular modes of
|
||
assemblage and types of social power. Chomsky's grammaticality, the cate-
|
||
gorical S symbol that dominates every sentence, is more fundamentally a
|
||
marker of power than a syntactic marker: you will construct grammatically
|
||
correct sentences, you will divide each statement into a noun phrase and a
|
||
verb phrase (first dichotomy . . .). Our criticism of these linguistic models
|
||
is not that they are too abstract but, on the contrary, that they are not
|
||
abstract enough, that they do not reach the abstract machine that connects
|
||
a language to the semantic and pragmatic contents of statements, to collec-
|
||
tive assemblages of enunciation, to a whole micropolitics of the social
|
||
field. A rhizome ceaselessly establishes connections between semiotic
|
||
chains, organizations of power, and circumstances relative to the arts, sci-
|
||
ences, and social struggles. A semiotic chain is like a tuber agglomerating
|
||
very diverse acts, not only linguistic, but also perceptive, mimetic,
|
||
gestural, and cognitive: there is no language in itself, nor are there any lin-
|
||
guistic universals, only a throng of dialects, patois, slangs, and specialized
|
||
languages. There is no ideal speaker-listener, any more than there is a
|
||
homogeneous linguistic community. Language is, in Weinreich's words,
|
||
"an essentially heterogeneous reality."1 There is no mother tongue, only a
|
||
power takeover by a dominant language within a political multiplicity.
|
||
Language stabilizes around a parish, a bishopric, a capital. It forms a bulb.
|
||
It evolves by subterranean stems and flows, along river valleys or train
|
||
tracks; it spreads like a patch of oil.2 It is always possible to break a language
|
||
8 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
down into internal structural elements, an undertaking not fundamentally
|
||
different from a search for roots. There is always something genealogical
|
||
about a tree. It is not a method for the people. A method of the rhizome
|
||
type, on the contrary, can analyze language only by decentering it onto
|
||
other dimensions and other registers. A language is never closed upon
|
||
itself, except as a function of impotence.
|
||
3. Principle of multiplicity: it is only when the multiple is effectively
|
||
treated as a substantive, "multiplicity," that it ceases to have any relation to
|
||
the One as subject or object, natural or spiritual reality, image and world.
|
||
Multiplicities are rhizomatic, and expose arborescent pseudomulti-
|
||
plicities for what they are. There is no unity to serve as a pivot in the object,
|
||
or to divide in the subject. There is not even the unity to abort in the object
|
||
or "return" in the subject. A multiplicity has neither subject nor object,
|
||
only determinations, magnitudes, and dimensions that cannot increase in
|
||
number without the multiplicity changing in nature (the laws of combina-
|
||
tion therefore increase in number as the multiplicity grows). Puppet
|
||
strings, as a rhizome or multiplicity, are tied not to the supposed will of an
|
||
artist or puppeteer but to a multiplicity of nerve fibers, which form another
|
||
puppet in other dimensions connected to the first: "Call the strings or
|
||
rods that move the puppet the weave. It might be objected that its multi-
|
||
plicity resides in the person of the actor, who projects it into the text.
|
||
Granted; but the actor's nerve fibers in turn form a weave. And they fall
|
||
through the gray matter, the grid, into the undifferentiated... . The inter-
|
||
play approximates the pure activity of weavers attributed in myth to the
|
||
Fates or Norns."3 An assemblage is precisely this increase in the dimen-
|
||
sions of a multiplicity that necessarily changes in nature as it expands its
|
||
connections. There are no points or positions in a rhizome, such as those
|
||
found in a structure, tree, or root. There are only lines. When Glenn Gould
|
||
speeds up the performance of a piece, he is not just displaying virtuosity, he
|
||
is transforming the musical points into lines, he is making the whole piece
|
||
proliferate. The number is no longer a universal concept measuring ele-
|
||
ments according to their emplacement in a given dimension, but has itself
|
||
become a multiplicity that varies according to the dimensions considered
|
||
(the primacy of the domain over a complex of numbers attached to that
|
||
domain). We do not have units (unites) of measure, only multiplicities or
|
||
varieties of measurement. The notion of unity (unite) appears only when
|
||
there is a power takeover in the multiplicity by the signifier or a corre-
|
||
sponding subjectification proceeding: This is the case for a pivot-unity
|
||
forming the basis for a set of biunivocal relationships between objective
|
||
elements or points, or for the One that divides following the law of a binary
|
||
logic of differentiation in the subject. Unity always operates in an empty
|
||
dimension supplementary to that of the system considered (overcoding).
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 9
|
||
|
||
The point is that a rhizome or multiplicity never allows itself to be
|
||
overcoded, never has available a supplementary dimension over and
|
||
above its number of lines, that is, over and above the multiplicity of num-
|
||
bers attached to those lines. All multiplicities are flat, in the sense that they
|
||
fill or occupy all of their dimensions: we will therefore speak of a plane of
|
||
consistency of multiplicities, even though the dimensions of this "plane"
|
||
increase with the number of connections that are made on it. Multiplicities
|
||
are defined by the outside: by the abstract line, the line of flight or
|
||
deterritorialization according to which they change in nature and connect
|
||
with other multiplicities. The plane of consistency (grid) is the outside of
|
||
all multiplicities. The line of flight marks: the reality of a finite number of
|
||
dimensions that the multiplicity effectively fills; the impossibility of a sup-
|
||
plementary dimension, unless the multiplicity is transformed by the line of
|
||
flight; the possibility and necessity of flattening all of the multiplicities on
|
||
a single plane of consistency or exteriority, regardless of their number of
|
||
dimensions. The ideal for a book would be to lay everything out on a plane
|
||
of exteriority of this kind, on a single page, the same sheet: lived events, his-
|
||
torical determinations, concepts, individuals, groups, social formations.
|
||
Kleist invented a writing of this type, a broken chain of affects and variable
|
||
speeds, with accelerations and transformations, always in a relation with
|
||
the outside. Open rings. His texts, therefore, are opposed in every way to
|
||
the classical or romantic book constituted by the interiority of a substance
|
||
or subject. The war machine-book against the State apparatus-book. Flat
|
||
multiplicities ofn dimensions are asignifying and asubjective. They are
|
||
designated by indefinite articles, or rather by partitives (some couchgrass,
|
||
some of a rhizome . ..).
|
||
4. Principle of asignifying rupture: against the oversignifying breaks
|
||
separating structures or cutting across a single structure. A rhizome may be
|
||
broken, shattered at a given spot, but it will start up again on one of its old
|
||
lines, or on new lines. You can never get rid of ants because they form an
|
||
animal rhizome that can rebound time and again after most of it has been
|
||
destroyed. Every rhizome contains lines of segmentarity according to
|
||
which it is stratified, territorialized, organized, signified, attributed, etc.,
|
||
as well as lines of deterritorialization down which it constantly flees. There
|
||
is a rupture in the rhizome whenever segmentary lines explode into a line
|
||
of flight, but the line of flight is part of the rhizome. These lines always tie
|
||
back to one another. That is why one can never posit a dualism or a dichot-
|
||
omy, even in the rudimentary form of the good and the bad. You may make
|
||
a rupture, draw a line of flight, yet there is still a danger that you will
|
||
reencounter organizations that restratify everything, formations that
|
||
restore power to a signifier, attributions that reconstitute a subject—
|
||
anything you like, from Oedipal resurgences to fascist concretions. Groups
|
||
10 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
and individuals contain microfascisms just waiting to crystallize. Yes,
|
||
couchgrass is also a rhizome. Good and bad are only the products of an
|
||
active and temporary selection, which must be renewed.
|
||
How could movements of deterritorialization and processes of reterri-
|
||
torialization not be relative, always connected, caught up in one another?
|
||
The orchid deterritorializes by forming an image, a tracing of a wasp; but
|
||
the wasp reterritorializes on that image. The wasp is nevertheless
|
||
deterritorialized, becoming a piece in the orchid's reproductive apparatus.
|
||
But it reterritorializes the orchid by transporting its pollen. Wasp and
|
||
orchid, as heterogeneous elements, form a rhizome. It could be said that
|
||
the orchid imitates the wasp, reproducing its image in a signifying fashion
|
||
(mimesis, mimicry, lure, etc.). But this is true only on the level of the
|
||
strata—a parallelism between two strata such that a plant organization on
|
||
one imitates an animal organization on the other. At the same time, some-
|
||
thing else entirely is going on: not imitation at all but a capture of code, sur-
|
||
plus value of code, an increase in valence, a veritable becoming, a
|
||
becoming-wasp of the orchid and a becoming-orchid of the wasp. Each of
|
||
these becomings brings about the deterritorialization of one term and the
|
||
reterritorialization of the other; the two becomings interlink and form
|
||
relays in a circulation of intensities pushing the deterritorialization ever
|
||
further. There is neither imitation nor resemblance, only an exploding of
|
||
two heterogeneous series on the line of flight composed by a common rhi-
|
||
zome that can no longer be attributed to or subjugated by anything signify-
|
||
ing. Remy Chauvin expresses it well: "the aparallel evolution of two beings
|
||
that have absolutely nothing to do with each other."4 More generally, evolu-
|
||
tionary schemas may be forced to abandon the old model of the tree and
|
||
descent. Under certain conditions, a virus can connect to germ cells and
|
||
transmit itself as the cellular gene of a complex species; moreover, it can
|
||
take flight, move into the cells of an entirely different species, but not with-
|
||
out bringing with it "genetic information" from the first host (for example,
|
||
Benveniste and Todaro's current research on a type C virus, with its double
|
||
connection to baboon DNA and the DNA of certain kinds of domestic
|
||
cats). Evolutionary schemas would no longer follow models of arborescent
|
||
descent going from the least to the most differentiated, but instead a rhi-
|
||
zome operating immediately in the heterogeneous and jumping from one
|
||
already differentiated line to another.5 Once again, there is aparallel evolu-
|
||
tion, of the baboon and the cat; it is obvious that they are not models or cop-
|
||
ies of each other (a becoming-baboon in the cat does not mean that the cat
|
||
"plays" baboon). We form a rhizome with our viruses, or rather our viruses
|
||
cause us to form a rhizome with other animals. As Francois Jacob says,
|
||
transfers of genetic material by viruses or through other procedures,
|
||
fusions of cells originating in different species, have results analogous to
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 11
|
||
|
||
those of "the abominable couplings dear to antiquity and the Middle
|
||
Ages."6 Transversal communications between different lines scramble the
|
||
genealogical trees. Always look for the molecular, or even submolecular,
|
||
particle with which we are allied. We evolve and die more from our
|
||
polymorphous and rhizomatic flus than from hereditary diseases, or
|
||
diseases that have their own line of descent. The rhizome is an anti-
|
||
genealogy.
|
||
The same applies to the book and the world: contrary to a deeply rooted
|
||
belief, the book is not an image of the world. It forms a rhizome with the
|
||
world, there is an aparallel evolution of the book and the world; the book
|
||
assures the deterritorialization of the world, but the world effects a reterri-
|
||
torialization of the book, which in turn deterritorializes itself in the world
|
||
(if it is capable, if it can). Mimicry is a very bad concept, since it relies on
|
||
binary logic to describe phenomena of an entirely different nature. The
|
||
crocodile does not reproduce a tree trunk, any more than the chameleon
|
||
reproduces the colors of its surroundings. The Pink Panther imitates noth-
|
||
ing, it reproduces nothing, it paints the world its color, pink on pink; this is
|
||
its becoming-world, carried out in such a way that it becomes impercepti-
|
||
ble itself, asignifying, makes its rupture, its own line of flight, follows its
|
||
"aparallel evolution" through to the end. The wisdom of the plants: even
|
||
when they have roots, there is always an outside where they form a rhizome
|
||
with something else—with the wind, an animal, human beings (and there
|
||
is also an aspect under which animals themselves form rhizomes, as do
|
||
people, etc.). "Drunkenness as a triumphant irruption of the plant in us."
|
||
Always follow the rhizome by rupture; lengthen, prolong, and relay the line
|
||
of flight; make it vary, until you have produced the most abstract and tortu-
|
||
ous of lines of n dimensions and broken directions. Conjugate
|
||
deterritorialized flows. Follow the plants: you start by delimiting a first line
|
||
consisting of circles of convergence around successive singularities; then
|
||
you see whether inside that line new circles of convergence establish them-
|
||
selves, with new points located outside the limits and in other directions.
|
||
Write, form a rhizome, increase your territory by deterritorialization,
|
||
extend the line of flight to the point where it becomes an abstract machine
|
||
covering the entire plane of consistency. "Go first to your old plant and
|
||
watch carefully the watercourse made by the rain. By now the rain must
|
||
have carried the seeds far away. Watch the crevices made by the runoff, and
|
||
from them determine the direction of the flow. Then find the plant that is
|
||
growing at the farthest point from your plant. All the devil's weed plants
|
||
that are growing in between are yours. Later... you can extend the size of
|
||
your territory by following the watercourse from each point along the
|
||
way."7 Music has always sent out lines of flight, like so many "transforma-
|
||
tional multiplicities," even overturning the very codes that structure or
|
||
12 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
arborify it; that is why musical form, right down to its ruptures and prolif-
|
||
erations, is comparable to a weed, a rhizome.8
|
||
5 and 6. Principle of cartography and decalcomania: a rhizome is not
|
||
amenable to any structural or generative model. It is a stranger to any idea
|
||
of genetic axis or deep structure. A genetic axis is like an objective pivotal
|
||
unity upon which successive stages are organized; a deep structure is more
|
||
like a base sequence that can be broken down into immediate constituents,
|
||
while the unity of the product passes into another, transformational and
|
||
subjective, dimension. This does not constitute a departure from the repre-
|
||
sentative model of the tree, or root—pivotal taproot or fascicles (for exam-
|
||
ple, Chomsky's "tree" is associated with a base sequence and represents the
|
||
process of its own generation in terms of binary logic). A variation on the
|
||
oldest form of thought. It is our view that genetic axis and profound struc-
|
||
ture are above all infinitely reproducible principles of tracing. All of tree
|
||
logic is a logic of tracing and reproduction. In linguistics as in psychoanaly-
|
||
sis, its object is an unconscious that is itself representative, crystallized
|
||
into codified complexes, laid out along a genetic axis and distributed
|
||
within a syntagmatic structure. Its goal is to describe a de facto state, to
|
||
maintain balance in intersubjective relations, or to explore an unconscious
|
||
that is already there from the start, lurking in the dark recesses of memory
|
||
and language. It consists of tracing, on the basis of an overcoding structure
|
||
or supporting axis, something that comes ready-made. The tree articulates
|
||
and hierarchizes tracings; tracings are like the leaves of a tree.
|
||
The rhizome is altogether different, a map and not a tracing. Make a
|
||
map, not a tracing. The orchid does not reproduce the tracing of the wasp;
|
||
it forms a map with the wasp, in a rhizome. What distinguishes the map
|
||
from the tracing is that it is entirely oriented toward an experimentation in
|
||
contact with the real. The map does not reproduce an unconscious closed
|
||
in upon itself; it constructs the unconscious. It fosters connections between
|
||
fields, the removal of blockages on bodies without organs, the maximum
|
||
opening of bodies without organs onto a plane of consistency. It is itself a
|
||
part of the rhizome. The map is open and connectable in all of its dimen-
|
||
sions; it is detachable, reversible, susceptible to constant modification. It
|
||
can be torn, reversed, adapted to any kind of mounting, reworked by an
|
||
individual, group, or social formation. It can be drawn on a wall, conceived
|
||
of as a work of art, constructed as a political action or as a meditation. Per-
|
||
haps one of the most important characteristics of the rhizome is that it
|
||
always has multiple entryways; in this sense, the burrow is an animal rhi-
|
||
zome, and sometimes maintains a clear distinction between the line of
|
||
flight as passageway and storage or living strata (cf. the muskrat). A map
|
||
has multiple entryways, as opposed to the tracing, which always comes
|
||
back "to the same." The map has to do with performance, whereas the trac-
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 13
|
||
|
||
ing always involves an alleged "competence." Unlike psychoanalysis, psy-
|
||
choanalytic competence (which confines every desire and statement to a
|
||
genetic axis or overcoding structure, and makes infinite, monotonous trac-
|
||
ings of the stages on that axis or the constituents of that structure),
|
||
schizoanalysis rejects any idea of pretraced destiny, whatever name is
|
||
given to it—divine, anagogic, historical, economic, structural, hereditary,
|
||
or syntagmatic. (It is obvious that Melanie Klein has no understanding of
|
||
the cartography of one of her child patients, Little Richard, and is content
|
||
to make ready-made tracings—Oedipus, the good daddy and the bad
|
||
daddy, the bad mommy and the good mommy—while the child makes a
|
||
desperate attempt to carry out a performance that the psychoanalyst
|
||
totally misconstrues.)9 Drives and part-objects are neither stages on a
|
||
genetic axis nor positions in a deep structure; they are political options for
|
||
problems, they are entryways and exits, impasses the child lives out politi-
|
||
cally, in other words, with all the force of his or her desire.
|
||
Have we not, however, reverted to a simple dualism by contrasting maps
|
||
to tracings, as good and bad sides? Is it not of the essence of the map to be
|
||
traceable? Is it not of the essence of the rhizome to intersect roots and
|
||
sometimes merge with them? Does not a map contain phenomena of
|
||
redundancy that are already like tracings of its own? Does not a multipli-
|
||
city have strata upon which unifications and totalizations, massifications,
|
||
mimetic mechanisms, signifying power takeovers, and subjective attribu-
|
||
tions take root? Do not even lines of flight, due to their eventual diver-
|
||
gence, reproduce the very formations their function it was to dismantle or
|
||
outflank? But the opposite is also true. It is a question of method: the trac-
|
||
ing should always be put back on the map. This operation and the previous
|
||
one are not at all symmetrical. For it is inaccurate to say that a tracing
|
||
reproduces the map. It is instead like a photograph or X ray that begins by
|
||
selecting or isolating, by artificial means such as colorations or other
|
||
restrictive procedures, what it intends to reproduce. The imitator always
|
||
creates the model, and attracts it. The tracing has already translated the
|
||
map into an image; it has already transformed the rhizome into roots and
|
||
radicles. It has organized, stabilized, neutralized the multiplicities accord-
|
||
ing to the axes of signifiance and subjectification belonging to it. It has gen-
|
||
erated, structuralized the rhizome, and when it thinks it is reproducing
|
||
something else it is in fact only reproducing itself. That is why the tracing is
|
||
so dangerous. It injects redundancies and propagates them. What the trac-
|
||
ing reproduces of the map or rhizome are only the impasses, blockages,
|
||
incipient taproots, or points of structuration. Take a look at psychoanalysis
|
||
and linguistics: all the former has ever made are tracings or photos of the
|
||
unconscious, and the latter of language, with all the betrayals that implies
|
||
(it's not surprising that psychoanalysis tied its fate to that of linguistics).
|
||
14 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
Look at what happened to Little Hans already, an example of child psycho-
|
||
analysis at its purest: they kept on BREAKING HIS RHIZOME and BLOTCHING
|
||
HIS MAP, setting it straight for him, blocking his every way out, until he
|
||
began to desire his own shame and guilt, until they had rooted shame and
|
||
guilt in him, PHOBIA (they barred him from the rhizome of the building,
|
||
then from the rhizome of the street, they rooted him in his parents' bed,
|
||
they radicled him to his own body, they fixated him on Professor Freud).
|
||
Freud explicitly takes Little Hans's cartography into account, but always
|
||
and only in order to project it back onto the family photo. And look what
|
||
Melanie Klein did to Little Richard's geopolitical maps: she developed
|
||
photos from them, made tracings of them. Strike the pose or follow the
|
||
axis, genetic stage or structural destiny—one way or the other, your rhi-
|
||
zome will be broken. You will be allowed to live and speak, but only after
|
||
every outlet has been obstructed. Once a rhizome has been obstructed,
|
||
arborified, it's all over, no desire stirs; for it is always by rhizome that desire
|
||
moves and produces. Whenever desire climbs a tree, internal repercus-
|
||
sions trip it up and it falls to its death; the rhizome, on the other hand, acts
|
||
on desire by external, productive outgrowths.
|
||
That is why it is so important to try the other, reverse but nonsym-
|
||
metrical, operation. Plug the tracings back into the map, connect the roots
|
||
or trees back up with a rhizome. In the case of Little Hans, studying the
|
||
unconscious would be to show how he tries to build a rhizome, with the
|
||
family house but also with the line of flight of the building, the street, etc.;
|
||
how these lines are blocked, how the child is made to take root in the family,
|
||
be photographed under the father, be traced onto the mother's bed; then
|
||
how Professor Freud's intervention assures a power takeover by the
|
||
signifier, a subjectification of affects; how the only escape route left to the
|
||
child is a becoming-animal perceived as shameful and guilty (the
|
||
becoming-horse of Little Hans, a truly political option). But these impasses
|
||
must always be resituated on the map, thereby opening them up to possible
|
||
lines of flight. The same applies to the group map: show at what point in the
|
||
rhizome there form phenomena of massification, bureaucracy, leadership,
|
||
fascization, etc., which lines nevertheless survive, if only underground,
|
||
continuing to make rhizome in the shadows. Deligny's method: map the
|
||
gestures and movements of an autistic child, combine several maps for the
|
||
same child, for several different children.10 If it is true that it is of the
|
||
essence of the map or rhizome to have multiple entryways, then it is plausi-
|
||
ble that one could even enter them through tracings or the root-tree, assum-
|
||
ing the necessary precautions are taken (once again, one must avoid any
|
||
Manichaean dualism). For example, one will often be forced to take
|
||
dead ends, to work with signifying powers and subjective affections, to find
|
||
a foothold in formations that are Oedipal or paranoid or even worse,
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 15
|
||
|
||
rigidified territorialities that open the way for other transformational
|
||
operations. It is even possible for psychoanalysis to serve as a foothold, in
|
||
spite of itself. In other cases, on the contrary, one will bolster oneself
|
||
directly on a line of flight enabling one to blow apart strata, cut roots, and
|
||
make new connections. Thus, there are very diverse map-tracing, rhizome-
|
||
root assemblages, with variable coefficients of deterritorialization. There
|
||
exist tree or root structures in rhizomes; conversely, a tree branch or root
|
||
division may begin to burgeon into a rhizome. The coordinates are deter-
|
||
mined not by theoretical analyses implying universals but by a pragmatics
|
||
composing multiplicities or aggregates of intensities. A new rhizome may
|
||
form in the heart of a tree, the hollow of a root, the crook of a branch. Or
|
||
else it is a microscopic element of the root-tree, a radicle, that gets rhizome
|
||
production going. Accounting and bureaucracy proceed by tracings: they
|
||
can begin to burgeon nonetheless, throwing out rhizome stems, as in a
|
||
Kafka novel. An intensive trait starts working for itself, a hallucinatory
|
||
perception, synesthesia, perverse mutation, or play of images shakes loose,
|
||
challenging the hegemony of the signifier. In the case of the child, gestural,
|
||
mimetic, ludic, and other semiotic systems regain their freedom and extri-
|
||
cate themselves from the "tracing," that is, from the dominant competence
|
||
of the teacher's language—a microscopic event upsets the local balance of
|
||
power. Similarly, generative trees constructed according to Chomsky's
|
||
syntagmatic model can open up in all directions, and in turn form a rhi-
|
||
zome.11 To be rhizomorphous is to produce stems and filaments that seem
|
||
to be roots, or better yet connect with them by penetrating the trunk, but
|
||
put them to strange new uses. We're tired of trees. We should stop believing
|
||
in trees, roots, and radicles. They've made us suffer too much. All of
|
||
arborescent culture is founded on them, from biology to linguistics. Noth-
|
||
ing is beautiful or loving or political aside from underground stems and
|
||
aerial roots, adventitious growths and rhizomes. Amsterdam, a city
|
||
entirely without roots, a rhizome-city with its stem-canals, where utility
|
||
connects with the greatest folly in relation to a commercial war machine.
|
||
Thought is not arborescent, and the brain is not a rooted or ramified
|
||
matter. What are wrongly called "dendrites" do not assure the connection
|
||
of neurons in a continuous fabric. The discontinuity between cells, the role
|
||
of the axons, the functioning of the synapses, the existence of synaptic
|
||
microfissures, the leap each message makes across these fissures, make the
|
||
brain a multiplicity immersed in its plane of consistency or neuroglia, a
|
||
whole uncertain, probabilistic system ("the uncertain nervous system").
|
||
Many people have a tree growing in their heads, but the brain itself is much
|
||
more a grass than a tree. "The axon and the dendrite twist around each
|
||
other like bindweed around brambles, with synapses at each of the
|
||
thorns."12 The same goes for memory. Neurologists and psychophysiolo-
|
||
16 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
gists distinguish between long-term memory and short-term memory (on
|
||
the order of a minute). The difference between them is not simply quantita-
|
||
tive: short-term memory is of the rhizome or diagram type, and long-term
|
||
memory is arborescent and centralized (imprint, engram, tracing, or pho-
|
||
tograph). Short-term memory is in no way subject to a law of contiguity or
|
||
immediacy to its object; it can act at a distance, come or return a long time
|
||
after, but always under conditions of discontinuity, rupture, and multipli-
|
||
city. Furthermore, the difference between the two kinds of memory is not
|
||
that of two temporal modes of apprehending the same thing; they do not
|
||
grasp the same thing, memory, or idea. The splendor of the short-term
|
||
Idea: one writes using short-term memory, and thus short-term ideas, even
|
||
if one reads or rereads using long-term memory of long-term concepts.
|
||
Short-term memory includes forgetting as a process; it merges not with the
|
||
instant but instead with the nervous, temporal, and collective rhizome.
|
||
Long-term memory (family, race, society, or civilization) traces and trans-
|
||
lates, but what it translates continues to act in it, from a distance, offbeat,
|
||
in an "untimely" way, not instantaneously.
|
||
The tree and root inspire a sad image of thought that is forever imitating
|
||
the multiple on the basis of a centered or segmented higher unity. If we con-
|
||
sider the set, branches-roots, the trunk plays the role of opposed segment
|
||
for one of the subsets running from bottom to top: this kind of segment is a
|
||
"link dipole," in contrast to the "unit dipoles" formed by spokes radiating
|
||
from a single center.13 Even if the links themselves proliferate, as in the
|
||
radicle system, one can never get beyond the One-Two, and fake multiplici-
|
||
ties. Regenerations, reproductions, returns, hydras, and medusas do not
|
||
get us any further. Arborescent systems are hierarchical systems with cen-
|
||
ters of signifiance and subjectification, central automata like organized
|
||
memories. In the corresponding models, an element only receives infor-
|
||
mation from a higher unit, and only receives a subjective affection along
|
||
preestablished paths. This is evident in current problems in information
|
||
science and computer science, which still cling to the oldest modes of
|
||
thought in that they grant all power to a memory or central organ. Pierre
|
||
Rosenstiehl and Jean Petitot, in a fine article denouncing "the imagery of
|
||
command trees" (centered systems or hierarchical structures), note that
|
||
"accepting the primacy of hierarchical structures amounts to giving
|
||
arborescent structures privileged status The arborescent form admits
|
||
of topological explanation.... In a hierarchical system, an individual has
|
||
only one active neighbor, his or her hierarchical superior.... The channels
|
||
of transmission are preestablished: the arborescent system preexists the
|
||
individual, who is integrated into it at an allotted place" (signifiance and
|
||
subjectification). The authors point out that even when one thinks one has
|
||
reached a multiplicity, it may be a false one—of what we call the radicle
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 17
|
||
|
||
type—because its ostensibly nonhierarchical presentation or statement in
|
||
fact only admits of a totally hierarchical solution. An example is the
|
||
famous friendship theorem: "If any two given individuals in a society have
|
||
precisely one mutual friend, then there exists an individual who is the
|
||
friend of all the others." (Rosenstiehl and Petitot ask who that mutual
|
||
friend is. Who is "the universal friend in this society of couples: the master,
|
||
the confessor, the doctor? These ideas are curiously far removed from the
|
||
initial axioms." Who is this friend of humankind? Is it thep/zz/osopher as
|
||
he appears in classical thought, even if he is an aborted unity that makes
|
||
itself felt only through its absence or subjectivity, saying all the while, I
|
||
know nothing, I am nothing?) Thus the authors speak of dictatorship theo-
|
||
rems. Such is indeed the principle of roots-trees, or their outcome: the
|
||
radicle solution, the structure of Power.14
|
||
To these centered systems, the authors contrast acentered systems,
|
||
finite networks of automata in which communication runs from any neigh-
|
||
bor to any other, the stems or channels do not preexist, and all individuals
|
||
are interchangeable, defined only by their state at a given moment—such
|
||
that the local operations are coordinated and the final, global result syn-
|
||
chronized without a central agency. Transduction of intensive states
|
||
replaces topology, and "the graph regulating the circulation of information
|
||
is in a way the opposite of the hierarchical graph.. . . There is no reason for
|
||
the graph to be a tree" (we have been calling this kind of graph a map). The
|
||
problem of the war machine, or the firing squad: is a general necessary for n
|
||
individuals to manage to fire in unison? The solution without a General is
|
||
to be found in an acentered multiplicity possessing a finite number of
|
||
states with signals to indicate corresponding speeds, from a war rhizome or
|
||
guerrilla logic point of view, without any tracing, without any copying of a
|
||
central order. The authors even demonstrate that this kind of machinic
|
||
multiplicity, assemblage, or society rejects any centralizing or unifying
|
||
automaton as an "asocial intrusion."15 Under these conditions, n is in fact
|
||
always n - 1. Rosenstiehl and Petitot emphasize that the opposition,
|
||
centered-acentered, is valid less as a designation for things than as a mode
|
||
of calculation applied to things. Trees may correspond to the rhizome, or
|
||
they may burgeon into a rhizome. It is true that the same thing is generally
|
||
susceptible to both modes of calculation or both types of regulation, but
|
||
not without undergoing a change in state. Take psychoanalysis as an exam-
|
||
ple again: it subjects the unconscious to arborescent structures, hierarchi-
|
||
cal graphs, recapitulatory memories, central organs, the phallus, the
|
||
phallus-tree—not only in its theory but also in its practice of calculation
|
||
and treatment. Psychoanalysis cannot change its method in this regard: it
|
||
bases its own dictatorial power upon a dictatorial conception of the uncon-
|
||
scious. Psychoanalysis's margin of maneuverability is therefore very
|
||
18 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
limited. In both psychoanalysis and its object, there is always a general,
|
||
always a leader (General Freud). Schizoanalysis, on the other hand, treats
|
||
the unconscious as an acentered system, in other words, as a machinic net-
|
||
work of finite automata (a rhizome), and thus arrives at an entirely differ-
|
||
ent state of the unconscious. These same remarks apply to linguistics;
|
||
Rosenstiehl and Petitot are right to bring up the possibility of an
|
||
"acentered organization of a society of words." For both statements and
|
||
desires, the issue is never to reduce the unconscious or to interpret it or to
|
||
make it signify according to a tree model. The issue is to produce the uncon-
|
||
scious, and with it new statements, different desires: the rhizome is pre-
|
||
cisely this production of the unconscious.
|
||
It is odd how the tree has dominated Western reality and all of Western
|
||
thought, from botany to biology and anatomy, but also gnosiology, theol-
|
||
ogy, ontology, all of philosophy . . . : the root-foundation, Grund, ratine,
|
||
fondement. The West has a special relation to the forest, and deforestation;
|
||
the fields carved from the forest are populated with seed plants produced
|
||
by cultivation based on species lineages of the arborescent type; animal
|
||
raising, carried out on fallow fields, selects lineages forming an entire ani-
|
||
mal arborescence. The East presents a different figure: a relation to the
|
||
steppe and the garden (or in some cases, the desert and the oasis), rather
|
||
than forest and field; cultivation of tubers by fragmentation of the individ-
|
||
ual; a casting aside or bracketing of animal raising, which is confined to
|
||
closed spaces or pushed out onto the steppes of the nomads. The West: agri-
|
||
culture based on a chosen lineage containing a large number of variable
|
||
individuals. The East: horticulture based on a small number of individuals
|
||
derived from a wide range of "clones." Does not the East, Oceania in par-
|
||
ticular, offer something like a rhizomatic model opposed in every respect
|
||
to the Western model of the tree? Andre Haudricourt even sees this as the
|
||
basis for the opposition between the moralities or philosophies of tran-
|
||
scendence dear to the West and the immanent ones of the East: the God
|
||
who sows and reaps, as opposed to the God who replants and unearths
|
||
(replanting of offshoots versus sowing of seeds).16 Transcendence: a specif-
|
||
ically European disease. Neither is music the same, the music of the earth is
|
||
different, as is sexuality: seed plants, even those with two sexes in the same
|
||
plant, subjugate sexuality to the reproductive model; the rhizome, on the
|
||
other hand, is a liberation of sexuality not only from reproduction but also
|
||
from genitality. Here in the West, the tree has implanted itself in our bod-
|
||
ies, rigidifying and stratifying even the sexes. We have lost the rhizome, or
|
||
the grass. Henry Miller: "China is the weed in the human cabbage patch.
|
||
. . . The weed is the Nemesis of human endeavor.... Of all the imaginary
|
||
existences we attribute to plant, beast and star the weed leads the most sat-
|
||
isfactory life of all. True, the weed produces no lilies, no battleships, no Ser-
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 19
|
||
|
||
mons on the Mount.... Eventually the weed gets the upper hand. Eventu-
|
||
ally things fall back into a state of China. This condition is usually referred
|
||
to by historians as the Dark Age. Grass is the only way out.... The weed
|
||
exists only to fill the waste spaces left by cultivated areas. It grows between,
|
||
among other things. The lily is beautiful, the cabbage is provender, the
|
||
poppy is maddening—but the weed is rank growth . . . : it points a
|
||
moral."17 Which China is Miller talking about? The old China, the new, an
|
||
imaginary one, or yet another located on a shifting map?
|
||
America is a special case. Of course it is not immune from domination
|
||
by trees or the search for roots. This is evident even in the literature, in the
|
||
quest for a national identity and even for a European ancestry or genealogy
|
||
(Kerouac going off in search of his ancestors). Nevertheless, everything
|
||
important that has happened or is happening takes the route of the Ameri-
|
||
can rhizome: the beatniks, the underground, bands and gangs, successive
|
||
lateral offshoots in immediate connection with an outside. American
|
||
books are different from European books, even when the American sets off
|
||
in pursuit of trees. The conception of the book is different. Leaves of Grass.
|
||
And directions in America are different: the search for arborescence and
|
||
the return to the Old World occur in the East. But there is the rhizomatic
|
||
West, with its Indians without ancestry, its ever-receding limit, its shifting
|
||
and displaced frontiers. There is a whole American "map" in the West,
|
||
where even the trees form rhizomes. America reversed the directions: it put
|
||
its Orient in the West, as if it were precisely in America that the earth came
|
||
full circle; its West is the edge of the East.18 (India is not the intermediary
|
||
between the Occident and the Orient, as Haudricourt believed: America is
|
||
the pivot point and mechanism of reversal.) The American singer Patti
|
||
Smith sings the bible of the American dentist: Don't go for the root, follow
|
||
the canal...
|
||
Are there not also two kinds of bureaucracy, or even three (or still more)?
|
||
Western bureaucracy: its agrarian, cadastral origins; roots and fields; trees
|
||
and their role as frontiers; the great census of William the Conqueror; feu-
|
||
dalism; the policies of the kings of France; making property the basis of the
|
||
State; negotiating land through warfare, litigation, and marriages. The
|
||
kings of France chose the lily because it is a plant with deep roots that clings
|
||
to slopes. Is bureaucracy the same in the Orient? Of course it is all too easy
|
||
to depict an Orient of rhizomes and immanence; yet it is true that in the
|
||
Orient the State does not act following a schema of arborescence corre-
|
||
sponding to preestablished, arborified, and rooted classes; its bureaucracy
|
||
is one of channels, for example, the much-discussed case of hydraulic
|
||
power with "weak property," in which the State engenders channeled and
|
||
channelizing classes (cf. the aspects of Wittfogel's work that have not been
|
||
refuted).19 The despot acts as a river, not as a fountainhead, which is still a
|
||
20 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
point, a tree-point or root; he flows with the current rather than sitting
|
||
under a tree; Buddha's tree itself becomes a rhizome; Mao's river and
|
||
Louis's tree. Has not America acted as an intermediary here as well? For it
|
||
proceeds both by internal exterminations and liquidations (not only the
|
||
Indians but also the farmers, etc.), and by successive waves of immigration
|
||
from the outside. The flow of capital produces an immense channel, a
|
||
quantification of power with immediate "quanta," where each person
|
||
profits from the passage of the money flow in his or her own way (hence the
|
||
reality-myth of the poor man who strikes it rich and then falls into poverty
|
||
again): in America everything comes together, tree and channel, root and
|
||
rhizome. There is no universal capitalism, there is no capitalism in itself;
|
||
capitalism is at the crossroads of all kinds of formations, it is neocapitalism
|
||
by nature. It invents its eastern face and western face, and reshapes them
|
||
both—all for the worst.
|
||
At the same time, we are on the wrong track with all these geographical
|
||
distributions. An impasse. So much the better. If it is a question of showing
|
||
that rhizomes also have their own, even more rigid, despotism and hierar-
|
||
chy, then fine and good: for there is no dualism, no ontological dualism
|
||
between here and there, no axiological dualism between good and bad, no
|
||
blend or American synthesis. There are knots of arborescence in rhizomes,
|
||
and rhizomatic offshoots in roots. Moreover, there are despotic formations
|
||
of immanence and channelization specific to rhizomes, just as there are
|
||
anarchic deformations in the transcendent system of trees, aerial roots,
|
||
and subterranean stems. The important point is that the root-tree and
|
||
canal-rhizome are not two opposed models: the first operates as a tran-
|
||
scendent model and tracing, even if it engenders its own escapes; the sec-
|
||
ond operates as an immanent process that overturns the model and
|
||
outlines a map, even if it constitutes its own hierarchies, even if it gives rise
|
||
to a despotic channel. It is not a question of this or that place on earth, or of
|
||
a given moment in history, still less of this or that category of thought. It is a
|
||
question of a model that is perpetually in construction or collapsing, and of
|
||
a process that is perpetually prolonging itself, breaking off and starting up
|
||
again. No, this is not a new or different dualism. The problem of writing: in
|
||
order to designate something exactly, anexact expressions are utterly
|
||
unavoidable. Not at all because it is a necessary step, or because one can
|
||
only advance by approximations: anexactitude is in no way an approxima-
|
||
tion; on the contrary, it is the exact passage of that which is under way. We
|
||
invoke one dualism only in order to challenge another. We employ a dual-
|
||
ism of models only in order to arrive at a process that challenges all models.
|
||
Each time, mental correctives are necessary to undo the dualisms we had
|
||
no wish to construct but through which we pass. Arrive at the magic
|
||
formula we all seek—PLURALISM = MONISM—via all the dualisms that are
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 21
|
||
|
||
the enemy, an entirely necessary enemy, the furniture we are forever
|
||
rearranging.
|
||
Let us summarize the principal characteristics of a rhizome: unlike trees
|
||
or their roots, the rhizome connects any point to any other point, and its
|
||
traits are not necessarily linked to traits of the same nature; it brings into
|
||
play very different regimes of signs, and even nonsign states. The rhizome
|
||
is reducible neither to the One nor the multiple. It is not the One that
|
||
becomes Two or even directly three, four, five, etc. It is not a multiple
|
||
derived from the One, or to which One is added (n + 1). It is composed not
|
||
of units but of dimensions, or rather directions in motion. It has neither
|
||
beginning nor end, but always a middle (milieu) from which it grows and
|
||
which it overspills. It constitutes linear multiplicities with n dimensions
|
||
having neither subject nor object, which can be laid out on a plane of con-
|
||
sistency, and from which the One is always subtracted (n - 1). When a mul-
|
||
tiplicity of this kind changes dimension, it necessarily changes in nature as
|
||
well, undergoes a metamorphosis. Unlike a structure, which is defined by a
|
||
set of points and positions, with binary relations between the points and
|
||
biunivocal relationships between the positions, the rhizome is made only
|
||
of lines: lines of segmentarity and stratification as its dimensions, and the
|
||
line of flight or deterritorialization as the maximum dimension after
|
||
which the multiplicity undergoes metamorphosis, changes in nature.
|
||
These lines, or lineaments, should not be confused with lineages of the
|
||
arborescent type, which are merely localizable linkages between points and
|
||
positions. Unlike the tree, the rhizome is not the object of reproduction:
|
||
neither external reproduction as image-tree nor internal reproduction as
|
||
tree-structure. The rhizome is an antigenealogy. It is a short-term memory,
|
||
or antimemory. The rhizome operates by variation, expansion, conquest,
|
||
capture, offshoots. Unlike the graphic arts, drawing, or photography,
|
||
unlike tracings, the rhizome pertains to a map that must be produced, con-
|
||
structed, a map that is always detachable, connectable, reversible,
|
||
modifiable, and has multiple entryways and exits and its own lines of
|
||
flight. It is tracings that must be put on the map, not the opposite. In con-
|
||
trast to centered (even polycentric) systems with hierarchical modes of
|
||
communication and preestablished paths, the rhizome is an acentered,
|
||
nonhierarchical, nonsignifying system without a General and without an
|
||
organizing memory or central automaton, defined solely by a circulation
|
||
of states. What is at question in the rhizome is a relation to sexuality—but
|
||
also to the animal, the vegetal, the world, politics, the book, things natural
|
||
and artificial—that is totally different from the arborescent relation: all
|
||
manner of "becomings."
|
||
A plateau is always in the middle, not at the beginning or the end. A rhi-
|
||
zome is made of plateaus. Gregory Bateson uses the word "plateau" to
|
||
22 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
designate something very special: a continuous, self-vibrating region of
|
||
intensities whose development avoids any orientation toward a culmina-
|
||
tion point or external end. Bateson cites Balinese culture as an example:
|
||
mother-child sexual games, and even quarrels among men, undergo this
|
||
bizarre intensive stabilization. "Some sort of continuing plateau of inten-
|
||
sity is substituted for [sexual] climax," war, or a culmination point. It is a
|
||
regrettable characteristic of the Western mind to relate expressions and
|
||
actions to exterior or transcendent ends, instead of evaluating them on a
|
||
plane of consistency on the basis of their intrinsic value.20 For example, a
|
||
book composed of chapters has culmination and termination points. What
|
||
takes place in a book composed instead of plateaus that communicate with
|
||
one another across microfissures, as in a brain? We call a "plateau" any
|
||
multiplicity connected to other multiplicities by superficial underground
|
||
stems in such a way as to form or extend a rhizome. We are writing this
|
||
book as a rhizome. It is composed of plateaus. We have given it a circular
|
||
form, but only for laughs. Each morning we would wake up, and each of us
|
||
would ask himself what plateau he was going to tackle, writing five lines
|
||
here, ten there. We had hallucinatory experiences, we watched lines leave
|
||
one plateau and proceed to another like columns of tiny ants. We made cir-
|
||
cles of convergence. Each plateau can be read starting anywhere and can be
|
||
related to any other plateau. To attain the multiple, one must have a
|
||
method that effectively constructs it; no typographical cleverness, no lexi-
|
||
cal agility, no blending or creation of words, no syntactical boldness, can
|
||
substitute for it. In fact, these are more often than not merely mimetic pro-
|
||
cedures used to disseminate or disperse a unity that is retained in a differ-
|
||
ent dimension for an image-book. Technonarcissism. Typographical,
|
||
lexical, or syntactic creations are necessary only when they no longer
|
||
belong to the form of expression of a hidden unity, becoming themselves
|
||
dimensions of the multiplicity under consideration; we only know of rare
|
||
successes in this.21 We ourselves were unable to do it. We just used words
|
||
that in turn function for us as plateaus. RHIZOMATICS = SCHIZOANALYSIS =
|
||
STRATOANALYSIS = PRAGMATICS = MICROPOLITICS. These words are con-
|
||
cepts, but concepts are lines, which is to say, number systems attached to a
|
||
particular dimension of the multiplicities (strata, molecular chains, lines
|
||
of flight or rupture, circles of convergence, etc.). Nowhere do we claim for
|
||
our concepts the title of a science. We are no more familiar with scientif-
|
||
icity than we are with ideology; all we know are assemblages. And the only
|
||
assemblages are machinic assemblages of desire and collective assem-
|
||
blages of enunciation. No signifiance, no subjectification: writing to the
|
||
«th power (all individuated enunciation remains trapped within the domi-
|
||
nant significations, all signifying desire is associated with dominated sub-
|
||
jects). An assemblage, in its multiplicity, necessarily acts on semiotic flows,
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 23
|
||
|
||
material flows, and social flows simultaneously (independently of any
|
||
recapitulation that may be made of it in a scientific or theoretical corpus).
|
||
There is no longer a tripartite division between a field of reality (the world)
|
||
and a field of representation (the book) and a field of subjectivity (the
|
||
author). Rather, an assemblage establishes connections between certain
|
||
multiplicities drawn from each of these orders, so that a book has no sequel
|
||
nor the world as its object nor one or several authors as its subject. In short,
|
||
we think that one cannot write sufficiently in the name of an outside. The
|
||
outside has no image, no signification, no subjectivity. The book as assem-
|
||
blage with the outside, against the book as image of the world. A rhizome-
|
||
book, not a dichotomous, pivotal, or fascicular book. Never send down
|
||
roots, or plant them, however difficult it may be to avoid reverting to the
|
||
old procedures. "Those things which occur to me, occur to me not from the
|
||
root up but rather only from somewhere about their middle. Let someone
|
||
then attempt to seize them, let someone attempt to seize a blade of grass
|
||
and hold fast to it when it begins to grow only from the middle."22 Why is
|
||
this so difficult? The question is directly one of perceptual semiotics. It's
|
||
not easy to see things in the middle, rather than looking down on them from
|
||
above or up at them from below, or from left to right or right to left: try it,
|
||
you'll see that everything changes. It's not easy to see the grass in things and
|
||
in words (similarly, Nietzsche said that an aphorism had to be "rumi-
|
||
nated"; never is a plateau separable from the cows that populate it, which
|
||
are also the clouds in the sky).
|
||
History is always written from the sedentary point of view and in the
|
||
name of a unitary State apparatus, at least a possible one, even when the
|
||
topic is nomads. What is lacking is a Nomadology, the opposite of a history.
|
||
There are rare successes in this also, for example, on the subject of the
|
||
Children's Crusades: Marcel Schwob's book multiplies narratives like so
|
||
many plateaus with variable numbers of dimensions. Then there is
|
||
Andrzejewski's book, Les portes duparadis (The gates of paradise), com-
|
||
posed of a single uninterrupted sentence; a flow of children; a flow of walk-
|
||
ing with pauses, straggling, and forward rushes; the semiotic flow of the
|
||
confessions of all the children who go up to the old monk at the head of the
|
||
procession to make their declarations; a flow of desire and sexuality, each
|
||
child having left out of love and more or less directly led by the dark posthu-
|
||
mous pederastic desire of the count of Vendome; all this with circles of con-
|
||
vergence. What is important is not whether the flows are "One or
|
||
multiple"—we're past that point: there is a collective assemblage of enun-
|
||
ciation, a machinic assemblage of desire, one inside the other and both
|
||
plugged into an immense outside that is a multiplicity in any case. A more
|
||
recent example is Armand Farrachi's book on the Fourth Crusade, La dis-
|
||
location, in which the sentences space themselves out and disperse, or else
|
||
24 D INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME
|
||
|
||
jostle together and coexist, and in which the letters, the typography begin
|
||
to dance as the crusade grows more delirious.23 These are models of
|
||
nomadic and rhizomatic writing. Writing weds a war machine and lines of
|
||
flight, abandoning the strata, segmentarities, sedentarily, the State
|
||
apparatus. But why is a model still necessary? Aren't these books still
|
||
"images" of the Crusades? Don't they still retain a unity, in Schwob's case a
|
||
pivotal unity, in Farrachi's an aborted unity, and in the most beautiful
|
||
example, Les portes du paradis, the unity of the funereal count? Is there a
|
||
need for a more profound nomadism than that of the Crusades, a
|
||
nomadism of true nomads, or of those who no longer even move or imitate
|
||
anything? The nomadism of those who only assemble (agencent). How can
|
||
the book find an adequate outside with which to assemble in heterogeneity,
|
||
rather than a world to reproduce? The cultural book is necessarily a tracing:
|
||
already a tracing of itself, a tracing of the previous book by the same author,
|
||
a tracing of other books however different they may be, an endless tracing
|
||
of established concepts and words, a tracing of the world present, past, and
|
||
future. Even the anticultural book may still be burdened by too heavy a cul-
|
||
tural load: but it will use it actively, for forgetting instead of remembering,
|
||
for underdevelopment instead of progress toward development, in
|
||
nomadism rather than sedentarily, to make a map instead of a tracing.
|
||
RHIZOMATICS = POP ANALYSIS, even if the people have other things to do
|
||
besides read it, even if the blocks of academic culture or pseudoscien-
|
||
tificity in it are still too painful or ponderous. For science would go com-
|
||
pletely mad if left to its own devices. Look at mathematics: it's not a
|
||
science, it's a monster slang, it's nomadic. Even in the realm of theory,
|
||
especially in the realm of theory, any precarious and pragmatic framework
|
||
is better than tracing concepts, with their breaks and progress changing
|
||
nothing. Imperceptible rupture, not signifying break. The nomads
|
||
invented a war machine in opposition to the State apparatus. History has
|
||
never comprehended nomadism, the book has never comprehended the
|
||
outside. The State as the model for the book and for thought has a long his-
|
||
tory: logos, the philosopher-king, the transcendence of the Idea, the
|
||
interiority of the concept, the republic of minds, the court of reason, the
|
||
functionaries of thought, man as legislator and subject. The State's preten-
|
||
sion to be a world order, and to root man. The war machine's relation to an
|
||
outside is not another "model"; it is an assemblage that makes thought
|
||
itself nomadic, and the book a working part in every mobile machine, a
|
||
stem for a rhizome (Kleist and Kafka against Goethe).
|
||
Write to the nth power, the n - 1 power, write with slogans: Make rhi-
|
||
zomes, not roots, never plant! Don't sow, grow offshoots! Don't be one or
|
||
multiple, be multiplicities! Run lines, never plot a point! Speed turns the
|
||
point into a line!24 Be quick, even when standing still! Line of chance, line
|
||
INTRODUCTION: RHIZOME D 25
|
||
|
||
of hips, line of flight. Don't bring out the General in you! Don't have just
|
||
ideas, just have an idea (Godard). Have short-term ideas. Make maps, not
|
||
photos or drawings. Be the Pink Panther and your loves will be like the
|
||
wasp and the orchid, the cat and the baboon. As they say about old man
|
||
river:
|
||
He don't plant 'tatos
|
||
Don't plant cotton
|
||
Them that plants them is soon forgotten
|
||
But old man river he just keeps rollin' along
|
||
A rhizome has no beginning or end; it is always in the middle, between
|
||
things, interbeing, intermezzo. The tree is filiation, but the rhizome is alli-
|
||
ance, uniquely alliance. The tree imposes the verb "to be," but the fabric of
|
||
the rhizome is the conjunction, "and. . . and.. . and. . ." This conjunction
|
||
carries enough force to shake and uproot the verb "to be." Where are you
|
||
going? Where are you coming from? What are you heading for? These are
|
||
totally useless questions. Making a clean slate, starting or beginning again
|
||
from ground zero, seeking a beginning or a foundation—all imply a false
|
||
conception of voyage and movement (a conception that is methodical, ped-
|
||
agogical, initiatory, symbolic...). But Kleist, Lenz, and Buchner have
|
||
another way of traveling and moving: proceeding from the middle, through
|
||
the middle, coming and going rather than starting and finishing.25 Ameri-
|
||
can literature, and already English literature, manifest this rhizomatic
|
||
direction to an even greater extent; they know how to move between things,
|
||
establish a logic of the AND, overthrow ontology, do away with foundations,
|
||
nullify endings and beginnings. They know how to practice pragmatics.
|
||
The middle is by no means an average; on the contrary, it is where things
|
||
pick up speed. Between things does not designate a localizable relation
|
||
going from one thing to the other and back again, but a perpendicular
|
||
direction, a transversal movement that sweeps one and the other away, a
|
||
stream without beginning or end that undermines its banks and picks up
|
||
speed in the middle.
|
||
2. 1914: One or Several Wolves?
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Field of Tracks, or Wolf Line
|
||
|
||
That day, the Wolf-Man rose from the couch particularly tired. He knew
|
||
that Freud had a genius for brushing up against the truth and passing it by,
|
||
then filling the void with associations. He knew that Freud knew nothing
|
||
about wolves, or anuses for that matter. The only thing Freud understood
|
||
was what a dog is, and a dog's tail. It wasn't enough. It wouldn't be enough.
|
||
The Wolf-Man knew that Freud would soon declare him cured, but that it
|
||
was not at all the case and his treatment would continue for all eternity
|
||
under Brunswick, Lacan, Leclaire. Finally, he knew that he was in the pro-
|
||
cess of acquiring a veritable proper name, the Wolf-Man, a name more
|
||
properly his than his own, since it attained the highest degree of singularity
|
||
26
|
||
1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES? D 27
|
||
|
||
in the instantaneous apprehension of a generic multiplicity: wolves. He
|
||
knew that this new and true proper name would be disfigured and mis-
|
||
spelled, retranscribed as a patronymic.
|
||
Freud, for his part, would go on to write some extraordinary pages.
|
||
Entirely practical pages: his article of 1915 on "The Unconscious," which
|
||
deals with the difference between neurosis and psychosis. Freud says that
|
||
hysterics or obsessives are people capable of making a global comparison
|
||
between a sock and a vagina, a scar and castration, etc. Doubtless, it is at
|
||
one and the same time that they apprehend the object globally and perceive
|
||
it as lost. Yet it would never occur to a neurotic to grasp the skin erotically
|
||
as a multiplicity of pores, little spots, little scars or black holes, or to grasp
|
||
the sock erotically as a multiplicity of stitches. The psychotic can: "we
|
||
should expect the multiplicity of these little cavities to prevent him from
|
||
using them as substitutes for the female genital."1 Comparing a sock to a
|
||
vagina is OK, it's done all the time, but you'd have to be insane to compare
|
||
a pure aggregate of stitches to a field of vaginas: that's what Freud says.
|
||
This represents an important clinical discovery: a whole difference in style
|
||
between neurosis and psychosis. For example, Salvador Dali, in attempt-
|
||
ing to reproduce his delusions, may go on at length about THE rhinoceros
|
||
horn; he has not for all of that left neurotic discourse behind. But when he
|
||
starts comparing goosebumps to a field of tiny rhinoceros horns, we get the
|
||
feeling that the atmosphere has changed and that we are now in the pres-
|
||
ence of madness. Is it still a question of a comparison at all? It is, rather, a
|
||
pure multiplicity that changes elements, or becomes. On the micrological
|
||
level, the little bumps "become" horns, and the horns, little penises.
|
||
No sooner does Freud discover the greatest art of the unconscious, this
|
||
art of molecular multiplicities, than we find him tirelessly at work bringing
|
||
back molar unities, reverting to his familiar themes of the father, the penis,
|
||
the vagina, Castration with a capital C... (On the verge of discovering a
|
||
rhizome, Freud always returns to mere roots.) The reductive procedure of
|
||
the 1915 article is quite interesting: he says that the comparisons and iden-
|
||
tifications of the neurotic are guided by representations of things, whereas
|
||
all the psychotic has left are representations of words (for example, the
|
||
word "hole"). "What has dictated the substitution is not the resemblance
|
||
between the things denoted but the sameness of the words used to express
|
||
them" (p. 201). Thus, when there is no unity in the thing, there is at least
|
||
unity and identity in the word. It will be noted that names are taken in their
|
||
extensive usage, in other words, function as common nouns ensuring the
|
||
unification of an aggregate they subsume. The proper name can be nothing
|
||
more than an extreme case of the common noun, containing its already
|
||
domesticated multiplicity within itself and linking it to a being or object
|
||
posited as unique. This jeopardizes, on the side of words and things both,
|
||
28 D 1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES?
|
||
|
||
the relation of the proper name as an intensity to the multiplicity it instan-
|
||
taneously apprehends. For Freud, when the thing splinters and loses its
|
||
identity, the word is still there to restore that identity or invent a new one.
|
||
Freud counted on the word to reestablish a unity no longer found in things.
|
||
Are we not witnessing the first stirrings of a subsequent adventure, that of
|
||
the Signifier, the devious despotic agency that substitutes itself for
|
||
asignifying proper names and replaces multiplicities with the dismal unity
|
||
of an object declared lost?
|
||
We're not far from wolves. For the Wolf-Man, in his second so-called
|
||
psychotic episode, kept constant watch over the variations or changing
|
||
path of the little holes or scars on the skin of his nose. During the first epi-
|
||
sode, which Freud declares neurotic, he recounted a dream he had about
|
||
six or seven wolves in a tree, and drew five. Who is ignorant of the fact that
|
||
wolves travel in packs? Only Freud. Every child knows it. Not Freud. With
|
||
false scruples he asks, How are we to explain the fact that there are five, six,
|
||
or seven wolves in this dream? He has decided that this is neurosis, so he
|
||
uses the other reductive procedure: free association on the level of the rep-
|
||
resentation of things, rather than verbal subsumption on the level of the
|
||
representation of words. The result is the same, since it is always a question
|
||
of bringing back the unity or identity of the person or allegedly lost object.
|
||
The wolves will have to be purged of their multiplicity. This operation is
|
||
accomplished by associating the dream with the tale, "The Wolf and the
|
||
Seven Kid-Goats" (only six of which get eaten). We witness Freud's reduc-
|
||
tive glee; we literally see multiplicity leave the wolves to take the shape of
|
||
goats that have absolutely nothing to do with the story. Seven wolves that
|
||
are only kid-goats. Six wolves: the seventh goat (the Wolf-Man himself) is
|
||
hiding in the clock. Five wolves: he may have seen his parents make love at
|
||
five o'clock, and the roman numeral V is associated with the erotic spread-
|
||
ing of a woman's legs. Three wolves: the parents may have made love three
|
||
times. Two wolves: the first coupling the child may have seen was the two
|
||
parents moreferarum, or perhaps even two dogs. One wolf: the wolf is the
|
||
father, as we all knew from the start. Zero wolves: he lost his tail, he is not
|
||
just a castrater but also castrated. Who is Freud trying to fool? The wolves
|
||
never had a chance to get away and save their pack: it was already decided
|
||
from the very beginning that animals could serve only to represent coitus
|
||
between parents, or, conversely, be represented by coitus between parents.
|
||
Freud obviously knows nothing about the fascination exerted by wolves
|
||
and the meaning of their silent call, the call to become-wolf. Wolves watch,
|
||
intently watch, the dreaming child; it is so much more reassuring to tell
|
||
oneself that the dream produced a reversal and that it is really the child who
|
||
sees dogs or parents in the act of making love. Freud only knows the
|
||
1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES? D 29
|
||
|
||
Oedipalized wolf or dog, the castrated-castrating daddy-wolf, the dog in
|
||
the kennel, the analyst's bow-wow.
|
||
Franny is listening to a program on wolves. I say to her, Would you like to
|
||
be a wolf? She answers haughtily, How stupid, you can't be one wolf, you're
|
||
always eight or nine, six or seven. Not six or seven wolves all by yourself all
|
||
at once, but one wolf among others, with five or six others. In becoming-
|
||
wolf, the important thing is the position of the mass, and above all the posi-
|
||
tion of the subject itself in relation to the pack or wolf-multiplicity: how the
|
||
subject joins or does not join the pack, how far away it stays, how it does or
|
||
does not hold to the multiplicity. To soften the harshness of her response,
|
||
Franny recounts a dream: "There is a desert. Again, it wouldn't make any
|
||
sense to say that I am in the desert. It's a panoramic vision of the desert, and
|
||
it's not a tragic or uninhabited desert. It's only a desert because of its ocher
|
||
color and its blazing, shadowless sun. There is a teeming crowd in it, a
|
||
swarm of bees, a rumble of soccer players, or agroup of Tuareg. lam on the
|
||
edge of the crowd, at the periphery; but I belong to it, I am attached to it by
|
||
one of my extremities, a hand or foot. I know that the periphery is the only
|
||
place I can be, that I would die if I let myself be drawn into the center of the
|
||
fray, but just as certainly if I let go of the crowd. This is not an easy position
|
||
to stay in, it is even very difficult to hold, for these beings are in constant
|
||
motion and their movements are unpredictable and follow no rhythm.
|
||
They swirl, go north, then suddenly east; none of the individuals in the
|
||
crowd remains in the same place in relation to the others. So I too am in
|
||
perpetual motion; all this demands a high level of tension, but it gives me a
|
||
feeling of violent, almost vertiginous, happiness." A very good schizo
|
||
dream. To be fully a part of the crowd and at the same time completely out-
|
||
side it, removed from it: to be on the edge, to take a walk like Virginia Woolf
|
||
(never again will I say, "I am this, I am that").2
|
||
Problems of peopling in the unconscious: all that passes through the
|
||
pores of the schizo, the veins of the drug addict, swarming, teeming, fer-
|
||
ment, intensities, races and tribes. This tale of white skin prickling with
|
||
bumps and pustules, and of dwarfish black heads emerging from pores gri-
|
||
macing and abominable, needing to be shaved off every morning—is it a
|
||
tale by Jean Ray, who knew how to bring terror to phenomena of
|
||
micromultiplicity? And how about the "Lilliputian hallucinations" on
|
||
ether? One schizo, two schizos, three: "There are babies growing in my
|
||
every pore"—"With me, it's not in the pores, it's in my veins, little iron
|
||
rods growing in my veins"—"I don't want them to give me any shots,
|
||
except with camphorated alcohol. Otherwise breasts grow in my every
|
||
pore." Freud tried to approach crowd phenomena from the point of view of
|
||
the unconscious, but he did not see clearly, he did not see that the uncon-
|
||
scious itself was fundamentally a crowd. He was myopic and hard of
|
||
30 D 1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES?
|
||
|
||
hearing; he mistook crowds for a single person. Schizos, on the other hand,
|
||
have sharp eyes and ears. They don't mistake the buzz and shove of the
|
||
crowd for daddy's voice. Once Jung had a dream about bones and skulls. A
|
||
bone or a skull is never alone. Bones are a multiplicity. But Freud wants the
|
||
dream to signify the death of someone. "Jung was surprised and pointed
|
||
out that there were several skulls, not just one. Yet Freud still. . ."3
|
||
A multiplicity of pores, or blackheads, of little scars or stitches. Breasts,
|
||
babies, and rods. A multiplicity of bees, soccer players, or Tuareg. A multi-
|
||
plicity of wolves or jackals . . . All of these things are irreducible but bring
|
||
us to a certain status of the formations of the unconscious. Let us try to
|
||
define the factors involved: first, something plays the role of the full
|
||
body—the body without organs. In the preceding dream it was the desert.
|
||
In the Wolf-Man's dream it is the denuded tree upon which the wolves are
|
||
perched. It is also the skin as envelope or ring, and the sock as reversible
|
||
surface. It can be a house or part of a house, any number of things, any-
|
||
thing. Whenever someone makes love, really makes love, that person con-
|
||
stitutes a body without organs, alone and with the other person or people.
|
||
A body without organs is not an empty body stripped of organs, but a body
|
||
upon which that which serves as organs (wolves, wolf eyes, wolf jaws?) is
|
||
distributed according to crowd phenomena, in Brownian motion, in the
|
||
form of molecular multiplicities. The desert is populous. Thus the body
|
||
without organs is opposed less to organs as such than to the organization of
|
||
the organs insofar as it composes an organism. The body without organs is
|
||
not a dead body but a living body all the more alive and teeming once it has
|
||
blown apart the organism and its organization. Lice hopping on the beach.
|
||
Skin colonies. The full body without organs is a body populated by multi-
|
||
plicities. The problem of the unconscious has most certainly nothing to do
|
||
with generation but rather peopling, population. It is an affair of world-
|
||
wide population on the full body of the earth, not organic familial genera-
|
||
tion. "I love to invent peoples, tribes, racial origins . . . I return from my
|
||
tribes. As of today, I am the adoptive son of fifteen tribes, no more, no less.
|
||
And they in turn are my adopted tribes, for I love each of them more than if
|
||
I had been born into it." People say, After all, schizophrenics have a mother
|
||
and a father, don't they? Sorry, no, none as such. They only have a desert
|
||
with tribes inhabiting it, a full body clinging with multiplicities.
|
||
This brings us to the second factor, the nature of these multiplicities and
|
||
their elements. RHIZOME. One of the essential characteristics of the dream
|
||
of multiplicity is that each element ceaselessly varies and alters its distance
|
||
in relation to the others. On the Wolf-Man's nose, the elements, deter-
|
||
mined as pores in the skin, little scars in the pores, little ruts in the scar tis-
|
||
sue, ceaselessly dance, grow, and diminish. These variable distances are
|
||
not extensive quantities divisible by each other; rather, each is indivisible,
|
||
1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES? D 31
|
||
|
||
or "relatively indivisible," in other words, they are not divisible below or
|
||
above a certain threshold, they cannot increase or diminish without their
|
||
elements changing in nature. A swarm of bees: here they come as a rumble
|
||
of soccer players in striped jerseys, or a band of Tuareg. Or: the wolf clan
|
||
doubles up with a swarm of bees against the gang of Deulhs, under the
|
||
direction of Mowgli, who runs on the edge (yes, Kipling understood the call
|
||
of the wolves, their libidinal meaning, better than Freud; and in the Wolf-
|
||
Man's case the story about wolves is followed by one about wasps and but-
|
||
terflies, we go from wolves to wasps). What is the significance of these
|
||
indivisible distances that are ceaselessly transformed, and cannot be
|
||
divided or transformed without their elements changing in nature each
|
||
time? Is it not the intensive character of this kind of multiplicity's elements
|
||
and the relations between them? Exactly like a speed or a temperature,
|
||
which is not composed of other speeds and temperatures but rather is
|
||
enveloped in or envelops others, each of which marks a change in nature.
|
||
The metrical principle of these multiplicities is not to be found in a homo-
|
||
geneous milieu but resides elsewhere, in forces at work within them, in
|
||
physical phenomena inhabiting them, precisely in the libido, which consti-
|
||
tutes them from within, and in constituting them necessarily divides into
|
||
distinct qualitative and variable flows. Freud himself recognizes the multi-
|
||
plicity of libidinal "currents" that coexist in the Wolf-Man. That makes it
|
||
all the more surprising that he treats the multiplicities of the unconscious
|
||
the way he does. For him, there will always be a reduction to the One: the lit-
|
||
tle scars, the little holes, become subdivisions of the great scar or supreme
|
||
hole named castration; the wolves become substitutes for a single Father
|
||
who turns up everywhere, or wherever they put him. (As Ruth Mack
|
||
Brunswick says, Let's go all the way, the wolves are "all the fathers and doc-
|
||
tors" in the world; but the Wolf-Man thinks, "You trying to tell me my ass
|
||
isn't a wolf?")
|
||
What should have been done is the opposite, all of this should be under-
|
||
stood in intensity: the Wolf is the pack, in other words, the multiplicity
|
||
instantaneously apprehended as such insofar as it approaches or moves
|
||
away from zero, each distance being nondecomposable. Zero is the body
|
||
without organs of the Wolf-Man. If the unconscious knows nothing of
|
||
negation, it is because there is nothing negative in the unconscious, only
|
||
indefinite moves toward and away from zero, which does not at all express
|
||
lack but rather the positivity of the full body as support and prop ("for an
|
||
afflux is necessary simply to signify the absence of intensity"). The wolves
|
||
designate an intensity, a band of intensity, a threshold of intensity on the
|
||
Wolf-Man's body without organs. A dentist told the Wolf-Man that he
|
||
"would soon lose all his teeth because of the violence of his bite"—and that
|
||
his gums were pocked with pustules and little holes.4 Jaw as high intensity,
|
||
32 D 1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES?
|
||
|
||
teeth as low intensity, and pustular gums as approach to zero. The wolf, as
|
||
the instantaneous apprehension of a multiplicity in a given region, is not a
|
||
representative, a substitute, but an I feel. I feel myself becoming a wolf, one
|
||
wolf among others, on the edge of the pack. A cry of anguish, the only one
|
||
Freud hears: Help me not become wolf (or the opposite, Help me not fail in
|
||
this becoming). It is not a question of representation: don't think for a min-
|
||
ute that it has to do with believing oneself a wolf, representing oneself as a
|
||
wolf. The wolf, wolves, are intensities, speeds, temperatures, nondecom-
|
||
posable variable distances. A swarming, a wolfing. Who could ever believe
|
||
that the anal machine bears no relation to the wolf machine, or that the two
|
||
are only linked by an Oedipal apparatus, by the all-too-human figure of the
|
||
Father? For in the end the anus also expresses an intensity, in this case the
|
||
approach to zero of a distance that cannot be decomposed without its ele-
|
||
ments changing in nature. Afield of anuses, just like a pack of wolves. Does
|
||
not the child, on the periphery, hold onto the wolves by his anus? The jaw
|
||
descends to the anus. Hold onto those wolves by your jaw and your anus.
|
||
The jaw is not a wolf jaw, it's not that simple; jaw and wolf form a multipli-
|
||
city that is transformed into eye and wolf, anus and wolf, as a function of
|
||
other distances, at other speeds, with other multiplicities, between thresh-
|
||
olds. Lines of flight or of deterritorialization, becoming-wolf, becoming-
|
||
inhuman, deterritorialized intensities: that is what multiplicity is. To
|
||
become wolf or to become hole is to deterritorialize oneself following dis-
|
||
tinct but entangled lines. A hole is no more negative than a wolf. Castra-
|
||
tion, lack, substitution: a tale told by an overconscious idiot who has no
|
||
understanding of multiplicities as formations of the unconscious. A wolf is
|
||
a hole, they are both particles of the unconscious, nothing but particles,
|
||
productions of particles, particulate paths, as elements of molecular multi-
|
||
plicities. It is not even sufficient to say that intense and moving particles
|
||
pass through holes; a hole is just as much a particle as what passes through
|
||
it. Physicists say that holes are not the absence of particles but particles
|
||
traveling faster than the speed of light. Flying anuses, speeding vaginas,
|
||
there is no castration.
|
||
Let us return to the story of multiplicity, for the creation of this substan-
|
||
tive marks a very important moment. It was created precisely in order to
|
||
escape the abstract opposition between the multiple and the one, to escape
|
||
dialectics, to succeed in conceiving the multiple in the pure state, to cease
|
||
treating it as a numerical fragment of a lost Unity or Totality or as the
|
||
organic element of a Unity or Totality yet to come, and instead distinguish
|
||
between different types of multiplicity. Thus we find in the work of the
|
||
mathematician and physicist Riemann a distinction between discreet mul-
|
||
tiplicities and continuous multiplicities (the metrical principle of the sec-
|
||
ond kind of multiplicity resides solely in forces at work within them). Then
|
||
1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES? D 33
|
||
|
||
in Meinong and Russell we find a distinction between multiplicities of
|
||
magnitude or divisibility, which are extensive, and multiplicities of dis-
|
||
tance, which are closer to the intensive. And in Bergson there is a distinc-
|
||
tion between numerical or extended multiplicities and qualitative or
|
||
durational multiplicities. We are doing approximately the same thing
|
||
when we distinguish between arborescent multiplicities and rhizomatic
|
||
multiplicities. Between macro- and micromultiplicities. On the one hand,
|
||
multiplicities that are extensive, divisible, and molar; unifiable, total-
|
||
izable, organizable; conscious or preconscious—and on the other hand,
|
||
libidinal, unconscious, molecular, intensive multiplicities composed of
|
||
particles that do not divide without changing in nature, and distances that
|
||
do not vary without entering another multiplicity and that constantly con-
|
||
struct and dismantle themselves in the course of their communications, as
|
||
they cross over into each other at, beyond, or before a certain threshold.
|
||
The elements of this second kind of multiplicity are particles; their rela-
|
||
tions are distances; their movements are Brownian; their quantities are
|
||
intensities, differences in intensity.
|
||
This only provides the logical foundation. Elias Canetti distinguishes
|
||
between two types of multiplicity that are sometimes opposed but at other
|
||
times interpenetrate: mass ("crowd") multiplicities and pack multiplici-
|
||
ties. Among the characteristics of a mass, in Canetti's sense, we should note
|
||
large quantity, divisibility and equality of the members, concentration,
|
||
sociability of the aggregate as a whole, one-way hierarchy, organization of
|
||
territoriality or territorialization, and emission of signs. Among the char-
|
||
acteristics of a pack are small or restricted numbers, dispersion, nonde-
|
||
composable variable distances, qualitative metamorphoses, inequalities
|
||
as remainders or crossings, impossibility of a fixed totalization or hierar-
|
||
chization, a Brownian variability in directions, lines of deterritorial-
|
||
ization, and projection of particles.5 Doubtless, there is no more equality
|
||
or any less hierarchy in packs than in masses, but they are of a different
|
||
kind. The leader of the pack or the band plays move by move, must wager
|
||
everything every hand, whereas the group or mass leader consolidates or
|
||
capitalizes on past gains. The pack, even on its own turf, is constituted by a
|
||
line of flight or of deterritorialization that is a component part of it, and to
|
||
which it accredits a high positive value, whereas masses only integrate
|
||
these lines in order to segment them, obstruct them, ascribe them a nega-
|
||
tive sign. Canetti notes that in a pack each member is alone even in the
|
||
company of others (for example, wolves on the hunt); each takes care of
|
||
himself at the same time as participating in the band. "In the changing con-
|
||
stellation of the pack, in its dances and expeditions, he will again and again
|
||
find himself at its edge. He may be in the center, and then, immediately
|
||
afterwards, at the edge again; at the edge and then back in the center. When
|
||
34 n 1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES?
|
||
|
||
the pack forms a ring around the fire, each man will have neighbors to the
|
||
right and left, but no one behind him; his back is naked and exposed to the
|
||
wilderness."6 We recognize this as the schizo position, being on the periph-
|
||
ery, holding on by a hand or a f o o t . . . As opposed to the paranoid position
|
||
of the mass subject, with all the identifications of the individual with the
|
||
group, the group with the leader, and the leader with the group; be securely
|
||
embedded in the mass, get close to the center, never be at the edge except in
|
||
the line of duty. Why assume (as does Konrad Lorenz, for example) that
|
||
bands and their type of companionship represent a more rudimentary evo-
|
||
lutionary state than group societies or societies of conjugality? Not only do
|
||
there exist bands of humans, but there are particularly refined examples:
|
||
"high-society life" differs from "sociality" in that it is closer to the pack.
|
||
Social persons have a certain envious and erroneous image of the high-
|
||
society person because they are ignorant of high-society positions and hier-
|
||
archies, the relations of force, the very particular ambitions and projects.
|
||
High-society relations are never coextensive with social relations, they do
|
||
not coincide. Even "mannerisms" (all bands have them) are specific to
|
||
micromultiplicities and distinct from social manners or customs.
|
||
There is no question, however, of establishing a dualist opposition
|
||
between the two types of multiplicities, molecular machines and molar
|
||
machines; that would be no better than the dualism between the One and
|
||
the multiple. There are only multiplicities of multiplicities forming a single
|
||
assemblage, operating in the same assemblage: packs in masses and masses
|
||
in packs. Trees have rhizome lines, and the rhizome points of arbor-
|
||
escence. How could mad particles be produced with anything but a gigantic
|
||
cyclotron? How could lines of deterritorialization be assignable outside of
|
||
circuits of territoriality? Where else but in wide expanses, and in major
|
||
upheavals in those expanses, could a tiny rivulet of new intensity suddenly
|
||
start to flow? What do you not have to do in order to produce a new sound?
|
||
Becoming-animal, becoming-molecular, becoming-inhuman, each
|
||
involves a molar extension, a human hyperconcentration, or prepares the
|
||
way for them. In Kafka, it is impossible to separate the erection of a great
|
||
paranoid bureaucratic machine from the installation of little schizo
|
||
machines of becoming-dog or becoming-beetle. In the case of the Wolf-
|
||
Man, it is impossible to separate the becoming-wolf of his dream from the
|
||
military and religious organization of his obsessions. A military man does
|
||
a wolf; a military man does a dog. There are not two multiplicities or two
|
||
machines; one and the same machinic assemblage produces and distrib-
|
||
utes the whole, in other words, the set of statements corresponding to the
|
||
"complex." What does psychoanalysis have to say about all of this? Oedi-
|
||
pus, nothing but Oedipus, because it hears nothing and listens to nobody. It
|
||
flattens everything, masses and packs, molecular and molar machines,
|
||
1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES? D 35
|
||
|
||
multiplicities of every variety. Take the Wolf-Man's second dream during
|
||
his so-called psychotic episode: in the street, a wall with a closed door, to
|
||
the left an empty dresser; in front of the dresser, the patient, and a big
|
||
woman with a little scar who seems to want to skirt around the wall; behind
|
||
the wall, wolves, rushing for the door. Even Brunswick can't go wrong:
|
||
although she recognizes herself in the big woman, she does see that this
|
||
time the wolves are Bolsheviks, the revolutionary mass that had emptied
|
||
the dresser and confiscated the Wolf-Man's fortune. The wolves, in a
|
||
metastable state, have gone over to a large-scale social machine. But psycho-
|
||
analysis has nothing to say about all of these points—except what Freud
|
||
already said: it all leads back to daddy (what do you know, he was one of the
|
||
leaders of the liberal party in Russia, but that's hardly important; all that
|
||
needs to be said is that the revolution "assuaged the patient's feelings of
|
||
guilt"). You'd think that the investments and counterinvestments of the
|
||
libido had nothing to do with mass disturbances, pack movements, collec-
|
||
tive signs, and particles of desire.
|
||
Thus it does not suffice to attribute molar multiplicities and mass
|
||
machines to the preconscious, reserving another kind of machine or multi-
|
||
plicity for the unconscious. For it is the assemblage of both of these that is
|
||
the province of the unconscious, the way in which the former condition the
|
||
latter, and the latter prepare the way for the former, or elude them or return
|
||
to them: the libido suffuses everything. Keep everything in sight at the
|
||
same time—that a social machine or an organized mass has a molecular
|
||
unconscious that marks not only its tendency to decompose but also the
|
||
current components of its very operation and organization; that any indi-
|
||
vidual caught up in a mass has his/her own pack unconscious, which does
|
||
not necessarily resemble the packs of the mass to which that individual
|
||
belongs; that an individual or mass will live out in its unconscious the
|
||
masses and packs of another mass or another individual. What does it
|
||
mean to love somebody? It is always to seize that person in a mass, extract
|
||
him or her from a group, however small, in which he or she participates,
|
||
whether it be through the family only or through something else; then to
|
||
find that person's own packs, the multiplicities he or she encloses within
|
||
himself or herself which may be of an entirely different nature. To join
|
||
them to mine, to make them penetrate mine, and for me to penetrate the
|
||
other person's. Heavenly nuptials, multiplicities of multiplicities. Every
|
||
love is an exercise in depersonalization on a body without organs yet to be
|
||
formed, and it is at the highest point of this depersonalization that some-
|
||
one can be named, receives his or her family name or first name, acquires
|
||
the most intense discernibility in the instantaneous apprehension of the
|
||
multiplicities belonging to him or her, and to which he or she belongs. A
|
||
pack of freckles on a face, a pack of boys speaking through the voice of a
|
||
36 n 1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES?
|
||
|
||
woman, a clutch of girls in Charlus's voice, a horde of wolves in somebody's
|
||
throat, a multiplicity of anuses in the anus, mouth, or eye one is intent
|
||
upon. We each go through so many bodies in each other. Albertine is slowly
|
||
extracted from a group of girls with its own number, organization, code,
|
||
and hierarchy; and not only is this group or restricted mass suffused by an
|
||
unconscious, but Albertine has her own multiplicities that the narrator,
|
||
once he has isolated her, discovers on her body and in her lies—until the
|
||
end of their love returns her to the indiscernible.
|
||
Above all, it should not be thought that it suffices to distinguish the
|
||
masses and exterior groups someone belongs to or participates in from the
|
||
internal aggregates that person envelops in himself or herself. The
|
||
distinction to be made is not at all between exterior and interior, which
|
||
are always relative, changing, and reversible, but between different
|
||
types of multiplicities that coexist, interpenetrate, and change places—
|
||
machines, cogs, motors, and elements that are set in motion at a given
|
||
moment, forming an assemblage productive of statements: "I love you" (or
|
||
whatever). For Kafka, Felice is inseparable from a certain social machine,
|
||
and, as a representative of the firm that manufactures them, from
|
||
parlograph machines; how could she not belong to that organization in the
|
||
eyes of Kafka, a man fascinated by commerce and bureaucracy? But at the
|
||
same time, Felice's teeth, her big carnivorous teeth, send her racing down
|
||
other lines, into the molecular multiplicities of a becoming-dog, a
|
||
becoming-jackal . .. Felice is inseparable from the sign of the modern
|
||
social machines belonging to her, from those belonging to Kafka (not the
|
||
same ones), and from the particles, the little molecular machines, the
|
||
whole strange becoming or journey Kafka will make and have her make
|
||
through his perverse writing apparatus.
|
||
There are no individual statements, only statement-producing ma-
|
||
chinic assemblages. We say that the assemblage is fundamentally libidinal
|
||
and unconscious. It is the unconscious in person. For the moment, we will
|
||
note that assemblages have elements (or multiplicities) of several kinds:
|
||
human, social, and technical machines, organized molar machines; molec-
|
||
ular machines with their particles of becoming-inhuman; Oedipal appara-
|
||
tuses (yes, of course there are Oedipal statements, many of them); and
|
||
counter-Oedipal apparatuses, variable in aspect and functioning. We will
|
||
go into it later. We can no longer even speak of distinct machines, only of
|
||
types of interpenetrating multiplicities that at any given moment form a
|
||
single machinic assemblage, the faceless figure of the libido. Each of us is
|
||
caught up in an assemblage of this kind, and we reproduce its statements
|
||
when we think we are speaking in our own name; or rather we speak in our
|
||
own name when we produce its statement. And what bizarre statements
|
||
they are; truly, the talk of lunatics. We mentioned Kafka, but we could just
|
||
1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES? D 37
|
||
|
||
as well have said the Wolf-Man: a religious-military machine that Freud
|
||
attributes to obsessional neurosis; an anal pack machine, an anal be-
|
||
coming-wolf or -wasp or -butterfly machine, which Freud attributes to the
|
||
hysteric character; an Oedipal apparatus, which Freud considers the sole
|
||
motor, the immobile motor that must be found everywhere; and a counter-
|
||
Oedipal apparatus—incest with the sister, schizo-incest, or love with "peo-
|
||
ple of inferior station"; and anality, homosexuality?—all that Freud sees
|
||
only as Oedipal substitutes, regressions, and derivatives. In truth, Freud
|
||
sees nothing and understands nothing. He has no idea what a libidinal
|
||
assemblage is, with all the machineries it brings into play, all the multiple
|
||
loves.
|
||
Of course, there are Oedipal statements. For example, Kafka's story,
|
||
"Jackals and Arabs," is easy to read in that way: you can always do it, you
|
||
can't lose, it works every time, even if you understand nothing. The Arabs
|
||
are clearly associated with the father and the jackals with the mother;
|
||
between the two, there is a whole story of castration represented by the
|
||
rusty scissors. But it so happens that the Arabs are an extensive, armed,
|
||
organized mass stretching across the entire desert; and the jackals are an
|
||
intense pack forever launching into the desert following lines of flight or
|
||
deterritorialization ("they are madmen, veritable madmen"); between the
|
||
two, at the edge, the Man of the North, the jackal-man. And aren't those big
|
||
scissors the Arab sign that guides or releases jackal-particles, both to accel-
|
||
erate their mad race by detaching them from the mass and to bring them
|
||
back to the mass, to tame them and whip them, to bring them around?
|
||
Dead camel: Oedipal food apparatus. Counter-Oedipal carrion apparatus:
|
||
kill animals to eat, or eat to clean up carrion. The jackals formulate the
|
||
problem well: it is not that of castration but of "cleanliness" (propret'e, also
|
||
"ownness"), the test of desert-desire. Which will prevail, mass territoriality
|
||
or pack deterritorialization? The libido suffuses the entire desert, the body
|
||
without organs on which the drama is played out.
|
||
There are no individual statements, there never are. Every statement is
|
||
the product of a machinic assemblage, in other words, of collective agents
|
||
of enunciation (take "collective agents" to mean not peoples or societies
|
||
but multiplicities). The proper name (nom propre) does not designate an
|
||
individual: it is on the contrary when the individual opens up to the multi-
|
||
plicities pervading him or her, at the outcome of the most severe operation
|
||
of depersonalization, that he or she acquires his or her true proper name.
|
||
The proper name is the instantaneous apprehension of a multiplicity. The
|
||
proper name is the subject of a pure infinitive comprehended as such in a
|
||
field of intensity. What Proust said about the first name: when I said
|
||
Gilberte's name, I had the impression that I was holding her entire body
|
||
naked in my mouth. The Wolf-Man, a true proper name, an intimate first
|
||
38 D 1914: ONE OR SEVERAL WOLVES?
|
||
|
||
name linked to the becomings, infinitives, and intensities of a multiplied
|
||
and depersonalized individual. What does psychoanalysis know about
|
||
multiplication? The desert hour when the dromedary becomes a thousand
|
||
dromedaries snickering in the sky. The evening hour when a thousand
|
||
holes appear on the surface of the earth. Castration! Castration! cries the
|
||
psychoanalytic scarecrow, who never saw more than a hole, a father or a
|
||
dog where wolves are, a domesticated individual where there are wild mul-
|
||
tiplicities. We are not just criticizing psychoanalysis for having selected
|
||
Oedipal statements exclusively. For such statements are to a certain extent
|
||
part of a machinic assemblage, for which they could serve as correctional
|
||
indexes, as in a calculation of errors. We are criticizing psychoanalysis for
|
||
having used Oedipal enunciation to make patients believe they would pro-
|
||
duce individual, personal statements, and would finally speak in their own
|
||
name. The trap was set from the start: never will the Wolf-Man speak. Talk
|
||
as he might about wolves, howl as he might like a wolf, Freud does not even
|
||
listen; he glances at his dog and answers, "It's daddy." For as long as that
|
||
lasts, Freud calls it neurosis; when it cracks, it's psychosis. The Wolf-Man
|
||
will receive the psychoanalytic medal of honor for services rendered to the
|
||
cause, and even disabled veterans' benefits. He could have spoken in his
|
||
own name only if the machinic assemblage that was producing particular
|
||
statements in him had been brought to light. But there is no question of that
|
||
in psychoanalysis: at the very moment the subject is persuaded that he or
|
||
she will be uttering the most individual of statements, he or she is deprived
|
||
of all basis for enunciation. Silence people, prevent them from speaking,
|
||
and above all, when they do speak, pretend they haven't said a thing: the
|
||
famous psychoanalytic neutrality. The Wolf-Man keeps howling: Six
|
||
wolves! Seven wolves! Freud says, How's that? Goats, you say? How inter-
|
||
esting. Take away the goats and all you have left is a wolf, so it's your father
|
||
. . . That is why the Wolf-Man feels so fatigued: he's left lying there with all
|
||
his wolves in his throat, all those little holes on his nose, and all those libidi-
|
||
nal values on his body without organs. The war will come, the wolves will
|
||
become Bolsheviks, and the Wolf-Man will remain suffocated by all he had
|
||
to say. All we will be told is that he became well behaved, polite, and
|
||
resigned again, "honest and scrupulous." In short, cured. He gets back by
|
||
pointing out that psychoanalysis lacks a truly zoological vision: "Nothing
|
||
can be more valuable for a young person than the love of nature and a com-
|
||
prehension of the natural sciences, in particular zoology."7
|
||
3. 10,000 B.C.: The Geology of Morals
|
||
(Who Does the Earth Think It Is?)
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Double Articulation
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
39
|
||
40 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
The same Professor Challenger who made the Earth scream with his pain
|
||
machine, as described by Arthur Conan Doyle, gave a lecture after mixing
|
||
several textbooks on geology and biology in a fashion befitting his simian
|
||
disposition. He explained that the Earth—the Deterritorialized, the
|
||
Glacial, the giant Molecule—is a body without organs. This body without
|
||
organs is permeated by unformed, unstable matters, by flows in all direc-
|
||
tions, by free intensities or nomadic singularities, by mad or transitory par-
|
||
ticles. That, however, was not the question at hand. For there simultane-
|
||
ously occurs upon the earth a very important, inevitable phenomenon that
|
||
is beneficial in many respects and unfortunate in many others: stratifica-
|
||
tion. Strata are Layers, Belts. They consist of giving form to matters, of
|
||
imprisoning intensities or locking singularities into systems of resonance
|
||
and redundancy, of producing upon the body of the earth molecules large
|
||
and small and organizing them into molar aggregates. Strata are acts of
|
||
capture, they are like "black holes" or occlusions striving to seize whatever
|
||
comes within their reach.1 They operate by coding and territorialization
|
||
upon the earth; they proceed simultaneously by code and by territoriality.
|
||
The strata are judgments of God; stratification in general is the entire sys-
|
||
tem of the judgment of God (but the earth, or the body without organs, con-
|
||
stantly eludes that judgment, flees and becomes destratified, decoded,
|
||
deterritorialized).
|
||
Challenger quoted a sentence he said he came across in a geology text-
|
||
book. He said we needed to learn it by heart because we would only be in a
|
||
position to understand it later on: "A surface of stratification is a more
|
||
compact plane of consistency lying between two layers." The layers are the
|
||
strata. They come at least in pairs, one serving as substratum for the other.
|
||
The surface of stratification is a machinic assemblage distinct from the
|
||
strata. The assemblage is between two layers, between two strata; on one
|
||
side it faces the strata (in this direction, the assemblage is an inter stratum),
|
||
but the other side faces something else, the body without organs or plane of
|
||
consistency (here, it is a metastratum). In effect, the body without organs is
|
||
itself the plane of consistency, which becomes compact or thickens at the
|
||
level of the strata.
|
||
God is a Lobster, or a double pincer, a double bind. Not only do strata
|
||
come at least in pairs, but in a different way each stratum is double (it itself
|
||
has several layers). Each stratum exhibits phenomena constitutive of dou-
|
||
ble articulation. Articulate twice, B-A, BA. This is not at all to say that the
|
||
strata speak or are language based. Double articulation is so extremely var-
|
||
iable that we cannot begin with a general model, only a relatively simple
|
||
case. The first articulation chooses or deducts, from unstable particle-
|
||
flows, metastable molecular or quasi-molecular units (substances) upon
|
||
which it imposes a statistical order of connections and successions (forms).
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 41
|
||
|
||
The second articulation establishes functional, compact, stable structures
|
||
(forms), and constructs the molar compounds in which these structures are
|
||
simultaneously actualized (substances). In a geological stratum, for exam-
|
||
ple, the first articulation is the process of "sedimentation," which deposits
|
||
units of cyclic sediment according to a statistical order: flysch, with its
|
||
succession of sandstone and schist. The second articulation is the "fold-
|
||
ing" that sets up a stable functional structure and effects the passage from
|
||
sediment to sedimentary rock.
|
||
It is clear that the distinction between the two articulations is not
|
||
between substances and forms. Substances are nothing other than formed
|
||
matters. Forms imply a code, modes of coding and decoding. Substances as
|
||
formed matters refer to territorialities and degrees of territorialization and
|
||
deterritorialization. But each articulation has a code and a territorially;
|
||
therefore each possesses both form and substance. For now, all we can say is
|
||
that each articulation has a corresponding type of segmentarity or multi-
|
||
plicity: one type is supple, more molecular, and merely ordered; the other is
|
||
more rigid, molar, and organized. Although the first articulation is not
|
||
lacking in systematic interactions, it is in the second articulation in partic-
|
||
ular that phenomena constituting an overcoding are produced, phenom-
|
||
ena of centering, unification, totalization, integration, hierarchization,
|
||
and finalization. Both articulations establish binary relations between
|
||
their respective segments. But between the segments of one articulation
|
||
and the segments of the other there are biunivocal relationships obeying far
|
||
more complex laws. The word "structure" may be used to designate the
|
||
sum of these relations and relationships, but it is an illusion to believe that
|
||
structure is the earth's last word. Moreover, it cannot be taken for granted
|
||
that the distinction between the two articulations is always that of the
|
||
molecular and the molar.
|
||
He skipped over the immense diversity of the energetic, physico-
|
||
chemical, and geological strata. He went straight to the organic strata, or
|
||
the existence of a great organic stratification. The problem of the
|
||
organism—how to "make" the body an organism—is once again a problem
|
||
of articulation, of the articulatory relation. The Dogons, well known to the
|
||
professor, formulate the problem as follows: an organism befalls the body
|
||
of the smith, by virtue of a machine or machinic assemblage that stratifies
|
||
it. "The shock of the hammer and the anvil broke his arms and legs at the
|
||
elbows and knees, which until that moment he had not possessed. In this
|
||
way, he received the articulations specific to the new human form that was
|
||
to spread across the earth, a form dedicated to work.... His arm became
|
||
folded with a view to work."2 It is obviously only a manner of speaking to
|
||
limit the articulatory relation to the bones. The entire organism must be
|
||
considered in relation to a double articulation, and on different levels.
|
||
42 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
First, on the level of morphogenesis: on the one hand, realities of the
|
||
molecular type with aleatory relations are caught up in crowd phenomena
|
||
or statistical aggregates determining an order (the protein fiber and its
|
||
sequence or segmentarity); on the other hand, these aggregates themselves
|
||
are taken up into stable structures that "elect" stereoscopic compounds,
|
||
form organs, functions, and regulations, organize molar mechanisms, and
|
||
even distribute centers capable of overflying crowds, overseeing mecha-
|
||
nisms, utilizing and repairing tools, "overcoding" the aggregate (the fold-
|
||
ing back on itself of the fiber to form a compact structure; a second kind of
|
||
segmentarity).3 Sedimentation and folding, fiber and infolding.
|
||
On a different level, the cellular chemistry presiding over the constitu-
|
||
tion of proteins also operates by double articulation. This double articula-
|
||
tion is internal to the molecular, it is the articulation between small and
|
||
large molecules, a segmentarity by successive modifications and polymeri-
|
||
zation. "First, the elements taken from the medium are combined through
|
||
a series of transformations.. . .All this activity involves hundreds of chem-
|
||
ical reactions. But ultimately, it produces a limited number of small com-
|
||
pounds, a few dozen at most. In the second stage of cellular chemistry, the
|
||
small molecules are assembled to produce larger ones. It is the polymeriza-
|
||
tion of units linked end-to-end that forms the characteristic chains of mac-
|
||
romolecules. . .. The two stages of cellular chemistry, therefore, differ in
|
||
their function, products and nature. The first carves out chemical motifs;
|
||
the second assembles them. The first forms compounds that exist only
|
||
temporarily, for they are intermediaries on the path of biosynthesis; the
|
||
second constructs stable products. The first operates by a series of different
|
||
reactions; the second by repeating the same reaction."4 There is, moreover,
|
||
a third level, upon which cellular chemistry itself depends. It is the genetic
|
||
code, which is in turn inseparable from a double segmentarity or a double
|
||
articulation, this time between two types of independent molecules: the
|
||
sequence of protein units and the sequence of nucleic units, with binary
|
||
relations between units of the same type and biunivocal relationships
|
||
between units of different types. Thus there are always two articulations,
|
||
two segmentarities, two kinds of multiplicity, each of which brings into
|
||
play both forms and substances. But the distribution of these two articula-
|
||
tions is not constant, even within the same stratum.
|
||
The audience rather sulkily denounced the numerous misunderstand-
|
||
ings, misinterpretations, and even misappropriations in the professor's
|
||
presentation, despite the authorities he had appealed to, calling them his
|
||
"friends." Even the Dogons . . . And things would presently get worse. The
|
||
professor cynically congratulated himself on taking his pleasure from
|
||
behind, but the offspring always turned out to be runts and wens, bits and
|
||
pieces, if not stupid vulgarizations. Besides, the professor was not a geolo-
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 43
|
||
|
||
gist or a biologist, he was not even a linguist, ethnologist, or psychoanalyst;
|
||
what his specialty had been was long since forgotten. In fact, Professor
|
||
Challenger was double, articulated twice, and that did not make things any
|
||
easier, people never knew which of him was present. He (?) claimed to have
|
||
invented a discipline he referred to by various names: rhizomatics,
|
||
stratoanalysis, schizoanalysis, nomadology, micropolitics, pragmatics, the
|
||
science of multiplicities. Yet no one clearly understood what the goals,
|
||
method, or principles of this discipline were. Young Professor Alasca,
|
||
Challenger's pet student, tried hypocritically to defend him by explaining
|
||
that on a given stratum the passage from one articulation to the other was
|
||
easily verified because it was always accompanied by a loss of water, in
|
||
genetics as in geology, and even in linguistics, where the importance of the
|
||
"lost saliva" phenomenon is measured. Challenger took offense, preferring
|
||
to cite his friend, as he called him, the Danish Spinozist geologist,
|
||
Hjelmslev, that dark prince descended from Hamlet who also made lan-
|
||
guage his concern, precisely in order to analyze its "stratification."
|
||
Hjelmslev was able to weave a net out of the notions of matter, content and
|
||
expression, form and substance. These were the strata, said Hjelmslev. Now
|
||
this net had the advantage of breaking with the form-content duality, since
|
||
there was a form of content no less than a form of expression. Hjelmslev's
|
||
enemies saw this merely as a way of rebaptizing the discredited notions of
|
||
the signified and signifier, but something quite different was actually going
|
||
on. Despite what Hjelmslev himself may have said, the net is not linguistic
|
||
in scope or origin (the same must be said of double articulation: if language
|
||
has a specificity of its own, as it most certainly does, that specificity con-
|
||
sists neither in double articulation nor in Hjelmslev's net, which are gen-
|
||
eral characteristics of strata).
|
||
He used the term matter for the plane of consistency or Body without
|
||
Organs, in other words, the unformed, unorganized, nonstratified, or
|
||
destratified body and all its flows: subatomic and submolecular particles,
|
||
pure intensities, prevital and prephysical free singularities. He used the
|
||
term content for formed matters, which would now have to be considered
|
||
from two points of view: substance, insofar as these matters are "chosen,"
|
||
and form, insofar as they are chosen in a certain order (substance and form
|
||
of content). He used the term expression for functional structures, which
|
||
would also have to be considered from two points of view: the organization
|
||
of their own specific form, and substances insofar as they form compounds
|
||
(form and content of expression). A stratum always has a dimension of the
|
||
expressible or of expression serving as the basis for a relative invariance;
|
||
for example, nucleic sequences are inseparable from a relatively invariant
|
||
expression by means of which they determine the compounds, organs, and
|
||
functions of the organism.5 To express is always to sing the glory of God.
|
||
44 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
Every stratum is a judgment of God; not only do plants and animals,
|
||
orchids and wasps, sing or express themselves, but so do rocks and even riv-
|
||
ers, every stratified thing on earth. The first articulation concerns content,
|
||
the second expression. The distinction between the two articulations is not
|
||
between forms and substances but between content and expression,
|
||
expression having just as much substance as content and content just as
|
||
much form as expression. The double articulation sometimes coincides
|
||
with the molecular and the molar, and sometimes not; this is because con-
|
||
tent and expression are sometimes divided along those lines and some-
|
||
times along different lines. There is never correspondence or conformity
|
||
between content and expression, only isomorphism with reciprocal pre-
|
||
supposition. The distinction between content and expression is always
|
||
real, in various ways, but it cannot be said that the terms preexist their dou-
|
||
ble articulation. It is the double articulation that distributes them accord-
|
||
ing to the line it draws in each stratum; it is what constitutes their real
|
||
distinction. (On the other hand, there is no real distinction between form
|
||
and substance, only a mental or modal distinction: since substances are
|
||
nothing other than formed matters, formless substances are inconceivable,
|
||
although it is possible in certain instances to conceive of substanceless
|
||
forms.)
|
||
Even though there is a real distinction between them, content and
|
||
expression are relative terms ("first" and "second" articulation should also
|
||
be understood in an entirely relative fashion). Even though it is capable of
|
||
invariance, expression is just as much a variable as content. Content and
|
||
expression are two variables of a function of stratification. They not only
|
||
vary from one stratum to another, but intermingle, and within the same
|
||
stratum multiply and divide ad infinitum. Since every articulation is dou-
|
||
ble, there is not an articulation of content and an articulation of
|
||
expression—the articulation of content is double in its own right and con-
|
||
stitutes a relative expression within content; the articulation of expression
|
||
is also double and constitutes a relative content within expression. For this
|
||
reason, there exist intermediate states between content and expression,
|
||
expression and content: the levels, equilibriums, and exchanges through
|
||
which a stratified system passes. In short, we find forms and substances of
|
||
content that play the role of expression in relation to other forms and sub-
|
||
stances, and conversely for expression. These new distinctions do not,
|
||
therefore, coincide with the distinction between forms and substances
|
||
within each articulation; instead, they show that each articulation is
|
||
already, or still, double. This can be seen on the organic stratum: proteins
|
||
of content have two forms, one of which (the infolded fiber) plays the role
|
||
of functional expression in relation to the other. The same goes for the
|
||
nucleic acids of expression: double articulations cause certain formal and
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 45
|
||
|
||
substantial elements to play the role of content in relation to others; not
|
||
only does the half of the chain that is reproduced become a content, but the
|
||
reconstituted chain itself becomes a content in relation to the "messenger."
|
||
There are double pincers everywhere on a stratum; everywhere and in all
|
||
directions there are double binds and lobsters, a multiplicity of double
|
||
articulations affecting both expression and content. Through all of this,
|
||
Hjelmslev's warning should not be forgotten: "The terms expression plane
|
||
and content plane . . . are chosen in conformity with established notions
|
||
and are quite arbitrary. Their functional definition provides no justifica-
|
||
tion for calling one, and not the other, of these entities expression, or one,
|
||
and not the other, content. They are defined only by their mutual solidarity,
|
||
and neither of them can be identified otherwise. They are defined only
|
||
oppositively and relatively, as mutually opposed functives of one and the
|
||
same function."6 We must combine all the resources of real distinction,
|
||
reciprocal presupposition, and general relativism.
|
||
|
||
The question we must ask is what on a given stratum varies and what
|
||
does not. What accounts for the unity and diversity of a stratum? Matter,
|
||
the pure matter of the plane of consistency (or inconsistency) lies outside
|
||
the strata. The molecular materials borrowed from the substrata may be
|
||
the same throughout a stratum, but that does not mean that the molecules
|
||
will be the same. The substantial elements may be the same throughout the
|
||
stratum without the substances being the same. The formal relations or
|
||
bonds may be the same without the forms being the same. In biochemistry,
|
||
there is a unity of composition of the organic stratum defined at the level of
|
||
materials and energy, substantial elements or radicals, bonds and reac-
|
||
tions. But there is a variety of different molecules, substances, and forms.
|
||
Should we not sing the praise of Geoffrey Saint-Hilaire? For in the nine-
|
||
teenth century he developed a grandiose conception of stratification. He
|
||
said that matter, considered from the standpoint of its greatest divisibility,
|
||
consists in particles of decreasing size, flows or elastic fluids that "deploy
|
||
themselves" by radiating through space. Combustion is the process of this
|
||
escape or infinite division on the plane of consistency. Electrification is the
|
||
opposite process, constitutive of strata; it is the process whereby similar
|
||
particles group together to form atoms and molecules, similar molecules to
|
||
form bigger molecules, and the biggest molecules to form molar aggregates:
|
||
"the attraction of like by like," as in a double pincer or double articulation.
|
||
Thus there is no vital matter specific to the organic stratum, matter is the
|
||
same on all the strata. But the organic stratum does have a specific unity of
|
||
composition, a single abstract Animal, a single machine embedded in the
|
||
stratum, and presents everywhere the same molecular materials, the same
|
||
elements or anatomical components of organs, the same formal connec-
|
||
46 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
tions. Organic forms are nevertheless different from one another, as are
|
||
organs, compound substances, and molecules. It is of little or no impor-
|
||
tance that Geoffroy chose anatomical elements as the substantial units
|
||
rather than protein and nucleic acid radicals. At any rate, he already
|
||
invoked a whole interplay of molecules. The important thing is the princi-
|
||
ple of the simultaneous unity and variety of the stratum: isomorphism of
|
||
forms but no correspondence; identity of elements or components but no
|
||
identity of compound substances.
|
||
This is where the dialogue, or rather violent debate, with Cuvier came
|
||
in. To keep the last of the audience from leaving, Challenger imagined a
|
||
particularly epistemological dialogue of the dead, in puppet theater style.
|
||
Geoffroy called forth Monsters, Cuvier laid out all the Fossils in order,
|
||
Baer flourished flasks filled with embryos, Vialleton put on a tetrapod's
|
||
belt, Perrier mimed the dramatic battle between the Mouth and the Brain,
|
||
and so on. Geoffroy: The proof that there is isomorphism is that you can
|
||
always get from one form on the organic stratum to another, however dif-
|
||
ferent they may be, by means of "folding." To go from the Vertebrate to the
|
||
Cephalopod, bring the two sides of the Vertebrate's backbone together,
|
||
bend its head down to its feet and its pelvis up to the nape of its neck ...
|
||
Cuvier (angrily): That's just not true! You go from an Elephant to a
|
||
Medusa; I know, I tried. There are irreducible axes, types, branches. There
|
||
are resemblances between organs and analogies between forms, nothing
|
||
more. You're a falsifier, a metaphysician. Vialleton (a disciple of Cuvier
|
||
and Baer): Even if folding gave good results, who could endure it? It's not
|
||
by chance that Geoffroy only considers anatomical elements. No muscle or
|
||
ligament would survive it. Geoffroy: I said that there was isomorphism but
|
||
not correspondence. You have to bring "degrees of development or perfec-
|
||
tion" into the picture. It is not everywhere on a stratum that materials
|
||
reach the degree at which they form a given aggregate. Anatomical ele-
|
||
ments may be arrested or inhibited in certain places by molecular clashes,
|
||
the influence of the milieu, or pressure from neighbors to such an extent
|
||
that they compose different organs. The same formal relations or connec-
|
||
tions are then effectuated in entirely different forms and arrangements. It
|
||
is still the same abstract Animal that is realized throughout the stratum,
|
||
only to varying degrees, in varying modes. Each time, it is as perfect as its
|
||
surroundings or milieu allows it to be (it is obviously not yet a question of
|
||
evolution: neither folding nor degrees imply descent or derivation, only
|
||
autonomous realizations of the same abstract relations). This is where
|
||
Geoffroy invoked Monsters: human monsters are embryos that were
|
||
retarded at a certain degree of development, the human in them is only a
|
||
straitjacket for inhuman forms and substances. Yes, the Heteradelph is a
|
||
crustacean. Baer (an ally of Cuvier and contemporary of Darwin, about
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 47
|
||
|
||
whom he had reservations, in addition to being an enemy of Geoffroy):
|
||
That's not true, you can't confuse degrees of development with types of
|
||
forms. A single type has several degrees, a single degree is found in several
|
||
types, but never will you make types out of degrees. An embryo of one type
|
||
cannot display another type; at most, it can be of the same degree as an
|
||
embryo of the second type. Vialleton (a disciple of Baer's who took both
|
||
Darwin and Geoffroy one further): And then there are things that only an
|
||
embryo can do or endure. It can do or endure these things precisely because
|
||
of its type, not because it can go from one type to another according to
|
||
degrees of development. Admire the Tortoise. Its neck requires that a cer-
|
||
tain number of protovertebrae change position, and its front limbs must
|
||
slide 180 degrees in relation to that of a bird. You can never draw conclu-
|
||
sions about phylogenesis on the basis of embryogenesis. Folding does not
|
||
make it possible to go from one type to another; quite the contrary, the
|
||
types testify to the irreducibility of the forms of folding . . . (Thus Vialleton
|
||
presented two kinds of interconnected arguments in the service of the same
|
||
cause, saying first that there are things no animal can do by reason of its
|
||
substance, and then that there are things that only an embryo can do by rea-
|
||
son of its form. Two strong arguments.)7
|
||
We're a little lost now. There is so much going on in these retorts. So
|
||
many endlessly proliferating distinctions. So much getting even, for episte-
|
||
mology is not innocent. The sweet and subtle Geoffroy and the violent and
|
||
serious Cuvier do battle around Napoleon. Cuvier, the rigid specialist, is
|
||
pitted against Geoffroy, always ready to switch specialities. Cuvier hates
|
||
Geoffroy, he can't stomach Geoffrey's lighthearted formulas, his humor
|
||
(yes, Hens do indeed have teeth, the Lobster has skin on its bones, etc.).
|
||
Cuvier is a man of Power and Terrain, and he won't let Geoffroy forget it;
|
||
Geoffroy, on the other hand, prefigures the nomadic man of speed. Cuvier
|
||
reflects a Euclidean space, whereas Geoffroy thinks topologically. Today
|
||
let us invoke the folds of the cortex with all their paradoxes. Strata are topo-
|
||
logical, and Geoffroy is a great artist of the fold, a formidable artist; as
|
||
such, he already has a presentiment of a certain kind of animal rhizome
|
||
with aberrant paths of communication—Monsters. Cuvier reacts in terms
|
||
of discontinuous photographs, and casts of fossils. But we're a little lost,
|
||
because distinctions have proliferated in all directions.
|
||
We have not even taken Darwin, evolutionism, or neoevolutionism into
|
||
account yet. This, however, is where a decisive phenomenon occurs: our
|
||
puppet theater becomes more and more nebulous, in other words, collec-
|
||
tive and differential. Earlier, we invoked two factors, and their uncertain
|
||
relations, in order to explain the diversity within a stratum—degrees of
|
||
development or perfection and types of forms. They now undergo a pro-
|
||
found transformation. There is a double tendency for types of forms to be
|
||
48 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
understood increasingly in terms of populations, packs and colonies,
|
||
collectivities or multiplicities; and degrees of development in terms of
|
||
speeds, rates, coefficients, and differential relations. A double deepening.
|
||
This, Darwinism's fundamental contribution, implies a new coupling of
|
||
individuals and milieus on the stratum.8
|
||
First, if we assume the presence of an elementary or even molecular pop-
|
||
ulation in a given milieu, the forms do not preexist the population, they are
|
||
more like statistical results. The more a population assumes divergent
|
||
forms, the more its multiplicity divides into multiplicities of different
|
||
nature, the more its elements form distinct compounds or matters—the
|
||
more efficiently it distributes itself in the milieu, or divides up the milieu.
|
||
Thus the relationship between embryogenesis and phylogenesis is
|
||
reversed: the embryo does not testify to an absolute form preestablished in
|
||
a closed milieu; rather, the phylogenesis of populations has at its disposal,
|
||
in an open milieu, an entire range of relative forms to choose from, none of
|
||
which is preestablished. In embryogenesis, "It is possible to tell from the
|
||
parents, anticipating the outcome of the process, whether a pigeon or a wolf
|
||
is developing.... But here the points of reference themselves are in
|
||
motion: there are only fixed points for convenience of expression. At the
|
||
level of universal evolution, it is impossible to discern that kind of refer-
|
||
ence point Life on earth appears as a sum of relatively independent
|
||
species of flora and fauna with sometimes shifting or porous boundaries
|
||
between them. Geographical areas can only harbor a sort of chaos, or, at
|
||
best, extrinsic harmonies of an ecological order, temporary equilibriums
|
||
between populations."9
|
||
Second, simultaneously and under the same conditions, the degrees are
|
||
not degrees of preexistent development or perfection but are instead global
|
||
and relative equilibriums: they enter into play as a function of the advan-
|
||
tage they give particular elements, then a particular multiplicity in the
|
||
milieu, and as a function of a particular variation in the milieu. Degrees are
|
||
no longer measured in terms of increasing perfection or a differentiation
|
||
and increase in the complexity of the parts, but in terms of differential rela-
|
||
tions and coefficients such as selective pressure, catalytic action, speed of
|
||
propagation, rate of growth, evolution, mutation, etc. Relative progress,
|
||
then, can occur by formal and quantitative simplification rather than by
|
||
complication, by a loss of components and syntheses rather than by acqui-
|
||
sition (it is a question of speed, and speed is a differential). It is through
|
||
populations that one is formed, assumes forms, and through loss that one
|
||
progresses and picks up speed. Darwinism's two fundamental contribu-
|
||
tions move in the direction of a science of multiplicities: the substitution of
|
||
populations for types, and the substitution of rates or differential relations
|
||
for degrees.10 These are nomadic contributions with shifting boundaries
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 49
|
||
|
||
determined by populations or variations of multiplicities, and with differ-
|
||
ential coefficients or variations of relations. Contemporary biochemistry,
|
||
or "molecular Darwinism" as Monod calls it, confirms, on the level of a
|
||
single statistical and global individual, or a simple sample, the decisive
|
||
importance of molecular populations and microbiological rates (for exam-
|
||
ple, the endlessness of the sequence composing a chain, and the chance var-
|
||
iation of a single segment in the sequence).
|
||
Challenger admitted having digressed at length but added that there was
|
||
no possible way to distinguish between the digressive and the nondi-
|
||
gressive. The point was to arrive at several conclusions concerning the
|
||
unity and diversity of a single stratum, in this case the organic stratum.
|
||
To begin with, a stratum does indeed have a unity of composition, which
|
||
is what allows it to be called a stratum: molecular materials, substantial ele-
|
||
ments, and formal relations or traits. Materials are not the same as the
|
||
unformed matter of the plane of consistency; they are already stratified,
|
||
and come from "substrata." But of course substrata should not be thought
|
||
of only as substrata: in particular, their organization is no less complex
|
||
than, nor is it inferior to, that of the strata; we should be on our guard
|
||
against any kind of ridiculous cosmic evolutionism. The materials fur-
|
||
nished by a substratum are no doubt simpler than the compounds of a stra-
|
||
tum, but their level of organization in the substratum is no lower than that
|
||
of the stratum itself. The difference between materials and substantial ele-
|
||
ments is one of organization; there is a change in organization, not an aug-
|
||
mentation. The materials furnished by the substratum constitute an
|
||
exterior milieu for the elements and compounds of the stratum under con-
|
||
sideration, but they are not exterior to the stratum. The elements and com-
|
||
pounds constitute an interior of the stratum, just as the materials
|
||
constitute an exterior o/the stratum; both belong to the stratum, the latter
|
||
because they are materials that have been furnished to the stratum and
|
||
selected for it, the former because they are formed from the materials.
|
||
Once again, this exterior and interior are relative; they exist only through
|
||
their exchanges and therefore only by virtue of the stratum responsible for
|
||
the relation between them. For example, on a crystalline stratum, the
|
||
amorphous milieu, or medium, is exterior to the seed before the crystal has
|
||
formed; the crystal forms by interiorizing and incorporating masses of
|
||
amorphous material. Conversely, the interiority of the seed of the crystal
|
||
must move out to the system's exterior, where the amorphous medium can
|
||
crystallize (the aptitude to switch over to the other form of organization).
|
||
To the point that the seed itself comes from the outside. In short, both exte-
|
||
rior and interior are interior to the stratum. The same applies to the organic
|
||
stratum: the materials furnished by the substrata are an exterior medium
|
||
constituting the famous prebiotic soup, and catalysts play the role of seed
|
||
50 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
in the formation of interior substantial elements or even compounds.
|
||
These elements and compounds both appropriate materials and exteri-
|
||
orize themselves through replication, even in the conditions of the primor-
|
||
dial soup itself. Once again, interior and exterior exchange places, and both
|
||
are interior to the organic stratum. The limit between them is the mem-
|
||
brane that regulates the exchanges and transformation in organization (in
|
||
other words, the distributions interior to the stratum) and that defines all
|
||
of the stratum's formal relations or traits (even though the situation and
|
||
role of the limit vary widely depending on the stratum, for example, the
|
||
limit of the crystal as compared to the cellular membrane). We may there-
|
||
fore use the term central layer, or central ring, for the following aggregate
|
||
comprising the unity of composition of a stratum: exterior molecular
|
||
materials, interior substantial elements, and the limit or membrane con-
|
||
veying the formal relations. There is a single abstract machine that is envel-
|
||
oped by the stratum and constitutes its unity. This is the Ecumenon, as
|
||
opposed to the Planomenon of the plane of consistency.
|
||
It would be a mistake to believe that it is possible to isolate this unitary,
|
||
central layer of the stratum, or to grasp it in itself, by regression. In the first
|
||
place, a stratum necessarily goes from layer to layer, and from the very
|
||
beginning. It already has several layers. It goes from a center to a periphery,
|
||
at the same time as the periphery reacts back upon the center to form a new
|
||
center in relation to a new periphery. Flows constantly radiate outward,
|
||
then turn back. There is an outgrowth and multiplication of intermediate
|
||
states, and this process is one of the local conditions of the central ring
|
||
(different concentrations, variations that are tolerated below a certain
|
||
threshold of identity). These intermediate states present new figures of
|
||
milieus or materials, as well as of elements and compounds. They are inter-
|
||
mediaries between the exterior milieu and the interior element, substantial
|
||
elements and their compounds, compounds and substances, and between
|
||
the different formed substances (substances of content and substances of
|
||
expression). We will use the term epistrata for these intermediaries and
|
||
superpositions, these outgrowths, these levels. Returning to our two exam-
|
||
ples, on the crystalline stratum there are many intermediaries between the
|
||
exterior milieu or material and the interior seed: a multiplicity of perfectly
|
||
discontinuous states of metastability constituting so many hierarchical
|
||
degrees. Neither is the organic stratum separable from so-called interior
|
||
milieus that are interior elements in relation to exterior materials but also
|
||
exterior elements in relation to interior substances." These internal
|
||
organic milieus are known to regulate the degree of complexity or differen-
|
||
tiation of the parts of an organism. A stratum, considered from the stand-
|
||
point of its unity of composition, therefore exists only in its substantial
|
||
epistrata, which shatter its continuity, fragment its ring, and break it down
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 51
|
||
|
||
into gradations. The central ring does not exist independently of a periph-
|
||
ery that forms a new center, reacts back upon the first center, and in turn
|
||
gives forth discontinuous epistrata.
|
||
That is not all. In addition to this new or second-degree relativity of inte-
|
||
rior and exterior, there is a whole history on the level of the membrane or
|
||
limit. To the extent that elements and compounds incorporate or appropri-
|
||
ate materials, the corresponding organisms are forced to turn to other
|
||
"more foreign and less convenient" materials that they take from still
|
||
intact masses or other organisms. The milieu assumes a third figure here: it
|
||
is no longer an interior or exterior milieu, even a relative one, nor an inter-
|
||
mediate milieu, but instead an annexed or associated milieu. Associated
|
||
milieus imply sources of energy different from alimentary materials.
|
||
Before these sources are obtained, the organism can be said to nourish
|
||
itself but not to breathe: it is in a state of suffocation.12 Obtaining an energy
|
||
source permits an increase in the number of materials that can be trans-
|
||
formed into elements and compounds. The associated milieu is thus
|
||
defined by the capture of energy sources (respiration in the most general
|
||
sense), by the discernment of materials, the sensing of their presence or
|
||
absence (perception), and by the fabrication or nonfabrication of the corre-
|
||
sponding compounds (response, reaction). That there are molecular per-
|
||
ceptions no less than molecular reactions can be seen in the economy of the
|
||
cell and the property of regulatory agents to "recognize" only one or two
|
||
kinds of chemicals in a very diverse milieu of exteriority. The development
|
||
of the associated milieus culminates in the animal worlds described by von
|
||
Uexkiill, with all their active, perceptive, and energetic characteristics.
|
||
The unforgettable associated world of the Tick, defined by its gravitational
|
||
energy of falling, its olfactory characteristic of perceiving sweat, and its
|
||
active characteristic of latching on: the tick climbs a branch and drops onto
|
||
a passing mammal it has recognized by smell, then latches onto its skin (an
|
||
associated world composed of three factors, and no more). Active and per-
|
||
ceptive characteristics are themselves something of a double pincer, a dou-
|
||
ble articulation.13
|
||
Here, the associated milieus are closely related to organic forms. An
|
||
organic form is not a simple structure but a structuration, the constitution
|
||
of an associated milieu. An animal milieu, such as the spider web, is no less
|
||
"morphogenetic" than the form of the organism. One certainly cannot say
|
||
that the milieu determines the form; but to complicate things, this does not
|
||
make the relation between form and milieu any less decisive. Since the
|
||
form depends on an autonomous code, it can only be constituted in an
|
||
associated milieu that interlaces active, perceptive, and energetic charac-
|
||
teristics in a complex fashion, in conformity with the code's requirements;
|
||
and the form can develop only through intermediary milieus that regulate
|
||
52 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
the speeds and rates of its substances; and it can experience itself only in a
|
||
milieu of exteriority that measures the comparative advantages of the asso-
|
||
ciated milieus and the differential relations of the intermediary milieus.
|
||
Milieus always act, through selection, on entire organisms, the forms of
|
||
which depend on codes those milieus sanction indirectly. Associated
|
||
milieus divide a single milieu of exteriority among themselves as a func-
|
||
tion of different forms, just as intermediate milieus divide a milieu of
|
||
exteriority among themselves as a function of the rates or degrees of a sin-
|
||
gle form. But the dividing is done differently in the two cases. In relation to
|
||
the central belt of the stratum, the intermediate strata or milieus constitute
|
||
"epistrata" piled one atop the other, and form new centers for the new
|
||
peripheries. We will apply the term "parastrata" to the second way in which
|
||
the central belt fragments into sides and "besides," and the irreducible
|
||
forms and milieus associated with them. This time, it is at the level of the
|
||
limit or membrane of the central belt that the formal relations or traits
|
||
common to all of the strata necessarily assume entirely different forms or
|
||
types of forms corresponding to the parastrata. A stratum exists only in its
|
||
epistrata and parastrata, so that in the final analysis these must be consid-
|
||
ered strata in their own right. The ideally continuous belt or ring of the
|
||
stratum—the Ecumenon defined by the identity of molecular materials,
|
||
substantial elements, and formal relations—exists only as shattered, frag-
|
||
mented into epistrata and parastrata that imply concrete machines and
|
||
their respective indexes, and constitute different molecules, specific sub-
|
||
stances, and irreducible forms.14
|
||
We may now return to the two fundamental contributions of Darwinism
|
||
and answer the question of why forms or types of forms in the parastrata
|
||
must be understood in relation to populations, and degrees of develop-
|
||
ment in the epistrata as rates or differential relations. First, parastrata
|
||
envelop the very codes upon which the forms depend, and these codes nec-
|
||
essarily apply to populations. There must already be an entire molecular
|
||
population to be coded, and the effects of the code, or a change in the code,
|
||
are evaluated in relation to a more or less molar population, depending on
|
||
the code's ability to propagate in the milieu or create for itself a new associ-
|
||
ated milieu within which the modification will be popularizable. Yes, we
|
||
must always think in terms of packs and multiplicities: a code does or does
|
||
not take hold because the coded individual belongs to a certain population,
|
||
"the population inhabiting test tubes, a flask full of water, or a mammal's
|
||
intestine." What does it mean to say that new forms and associated milieus
|
||
potentially result from a change in the code, a modification of the code, or a
|
||
variation in the parastratum? The change is obviously not due to a passage
|
||
from one preestablished form to another, in other words, a translation
|
||
from one code to another. As long as the problem was formulated in that
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 53
|
||
|
||
fashion, it remained insoluble, and one would have to agree with Cuvier
|
||
and Baer that established types of forms are irreducible and therefore do
|
||
not admit of translation or transformation. But as soon as it is recognized
|
||
that a code is inseparable from a process of decoding that is inherent to it,
|
||
the problem receives a new formulation. There is no genetics without
|
||
"genetic drift." The modern theory of mutations has clearly demonstrated
|
||
that a code, which necessarily relates to a population, has an essential mar-
|
||
gin of decoding: not only does every code have supplements capable of free
|
||
variation, but a single segment may be copied twice, the second copy left
|
||
free for variation. In addition, fragments of code may be transferred from
|
||
the cells of one species to those of another, Man and Mouse, Monkey and
|
||
Cat, by viruses or through other procedures. This involves not translation
|
||
between codes (viruses are not translators) but a singular phenomenon we
|
||
call surplus value of code, or side-communication.'5 We will have occasion
|
||
to discuss this further, for it is essential to all becomings-animal. Every
|
||
code is affected by a margin of decoding due to these supplements and sur-
|
||
plus values—supplements in the order of a multiplicity, surplus values in
|
||
the order of a rhizome. Forms in the parastrata, the parastrata themselves,
|
||
far from lying immobile and frozen upon the strata, are part of a machinic
|
||
interlock: they relate to populations, populations imply codes, and codes
|
||
fundamentally include phenomena of relative decoding that are all the
|
||
more usable, composable, and addable by virtue of being relative, always
|
||
"beside."
|
||
Forms relate to codes and processes of coding and decoding in the
|
||
parastrata; substances, being formed matters, relate to territorialities and
|
||
movements of deterritorialization and reterritorialization on the epis-
|
||
trata. In truth, the epistrata are just as inseparable from the movements
|
||
that constitute them as the parastrata are from their processes. Nomadic
|
||
waves or flows of deterritorialization go from the central layer to the
|
||
periphery, then from the new center to the new periphery, falling back to
|
||
the old center and launching forth to the new.16 The organization of the
|
||
epistrata moves in the direction of increasing deterritorialization. Physical
|
||
particles and chemical substances cross thresholds of deterritorialization
|
||
on their own stratum and between strata; these thresholds correspond to
|
||
more or less stable intermediate states, to more or less transitory valences
|
||
and existences, to engagements with this or that other body, to densities of
|
||
proximity, to more or less localizable connections. Not only are physical
|
||
particles characterized by speeds of deterritorialization—Joycean
|
||
tachyons, particles-holes, and quarks recalling the fundamental idea of the
|
||
"soup"—but a single chemical substance (sulfur or carbon, for example)
|
||
has a number of more and less deterritorialized states. The more interior
|
||
milieus an organism has on its own stratum, assuring its autonomy and
|
||
54 O 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
bringing it into a set of aleatory relations with the exterior, the more
|
||
deterritorialized it is. That is why degrees of development must be under-
|
||
stood relatively, and as a function of differential speeds, relations, and
|
||
rates. Deterritorialization must be thought of as a perfectly positive power
|
||
that has degrees and thresholds (epistrata), is always relative, and has
|
||
reterritorialization as its flipside or complement. An organism that is
|
||
deterritorialized in relation to the exterior necessarily reterritorializes on
|
||
its interior milieus. A given presumed fragment of embryo is deterrito-
|
||
rialized when it changes thresholds or gradients, but is assigned a new role
|
||
by the new surroundings. Local movements are alterations. Cellular migra-
|
||
tion, stretching, invagination, folding are examples of this. Every voyage is
|
||
intensive, and occurs in relation to thresholds of intensity between which it
|
||
evolves or that it crosses. One travels by intensity; displacements and
|
||
spatial figures depend on intensive thresholds of nomadic deterritoriali-
|
||
zation (and thus on differential relations) that simultaneously define com-
|
||
plementary, sedentary reterritorializations. Every stratum operates this
|
||
way: by grasping in its pincers a maximum number of intensities or inten-
|
||
sive particles over which it spreads its forms and substances, constituting
|
||
determinate gradients and thresholds of resonance (deterritorialization on
|
||
a stratum always occurs in relation to a complementary reterrito-
|
||
rialization).17
|
||
As long as preestablished forms were compared to predetermined
|
||
degrees, all one could do was affirm their irreducibility, and there was no
|
||
way of judging possible communication between the two factors. But we
|
||
see now that forms depend on codes in the parastrata and plunge into pro-
|
||
cesses of decoding or drift and that degrees themselves are caught up in
|
||
movements of intensive territorialization and reterritorialization. There is
|
||
no simple correspondence between codes and territorialities on the one
|
||
hand and decodings and deterritorialization on the other: on the contrary,
|
||
a code may be a deterritorialization and a reterritorialization a decoding.
|
||
Wide gaps separate code and territoriality. The two factors nevertheless
|
||
have the same "subject" in a stratum: it is populations that are deter-
|
||
ritorialized and reterritorialized, and also coded and decoded. In addition,
|
||
these factors communicate or interlace in the milieus.
|
||
On the one hand, modifications of a code have an aleatory cause in the
|
||
milieu of exteriority, and it is their effects on the interior milieus, their
|
||
compatibility with them, that decide whether they will be popularized.
|
||
Deterritorializations and reterritorializations do not bring about the mod-
|
||
ifications; they do, however, strictly determine their selection. On the other
|
||
hand, every modification has an associated milieu that in turn entails a
|
||
certain deterritorialization in relation to the milieu of exteriority and a cer-
|
||
tain reterritorialization on intermediate or interior milieus. Perceptions
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 55
|
||
|
||
and actions in an associated milieu, even those on a molecular level, con-
|
||
struct or produce territorial signs (indexes). This is especially true of an ani-
|
||
mal world, which is constituted, marked off by signs that divide it into
|
||
zones (of shelter, hunting, neutrality, etc.), mobilize special organs, and
|
||
correspond to fragments of code; this is so even at the margin of decoding
|
||
inherent in the code. Even the domain of learning is defined by the code, or
|
||
prescribed by it. But indexes or territorial signs are inseparable from a dou-
|
||
ble movement. Since the associated milieu always confronts a milieu of
|
||
exteriority with which the animal is engaged and in which it takes neces-
|
||
sary risks, a line of flight must be preserved to enable the animal to regain
|
||
its associated milieu when danger appears (for example, the bull's line of
|
||
flight in the arena, which it uses to regain the turf it has chosen).18 A second
|
||
kind of line of flight arises when the associated milieu is rocked by blows
|
||
from the exterior, forcing the animal to abandon it and strike up an associa-
|
||
tion with new portions of exteriority, this time leaning on its interior
|
||
milieus like fragile crutches. When the seas dried, the primitive Fish left its
|
||
associated milieu to explore land, forced to "stand on its own legs," now
|
||
carrying water only on the inside, in the amniotic membranes protecting
|
||
the embryo. In one way or the other, the animal is more a fleer than a
|
||
fighter, but its flights are also conquests, creations. Territorialities, then,
|
||
are shot through with lines of flight testifying to the presence within them
|
||
of movements of deterritorialization and reterritorialization. In a certain
|
||
sense, they are secondary. They would be nothing without these move-
|
||
ments that deposit them. In short, the epistrata and parastrata are continu-
|
||
ally moving, sliding, shifting, and changing on the Ecumenon or unity of
|
||
composition of a stratum; some are swept away by lines of flight and move-
|
||
ments of deterritorialization, others by processes of decoding or drift, but
|
||
they all communicate at the intersection of the milieus. The strata are con-
|
||
tinually being shaken by phenomena of cracking and rupture, either at the
|
||
level of the substrata that furnish the materials (a prebiotic soup, a
|
||
prechemical soup ...), at the level of the accumulating epistrata, or at the
|
||
level of the abutting parastrata: everywhere there arise simultaneous accel-
|
||
erations and blockages, comparative speeds, differences in deterrito-
|
||
rialization creating relative fields of reterritorialization.
|
||
These relative movements should most assuredly not be confused with
|
||
the possibility of absolute deterritorialization, an absolute line of flight,
|
||
absolute drift. The former are stratic or interstratic, whereas the latter con-
|
||
cern the plane of consistency and its destratification (its "combustion," as
|
||
Geoffrey would say). There is no doubt that mad physical particles crash
|
||
through the strata as they accelerate, leaving minimal trace of their pas-
|
||
sage, escaping spatiotemporal and even existential coordinates as they
|
||
tend toward a state of absolute deterritorialization, the state of unformed
|
||
56 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
matter on the plane of consistency. In a certain sense, the acceleration of
|
||
relative deterritorializations reaches the sound barrier: if the particles
|
||
bounce off this wall, or allow themselves to be captured by black holes, they
|
||
fall back onto the strata, into the strata's relations and milieus; but if they
|
||
cross the barrier they reach the unformed, destratified element of the plane
|
||
of consistency. We may even say the the abstract machines that emit and
|
||
combine particles have two very different modes of existence: the Ecumenon
|
||
and the Planomenon. Either the abstract machines remain prisoner to
|
||
stratifications, are enveloped in a certain specific stratum whose program
|
||
or unity of composition they define (the abstract Animal, the abstract
|
||
chemical Body, Energy in itself) and whose movements of relative
|
||
deterritorialization they regulate, Or, on the contrary, the abstract machine
|
||
cuts across all stratifications, develops alone and in its own right on the
|
||
plane of consistency whose diagram it constitutes, the same machine at
|
||
work in astrophysics and in microphysics, in the natural and in the artifi-
|
||
cial, piloting flows of absolute deterritorialization (in no sense, of course, is
|
||
unformed matter chaos of any kind). But this presentation is still too
|
||
simplified.
|
||
First, one does not go from the relative to the absolute simply by acceler-
|
||
ation, even though increases in speed tend to have this comparative and
|
||
global result. Absolute deterritorialization is not defined as a giant acceler-
|
||
ator; its absoluteness does not hinge on how fast it goes. It is actually possi-
|
||
ble to reach the absolute by way of phenomena of relative slowness or delay.
|
||
Retarded development is an example. What qualifies a deterritorialization
|
||
is not its speed (some are very slow) but its nature, whether it constitutes
|
||
epistrata and parastrata and proceeds by articulated segments or, on the
|
||
contrary, jumps from one singularity to another following a nondecom-
|
||
posable, nonsegmentary line drawing a metastratum of the plane of consis-
|
||
tency. Second, under no circumstances must it be thought that absolute
|
||
deterritorialization comes suddenly of afterward, is in excess or beyond.
|
||
That would preclude any understanding of why the strata themselves are
|
||
animated by movements of relative deterritorialization and decoding that
|
||
are not like accidents occurring on them. In fact, what is primary is an abso-
|
||
lute deterritorialization an absolute line of flight, however complex or
|
||
multiple—that of the plane of consistency or body without organs (the
|
||
Earth, the absolutely deterritorialized). This absolute deterritorialization
|
||
becomes relative only after stratification occurs on that plane or body: It
|
||
is the strata that are always residue, not the opposite. The question is not
|
||
how something manages to leave the strata by how things get into them
|
||
in the first place. There is a perpetual immanence of absolute deterritori-
|
||
alization within relative deterritorialization; and the machinic assem-
|
||
blages between strata that regulate the differential relations and relative
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 57
|
||
|
||
movements also have cutting edges of deterritorialization oriented toward
|
||
the absolute. The plane of consistency is always immanent to the strata; the
|
||
two states of the abstract machine always coexist as two different states of
|
||
intensities.
|
||
|
||
Most of the audience had left (the first to go were the Marinetians with
|
||
their double articulation, followed by the Hjelmslevians with their content
|
||
and expression, and the biologists with their proteins and nucleic acids).
|
||
The only ones left were the mathematicians, accustomed to other follies,
|
||
along with a few astrologers, archaeologists, and scattered individuals.
|
||
Challenger, moreover, had changed since the beginning of his talk. His
|
||
voice had become hoarser, broken occasionally by an apish cough. His
|
||
dream was not so much to give a lecture to humans as to provide a program
|
||
for pure computers. Or else he was dreaming of an axiomatic, for axi-
|
||
omatics deals essentially with stratification. Challenger was addressing
|
||
himself to memory only. Now that we had discussed what was constant and
|
||
what varied in a stratum from the standpoint of substances and forms, the
|
||
question remaining to be answered was what varied between strata from
|
||
the standpoint of content and expression. For if it is true that there is
|
||
always a real distinction constitutive of double articulation, a reciprocal
|
||
presupposition of content and expression, then what varies from one stra-
|
||
tum to another is the nature of this real distinction, and the nature and
|
||
respective positions of the terms distinguished. Let us start with a certain
|
||
group of strata that can be characterized summarily as follows: on these
|
||
strata, content (form and substance) is molecular, and expression (form
|
||
and substance) is molar. The difference between the two is primarily one of
|
||
order of magnitude or scale. Resonance, or the communication occurring
|
||
between the two independent orders, is what institutes the stratified sys-
|
||
tem. The molecular content of that system has its own form corresponding
|
||
to the distribution of elemental masses and the action of one molecule
|
||
upon another; similarly, expression has a form manifesting the statistical
|
||
aggregate and state of equilibrium existing on the macroscopic level.
|
||
Expression is like an "operation of amplifying structuration carrying the
|
||
active properties of the originally microphysical discontinuity to the
|
||
macrophysical level."
|
||
We took as our point of departure cases of this kind on the geological
|
||
stratum, the crystalline stratum, and physicochemical strata, wherever the
|
||
molar can be said to express microscopic molecular interactions ("the crys-
|
||
tal is the macroscopic expression of a microscopic structure"; the "crystal-
|
||
line form expresses certain atomic or molecular characteristics of the
|
||
constituent chemical categories"). Of course, this still leaves numerous
|
||
possibilities, depending on the number and nature of the intermediate
|
||
58 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
states, and also on the impact of exterior forces on the formation of expres-
|
||
sion. There may be a greater or lesser number of intermediate states
|
||
between the molecular and the molar; there may be a greater or lesser num-
|
||
ber of exterior forces or organizing centers participating in the molar form.
|
||
Doubtless, these two factors are in an inverse relation to each other and
|
||
indicate limit-cases. For example, the molar form of expression may be of
|
||
the "mold" type, mobilizing a maximum of exterior forces; or it may be of
|
||
the "modulation" type, bringing into play only a minimum number of
|
||
them. Even in the case of the mold, however, there are nearly instantane-
|
||
ous, interior intermediate states between the molecular content that
|
||
assumes its own specific forms and the determinate molar expression of
|
||
the outside by the form of the mold. Conversely, even when the multiplica-
|
||
tion and temporalization of the intermediate states testify to the endo-
|
||
genous character of the molar form (as with crystals), a minimum of
|
||
exterior forces still intervene in each of the stages.19 We must therefore say
|
||
that the relative independence of content and expression, the real distinc-
|
||
tion between molecular content and molar expression with their respective
|
||
forms, has a special status enjoying a certain amount of latitude between
|
||
the limit-cases.
|
||
Since strata are judgments of God, one should not hesitate to apply all
|
||
the subtleties of medieval Scholasticism and theology. There is a real dis-
|
||
tinction between content and expression because the corresponding forms
|
||
are effectively distinct in the "thing" itself, and not only in the mind of the
|
||
observer. But this real distinction is quite special; it is only formal since the
|
||
two forms compose or shape a single thing, a single stratified subject. Vari-
|
||
ous examples of formal distinction can be cited: between scales or orders of
|
||
magnitude (as between a map and its model; or, in a different fashion,
|
||
between the micro- and macrophysical levels, as in the parable of
|
||
Eddington's two offices); between the various states or formal reasons
|
||
through which a thing passes; between the thing in one form, and as
|
||
affected by a possibly exterior causality giving it a different form; and so
|
||
forth. (There is a proliferation of distinct forms because, in addition to
|
||
content and expression each having its own forms, intermediate states
|
||
introduce forms of expression proper to content and forms of content
|
||
proper to expression.)
|
||
As diverse and real as formal distinctions are, on the organic stratum the
|
||
very nature of the distinction changes. As a result, the entire distribution
|
||
between content and expression is different. The organic stratum never-
|
||
theless preserves, and even amplifies, the relation between the molecular
|
||
and the molar, with all kinds of intermediate states. We saw this in the case
|
||
of morphogenesis, where double articulation is inseparable from a com-
|
||
munication between two orders of magnitude. The same thing applies to
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 59
|
||
|
||
cellular chemistry. But the organic stratum has a unique character that
|
||
must account for the amplifications. In a preceding discussion, expression
|
||
was dependent upon the expressed molecular content in all directions and
|
||
in every dimension and had independence only to the extent that it
|
||
appealed to a higher order of magnitude and to exterior forces: The real dis-
|
||
tinction was between forms, but forms belonging to the same aggregate, the
|
||
same thing or subject. Now, however, expression becomes independent in its
|
||
own right, in other words, autonomous. Before, the coding of a stratum was
|
||
coextensive with that stratum; on the organic stratum, on the other hand, it
|
||
takes place on an autonomous and independent line that detaches as much
|
||
as possible from the second and third dimensions. Expression ceases to be
|
||
voluminous or superficial, becoming linear, unidimensional (even in its
|
||
segmentarity). The essential thing is the linearity of the nucleic sequence.20
|
||
The real distinction between content and expression, therefore, is not sim-
|
||
ply formal. It is strictly speaking real, and passes into the molecular, with-
|
||
out regard to order of magnitude. It is between two classes of molecules,
|
||
nucleic acids of expression and proteins of content, nucleic elements or
|
||
nucleotides and protein elements or amino acids. Both expression and
|
||
content are now molecular and molar. The distinction no longer concerns a
|
||
single aggregate or subject; linearity takes us further in the direction of flat
|
||
multiplicities, rather than unity. Expression involves nucleotides and
|
||
nucleic acids as well as molecules that, in their substance and form, are
|
||
entirely independent not only of molecules of content but of any directed
|
||
action in the exterior milieu. Thus invariance is a characteristic of certain
|
||
molecules and is not found exclusively on the molar scale. Conversely, pro-
|
||
teins, in their substance and form of content, are equally independent of
|
||
nucleotides: the only thing univocally determined is that one amino acid
|
||
rather than another corresponds to a sequence of three nucleotides.2' What
|
||
the linear form of expression determines is therefore a derivative form of
|
||
expression, one that is relative to content and that, through a folding back
|
||
upon itself of the protein sequence of the amino acids, finally yields the
|
||
characteristic three-dimensional structures. In short, what is specific to the
|
||
organic stratum is this alignment of expression, this exhaustion or detach-
|
||
ment of a line of expression, this reduction of form and substance of expres-
|
||
sion to a unidimensional line, guaranteeing their reciprocal independence
|
||
from content without having to account for orders of magnitude.
|
||
This has many consequences. The new configuration of expression and
|
||
content conditions not only the organism's power to reproduce but also its
|
||
power to deterritorialize or accelerate deterritorialization. The alignment
|
||
of the code or linearity of the nucleic sequence in fact marks a threshold of
|
||
deterritorialization of the "sign" that gives it a new ability to be copied and
|
||
makes the organism more deterritorialized than a crystal: only something
|
||
60 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
deterritorialized is capable of reproducing itself. When content and
|
||
expression are divided along the lines of the molecular and the molar, sub-
|
||
stances move from state to state, from the preceding state to the following
|
||
state, or from layer to layer, from an already constituted layer to a layer in
|
||
the process of forming, while forms install themselves at the limit between
|
||
the last layer or last state and the exterior milieu. Thus the stratum devel-
|
||
ops into epistrata and parastrata; this is accomplished through a set of
|
||
inductions from layer to layer and state to state, or at the limit. A crystal dis-
|
||
plays this process in its pure state, since its form expands in all directions,
|
||
but always as a function of the surface layer of the substance, which can be
|
||
emptied of most of its interior without interfering with the growth. It is the
|
||
crystal's subjugation to three-dimensionality, in other words its index of
|
||
territoriality, that makes the structure incapable of formally reproducing
|
||
and expressing itself; only the accessible surface can reproduce itself, since
|
||
it is the only deterritorializable part. On the contrary, the detachment of a
|
||
pure line of expression on the organic stratum makes it possible for the
|
||
organism to attain a much higher threshold of deterritorialization, gives it
|
||
a mechanism of reproduction covering all the details of its complex spatial
|
||
structure, and enables it to put all of its interior layers "topologically in
|
||
contact" with the exterior, or rather with the polarized limit (hence the spe-
|
||
cial role of the living membrane). The development of the stratum into
|
||
epistrata and parastrata occurs not through simple inductions but through
|
||
transductlons that account for the amplification of the resonance between
|
||
the molecular and the molar, independently of order of magnitude; for the
|
||
functional efficacy of the interior substances, independently of distance;
|
||
and for the possibility of a proliferation and even interlacing of forms,
|
||
independently of codes (surplus values of code or phenomena of trans-
|
||
coding or aparallel evolution).22
|
||
There is a third major grouping of strata, defined less by a human
|
||
essence than, once again, by a new distribution of content and expression.
|
||
Form of content becomes "alloplastic" rather than "homoplastic"; in other
|
||
words, it brings about modifications in the external world. Form of expres-
|
||
sion becomes linguistic rather than genetic; in other words, it operates with
|
||
symbols that are comprehensible, transmittable, and modifiable from out-
|
||
side. What some call the properties of human beings—technology and
|
||
language, tool and symbol, free hand and supple larynx, "gesture and
|
||
speech"—are in fact properties of this new distribution. It would be diffi-
|
||
cult to maintain that the emergence of human beings marked the absolute
|
||
origin of this distribution. Leroi-Gourhan's analyses give us an under-
|
||
standing of how contents came to be linked with the hand-tool couple and
|
||
expressions with the face-language couple.23 In this context, the hand must
|
||
not be thought of simply as an organ but instead as a coding (the digital
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 61
|
||
|
||
code), a dynamic structuration, a dynamic formation (the manual form, or
|
||
manual formal traits). The hand as a general form of content is extended in
|
||
tools, which are themselves active forms implying substances, or formed
|
||
matters; finally, products are formed matters, or substances, which in turn
|
||
serve as tools. Whereas manual formal traits constitute the unity of compo-
|
||
sition of the stratum, the forms and substances of tools and products are
|
||
organized into parastrata and epistrata that themselves function as verita-
|
||
ble strata and mark discontinuities, breakages, communications and diffu-
|
||
sions, nomadisms and sedentarities, multiple thresholds and speeds of
|
||
relative deterritorialization in human populations. For with the hand as a
|
||
formal trait or general form of content a major threshold of deterri-
|
||
torialization is reached and opens, an accelerator that in itself permits a
|
||
shifting interplay of comparative deterritorializations and reterritorial-
|
||
izations—what makes this acceleration possible is, precisely, phenomena
|
||
of "retarded development" in the organic substrata. Not only is the hand a
|
||
deterritorialized front paw; the hand thus freed is itself deterritorialized in
|
||
relation to the grasping and locomotive hand of the monkey. The synergis-
|
||
tic deterritorializations of other organs (for example, the foot) must be
|
||
taken into account. So must correlative deterritorializations of the milieu:
|
||
the steppe as an associated milieu more deterritorialized than the forest,
|
||
exerting a selective pressure of deterritorialization upon the body and tech-
|
||
nology (it was on the steppe, not in the forest, that the hand was able to
|
||
appear as a free form, and fire as a technologically formable matter).
|
||
Finally, complementary reterritorializations must be taken into account
|
||
(the foot as a compensatory reterritorialization for the hand, also
|
||
occurring on the steppe). Maps should be made of these things, organic,
|
||
ecological, and technological maps one can lay out on the plane of
|
||
consistency.
|
||
On the other hand, language becomes the new form of expression, or
|
||
rather the set of formal traits defining the new expression in operation
|
||
throughout the stratum. Just as manual traits exist only in forms and
|
||
formed matters that shatter their continuity and determine the distribu-
|
||
tion of their effects, formal traits of expression exist only in a diversity of
|
||
formal languages and imply one or several formable substances. The sub-
|
||
stance involved is fundamentally vocal substance, which brings into play
|
||
various organic elements: not only the larynx, but the mouth and lips, and
|
||
the overall motricity of the face. Once again, a whole intensive map must
|
||
be accounted for: the mouth as a deterritorialization of the snout (the
|
||
whole "conflict between the mouth and the brain," as Perrier called it); the
|
||
lips as a deterritorialization of the mouth (only humans have lips, in other
|
||
words, an outward curling of the interior mucous membranes; only human
|
||
females have breasts, in other words, deterritorialized mammary glands:
|
||
62 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
the extended nursing period advantageous for language learning is accom-
|
||
panied by a complementary reterritorialization of the lips on the breasts,
|
||
and the breasts on the lips). What a curious deterritorialization, filling
|
||
one's mouth with words instead of food and noises. The steppe, once more,
|
||
seems to have exerted strong pressures of selection: the "supple larynx" is a
|
||
development corresponding to the free hand and could have arisen only in
|
||
a deforested milieu where it is no longer necessary to have gigantic laryn-
|
||
geal sacks in order for one's cries to be heard above the constant din of the
|
||
forest. To articulate, to speak, is to speak softly. Everyone knows that lum-
|
||
berjacks rarely talk.24 Physiological, acoustic, and vocal substance are not
|
||
the only things that undergo all these deterritorializations. The form of
|
||
expression, as language, also crosses a threshold.
|
||
Vocal signs have temporal linearity, and it is this superlinearity that con-
|
||
stitutes their specific deterritorialization and differentiates them from
|
||
genetic linearity. Genetic linearity is above all spatial, even though its seg-
|
||
ments are constructed and reproduced in succession; thus at this level it
|
||
does not require effective overcoding of any kind, only phenomena of end-
|
||
to-end connection, local regulations, and partial interactions (overcoding
|
||
takes place only at the level of integrations implying different orders of
|
||
magnitude). That is why Jacob is reluctant to compare the genetic code to a
|
||
language; in fact, the genetic code has neither emitter, receiver, compre-
|
||
hension, nor translation, only redundancies and surplus values.25 The tem-
|
||
poral linearity of language expression relates not only to a succession but to
|
||
a formal synthesis of succession in which time constitutes a process of lin-
|
||
ear overcoding and engenders a phenomenon unknown on the other strata:
|
||
translation, translatability, as opposed to the previous inductions and
|
||
transductions. Translation should not be understood simply as the ability
|
||
of one language to "represent" in some way the givens of another language,
|
||
but beyond that as the ability of language, with its own givens on its own
|
||
stratum, to represent all the other strata and thus achieve a scientific con-
|
||
ception of the world. The scientific world (Welt, as opposed to the Umwelt
|
||
of the animal) is the translation of all of the flows, particles, codes, and ter-
|
||
ritorialities of the other strata into a sufficiently deterritorialized system of
|
||
signs, in other words, into an overcoding specific to language. This prop-
|
||
erty of overcoding or superlinearity explains why, in language, not only is
|
||
expression independent of content, but form of expression is independent
|
||
of substance: translation is possible because the same form can pass from
|
||
one substance to another, which is not the case for the genetic code, for
|
||
example, between RNA and DNA chains. We will see later on how this situ-
|
||
ation gives rise to certain imperialist pretentions on behalf of language,
|
||
which are naively expressed in such formulas as: "Every semiology of a
|
||
nonlinguistic system must use the medium of language... .Language is the
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 63
|
||
|
||
interpreter of all the other systems, linguistic and nonlinguistic." This
|
||
amounts to defining an abstract character of language and then saying that
|
||
the other strata can share in that character only by being spoken in lan-
|
||
guage. That is stating the obvious. More positively, it must be noted that
|
||
the immanence within language of universal translation means that its
|
||
epistrata and parastrata, with respect to superpositions, diffusions, com-
|
||
munications, and abutments, operate in an entirely different manner than
|
||
those of other strata: all human movements, even the most violent, imply
|
||
translations.
|
||
We have to hurry, Challenger said, we're being rushed by the line of time
|
||
on this third stratum. So we have a new organization of content and
|
||
expression, each with its own forms and substances: technological content,
|
||
semiotic or symbolic expression. Content should be understood not sim-
|
||
ply as the hand and tools but as a technical social machine that preexists
|
||
them and constitutes states of force or formations of power. Expression
|
||
should be understood not simply as the face and language, or individual
|
||
languages, but as a semiotic collective machine that preexists them and
|
||
constitutes regimes of signs. A formation of power is much more than a
|
||
tool; a regime of signs is much more than a language. Rather, they act as
|
||
determining and selective agents, as much in the constitution of languages
|
||
and tools as in their usages and mutual or respective diffusions and com-
|
||
munications. The third stratum sees the emergence of Machines that are
|
||
fully a part of that stratum but at the same time rear up and stretch their
|
||
pincers out in all directions at all the other strata. Is this not like an interme-
|
||
diate state between the two states of the abstract Machine"?—the state in
|
||
which it remains enveloped in a corresponding stratum (ecumenon), and
|
||
the state in which it develops in its own right on the destratified plane of
|
||
consistency (planomenon). The abstract machine begins to unfold, to
|
||
stand to full height, producing an illusion exceeding all strata, even though
|
||
the machine itself still belongs to a determinate stratum. This is, obviously,
|
||
the illusion constitutive of man (who does man think he is?). This illusion
|
||
derives from the overcoding immanent to language itself. But what is not
|
||
illusory are the new distributions between content and expression: techno-
|
||
logical content characterized by the hand-tool relation and, at a deeper
|
||
level, tied to a social Machine and formations of power; symbolic expres-
|
||
sion characterized by face-language relations and, at a deeper level, tied to
|
||
a semiotic Machine and regimes of signs. On both sides, the epistrata and
|
||
parastrata, the superposed degrees and abutting forms, attain more than
|
||
ever before the status of autonomous strata in their own right. In cases
|
||
where we can discern two different regimes of signs or two different forma-
|
||
tions of power, we shall say that they are in fact two different strata in
|
||
human populations.
|
||
64 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
What precisely is the relation now between content and expression, and
|
||
what type of distinction is there between them? It's all in the head. Yet
|
||
never was a distinction more real. What we are trying to say is that there is
|
||
indeed one exterior milieu for the entire stratum, permeating the entire
|
||
stratum: the cerebral-nervous milieu. It comes from the organic substra-
|
||
tum, but of course that substratum does not merely play the role of a sub-
|
||
stratum or passive support. It is no less complex in organization. Rather, it
|
||
constitutes the prehuman soup immersing us. Our hands and faces are
|
||
immersed in it. The brain is a population, a set of tribes tending toward two
|
||
poles. In Leroi-Gourhan's analyses of the constitution of these two poles in
|
||
the soup—one of which depends on the actions of the face, the other on the
|
||
hand—their correlation or relativity does not preclude a real distinction
|
||
between them; quite the contrary, it entails one, as the reciprocal presuppo-
|
||
sition of two articulations, the manual articulation of content and the
|
||
facial articulation of expression. And the distinction is not simply real, as
|
||
between molecules, things, or subjects; it has become essential (as they
|
||
used to say in the Middle Ages), as between attributes, genres of being, or
|
||
irreducible categories: things and words. Yet we find that the most general
|
||
of movements, the one by which each of the distinct articulations is already
|
||
double in its own right, carries over onto this level; certain formal elements
|
||
of content play the role of expression in relation to content proper, and cer-
|
||
tain formal elements of expression play the role of content in relation to
|
||
expression proper. In the first case, Leroi-Gourhan shows how the hand
|
||
creates a whole world of symbols, a whole pluridimensional language, not
|
||
to be confused with unilinear verbal language, which constitutes a radiat-
|
||
ing expression specific to content (he sees this as the origin of writing).26
|
||
The second case is clearly displayed in the double articulation specific to
|
||
language itself, since phonemes form a radiating content specific to the
|
||
expression of monemes as linear significant segments (it is only under
|
||
these conditions that double articulation as a general characteristic of
|
||
strata has the linguistic meaning Martinet attributes to it). Our discussion
|
||
of the relations between content and expression, the real distinction
|
||
between them, and the variations of those relations and that distinction on
|
||
the major types of strata, is now provisionally complete.
|
||
Challenger wanted to go faster and faster. No one was left, but he went on
|
||
anyway. The change in his voice, and in his appearance, was growing more
|
||
and more pronounced. Something animalistic in him had begun to speak
|
||
when he started talking about human beings. You still couldn't put your
|
||
finger on it, but Challenger seemed to be deterritorializing on the spot. He
|
||
still had three problems he wanted to discuss. The first seemed primarily
|
||
terminological: Under what circumstances may we speak of signs? Should
|
||
we say they are everywhere on all the strata and that there is a sign when-
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 65
|
||
|
||
ever there is a form of expression? We may summarily distinguish three
|
||
kinds of signs: indexes (territorial signs), symbols (deterritorialized signs),
|
||
and icons (signs ofreterritorialization). Should we say that there are signs
|
||
on all the strata, under the pretext that every stratum includes territoriali-
|
||
ties and movements of deterritorialization and reterritorialization? This
|
||
kind of expansive method is very dangerous, because it lays the ground-
|
||
work for or reinforces the imperialism of language, if only by relying on its
|
||
function as universal translator or interpreter. It is obvious that there is no
|
||
system of signs common to all strata, not even in the form of a semiotic
|
||
"chora" theoretically prior to symbolization.27 It would appear that we
|
||
may accurately speak of signs only when there is a distinction between
|
||
forms of expression and forms of content that is not only real but also cate-
|
||
gorical. Under these conditions, there is a semiotic system on the corre-
|
||
sponding stratum because the abstract machine has precisely that fully
|
||
erect posture that permits it to "write," in other words, to treat language
|
||
and extract a regime of signs from it. But before it reaches that point, in
|
||
so-called natural codings, the abstract machine remains enveloped in the
|
||
strata: It does not write in any way and has no margin of latitude allowing it
|
||
to recognize something as a sign (except in the strictly territorial sense of
|
||
animal signs). After that point, the abstract machine develops on the plane
|
||
of consistency and no longer has any way of making a categorical distinc-
|
||
tion between signs and particles; for example, it writes, but flush with the
|
||
real, it inscribes directly upon the plane of consistency. It therefore seems
|
||
reasonable to reserve the word "sign" in the strict sense for the last group of
|
||
strata. This terminological discussion would be entirely without interest if
|
||
it did not bring us to yet another danger: not the imperialism of language
|
||
affecting all of the strata, but the imperialism of the signifier affecting lan-
|
||
guage itself, affecting all regimes of signs and the entire expanse of the
|
||
strata upon which they are located. The question here is not whether there
|
||
are signs on every stratum but whether all signs are signifiers, whether all
|
||
signs are endowed with signifiance, whether the semiotic of signs is neces-
|
||
sarily linked to a semiology of the signifier. Those who take this route may
|
||
even be led to forgo the notion of the sign, for the primacy of the signifier
|
||
over language guarantees the primacy of language over all of the strata even
|
||
more effectively than the simple expansion of the sign in all directions.
|
||
What we are saying is that the illusion specific to this posture of the abstract
|
||
Machine, the illusion that one can grasp and shuffle all the strata between
|
||
one's pincers, can be better secured through the erection of the signifier
|
||
than through the extension of the sign (thanks to signifiance, language can
|
||
claim to be in direct contact with the strata without having to go through
|
||
the supposed signs on each one). But we're still going in the same circle,
|
||
we're still spreading the same canker.
|
||
66 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
The linguistic relation between the signifier and signified has, of course,
|
||
been conceived in many different ways. It has been said that they are
|
||
arbitrary; that they are as necessary to each other as the two sides of the
|
||
same leaf; that they correspond term by term, or else globally; and that they
|
||
are so ambivalent as to be indistinguishable. In any event, the signified is
|
||
thought not to exist outside of its relationship with signifier, and the ulti-
|
||
mate signified is the very existence of the signifier, extrapolated beyond the
|
||
sign. There is only one thing that can be said about the signifier: it is Redun-
|
||
dancy, it is the Redundant. Hence its incredible despotism, and its success.
|
||
Theories of arbitrariness, necessity, term-by-term or global correspon-
|
||
dence, and ambivalence serve the same cause: the reduction of expression
|
||
to the signifier. Yet forms of content and forms of expression are highly
|
||
relative, always in a state of reciprocal presupposition. The relations
|
||
between their respective segments are biunivocal, exterior, and "de-
|
||
formed." There is never conformity between the two, or from one to the
|
||
other. There is always real independence and a real distinction; even to fit
|
||
the forms together, and to determine the relations between them, requires a
|
||
specific, variable assemblage. None of these characteristics applies to the
|
||
signifier-signified relation, even though some seem to coincide with it par-
|
||
tially and accidentally. Overall, these characteristics stand in radical oppo-
|
||
sition to the scenario of the signifier. A form of content is not a signified,
|
||
any more than a form of expression is a signifier.28 This is true for all the
|
||
strata, including those on which language plays a role.
|
||
Signifier enthusiasts take an oversimplified situation as their implicit
|
||
model: word and thing. From the word they extract the signifier, and from
|
||
the thing a signified in conformity with the word, and therefore subjugated
|
||
to the signifier. They operate in a sphere interior to and homogeneous with
|
||
language. Let us follow Foucault in his exemplary analysis, which, though
|
||
it seems not to be, is eminently concerned with linguistics. Take a thing like
|
||
the prison: the prison is a form, the "prison-form"; it is a form of content on
|
||
a stratum and is related to other forms of content (school, barracks, hospi-
|
||
tal, factory). This thing or form does not refer back to the word "prison"
|
||
but to entirely different words and concepts, such as "delinquent" and
|
||
"delinquency," which express a new way of classifying, stating, translating,
|
||
and even committing criminal acts. "Delinquency" is the form of expres-
|
||
sion in reciprocal presupposition with the form of content "prison." Delin-
|
||
quency is in no way a signifier, even a juridical signifier, the signified of
|
||
which would be the prison. That would flatten the entire analysis. More-
|
||
over, the form of expression is reducible not to words but to a set of state-
|
||
ments arising in the social field considered as a stratum (that is what a
|
||
regime of signs is). The form of content is reducible not to a thing but to a
|
||
complex state of things as a formation of power (architecture, regimenta-
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 67
|
||
|
||
tion, etc.). We could say that there are two constantly intersecting multipli-
|
||
cities, "discursive multiplicities" of expression and "nondiscursive multi-
|
||
plicities" of content. It is even more complex than that because the prison
|
||
as a form of content has a relative expression all its own; there are all kinds
|
||
of statements specific to it that do not necessarily coincide with the state-
|
||
ments of delinquency. Conversely, delinquency as a form of expression has
|
||
an autonomous content all its own, since delinquency expresses not only a
|
||
new way of evaluating crimes but a new way of committing them. Form of
|
||
content and form of expression, prison and delinquency: each has its own
|
||
history, microhistory, segments. At most, along with other contents and
|
||
expressions, they imply a shared state of the abstract Machine acting not at
|
||
all as a signifier but as a kind of diagram (a single abstract machine for the
|
||
prison and the school and the barracks and the hospital and the fac-
|
||
tory ...). Fitting the two types of forms together, segments of content and
|
||
segments of expression, requires a whole double-pincered, or rather
|
||
double-headed, concrete assemblage taking their real distinction into
|
||
account. It requires a whole organization articulating formations of power
|
||
and regimes of signs, and operating on the molecular level (societies char-
|
||
acterized by what Foucault calls disciplinary power).29 In short, we should
|
||
never oppose words to things that supposedly correspond to them, nor
|
||
signifiers to signifieds that are supposedly in conformity with them. What
|
||
should be opposed are distinct formalizations, in a state of unstable equi-
|
||
librium or reciprocal presupposition. "// is in vain that we say what we see;
|
||
what we see never resides in what we say."30 As in school: there is not just one
|
||
writing lesson, that of the great redundant Signifier for any and all
|
||
signifieds. There are two distinct formalizations in reciprocal presupposi-
|
||
tion and constituting a double-pincer: the formalization of expression in
|
||
the reading and writing lesson (with its own relative contents), and the
|
||
formalization of content in the lesson of things (with their own relative
|
||
expressions). We are never signifier or signified. We are stratified.
|
||
The preferred method would be severely restrictive, as opposed to the
|
||
expansive method that places signs on all strata or signifier in all signs
|
||
(although at the limit it may forgo signs entirely). First, there exist forms of
|
||
expression without signs (for example, the genetic code has nothing to do
|
||
with a language). It is only under certain conditions that strata can be said
|
||
to include signs; signs cannot be equated with language in general but are
|
||
defined by regimes of statements that are so many real usages or functions
|
||
of language. Then why retain the word sign for these regimes, which forma-
|
||
lize an expression without designating or signifying the simultaneous con-
|
||
tents, which are formalized in a different way? Signs are not signs of a thing;
|
||
they are signs of deterritorialization and reterritorialization, they mark a
|
||
certain threshold crossed in the course of these movements, and it is for
|
||
68 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
this reason that the word should be retained (as we have seen, this applies
|
||
even to animal "signs").
|
||
Next, if we consider regimes of signs using this restrictive definition, we
|
||
see that they are not, or not necessarily, signifiers. Just as signs designate
|
||
only a certain formalization of expression in a determinate group of strata,
|
||
signifiance itself designates only one specific regime among a number of
|
||
regimes existing in that particular formalization. Just as there are ase-
|
||
miotic expressions, or expressions without signs, there are asemiological
|
||
regimes of signs, asignifying signs, both on the strata and on the plane of
|
||
consistency. The most that can be said of signifiance is that it characterizes
|
||
one regime, which is not even the most interesting or modern or contempo-
|
||
rary one, but is perhaps only more pernicious, cancerous, and despotic
|
||
than the others, and more steeped in illusion than they.
|
||
In any case, content and expression are never reducible to signified-
|
||
signifier. And (this is the second problem) neither are they reducible to
|
||
base-superstructure. One can no more posit a primacy of content as the
|
||
determining factor than a primacy of expression as a signifying system.
|
||
Expression can never be made into a form reflecting content, even if one
|
||
endows it with a "certain" amount of independence and a certain potential
|
||
for reacting, if only because so-called economic content already has a form
|
||
and even forms of expression that are specific to it. Form of content and
|
||
form of expression involve two parallel formalizations in presupposition:
|
||
it is obvious that their segments constantly intertwine, embed themselves
|
||
in one another; but this is accomplished by the abstract machine from
|
||
which the two forms derive, and by machinic assemblages that regulate
|
||
their relations. If this parallelism is replaced by a pyramidal image, then
|
||
content (including its form) becomes an economic base of production dis-
|
||
playing all of the characteristics of the Abstract; the assemblages become
|
||
the first story of a superstructure that, as such, is necessarily situated
|
||
within a State apparatus; the regimes of signs and forms of expression
|
||
become the second story of the superstructure, defined by ideology. It isn't
|
||
altogether clear where language should go, since the great Despot decided
|
||
that it should be reserved a special place, as the common good of the nation
|
||
and the vehicle for information. Thus one misconstrues the nature of lan-
|
||
guage, which exists only in heterogeneous regimes of signs, and rather than
|
||
circulating information distributes contradictory orders. It misconstrues
|
||
the nature of regimes of signs, which express organizations of power or
|
||
assemblages and have nothing to do with ideology as the supposed expres-
|
||
sion of a content (ideology is a most execrable concept obscuring all of the
|
||
effectively operating social machines). It misconstrues the nature of orga-
|
||
nizations of power, which are in no way located within a State apparatus
|
||
but rather are everywhere, effecting formalizations of content and expres-
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 69
|
||
|
||
sion, the segments of which they intertwine. Finally, it misconstrues the
|
||
nature of content, which is in no way economic "in the last instance," since
|
||
there are as many directly economic signs or expressions as there are
|
||
noneconomic contents. Nor can the status of social formations be analyzed
|
||
by throwing some signifier into the base, or vice versa, or a bit of phallus or
|
||
castration into political economy, or a bit of economics or politics into
|
||
psychoanalysis.
|
||
There is a third problem. It is difficult to elucidate the system of the
|
||
strata without seeming to introduce a kind of cosmic or even spiritual evo-
|
||
lution from one to the other, as if they were arranged in stages and ascended
|
||
degrees of perfection. Nothing of the sort. The different figures of content
|
||
and expression are not stages. There is no biosphere or noosphere, but
|
||
everywhere the same Mechanosphere. If one begins by considering the
|
||
strata in themselves, it cannot be said that one is less organized than
|
||
another. This even applies to a stratum serving as a substratum: there is no
|
||
fixed order, and one stratum can serve directly as a substratum for another
|
||
without the intermediaries one would expect there to be from the stand-
|
||
point of stages and degrees (for example, microphysical sectors can serve as
|
||
an immediate substratum for organic phenomena). Or the apparent order
|
||
can be reversed, with cultural or technical phenomena providing a fertile
|
||
soil, a good soup, for the development of insects, bacteria, germs, or even
|
||
particles. The industrial age defined as the age of insects . . . It's even worse
|
||
nowadays: you can't even tell in advance which stratum is going to commu-
|
||
nicate with which other, or in what direction. Above all, there is no lesser,
|
||
no higher or lower, organization; the substratum is an integral part of the
|
||
stratum, is bound up with it as the milieu in which change occurs, and not
|
||
an increase in organization.31 Furthermore, if we consider the plane of con-
|
||
sistency we note that the most disparate of things and signs move upon it: a
|
||
semiotic fragment rubs shoulders with a chemical interaction, an electron
|
||
crashes into a language, a black hole captures a genetic message, a crystalli-
|
||
zation produces a passion, the wasp and the orchid cross a letter... There
|
||
is no "like" here, we are not saying "like an electron," "like an interaction,"
|
||
etc. The plane of consistency is the abolition of all metaphor; all that con-
|
||
sists is Real. These are electrons in person, veritable black holes, actual
|
||
organites, authentic sign sequences. It's just that they have been uprooted
|
||
from their strata, destratified, decoded, deterritorialized, and that is what
|
||
makes their proximity and interpenetration in the plane of consistency
|
||
possible. A silent dance. The plane of consistency knows nothing of differ-
|
||
ences in level, orders of magnitude, or distances. It knows nothing of the dif-
|
||
ference between the artificial and the natural. It knows nothing of the
|
||
distinction between contents and expressions, or that between forms and
|
||
70 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
formed substances; these things exist only by means of and in relation to the
|
||
strata.
|
||
But how can one still identify and name things if they have lost the strata
|
||
that qualified them, if they have gone into absolute deterritorialization?
|
||
Eyes are black holes, but what are black holes and eyes outside their strata
|
||
and territorialities? What it comes down to is that we cannot content our-
|
||
selves with a dualism or summary opposition between the strata and the
|
||
destratified plane of consistency. The strata themselves are animated and
|
||
defined by relative speeds of deterritorialization; moreover, absolute
|
||
deterritorialization is there from the beginning, and the strata are spin-
|
||
offs, thickenings on a plane of consistency that is everywhere, always pri-
|
||
mary and always immanent. In addition, the plane of consistency is
|
||
occupied, drawn by the abstract Machine; the abstract Machine exists
|
||
simultaneously developed on the destratified plane it draws, and envel-
|
||
oped in each stratum whose unity of composition it defines, and even half-
|
||
erected in certain strata whose form of prehension it defines. That which
|
||
races or dances upon the plane of consistency thus carries with it the aura of
|
||
its stratum, an undulation, a memory or tension. The plane of consistency
|
||
retains just enough of the strata to extract from them variables that operate
|
||
in the plane of consistency as its own functions. The plane of consistency,
|
||
or planomenon, is in no way an undifferentiated aggregate of unformed
|
||
matters, but neither is it a chaos of formed matters of every kind. It is true
|
||
that on the plane of consistency there are no longer forms or substances,
|
||
content or expression, respective and relative deterritorializations. But
|
||
beneath the forms and substances of the strata the plane of consistency (or
|
||
the abstract machine) constructs continuums of intensity: it creates conti-
|
||
nuity for intensities that it extracts from distinct forms and substances.
|
||
Beneath contents and expressions the plane of consistency (or the abstract
|
||
machine) emits and combines particles-signs that set the most asignifying
|
||
of signs to functioning in the most deterritorialized of particles. Beneath
|
||
relative movements the plane of consistency (or the abstract machine) per-
|
||
forms conjunctions of flows of deterritorialization that transform the
|
||
respective indexes into absolute values. The only intensities known to the
|
||
strata are discontinuous, bound up in forms and substances; the only parti-
|
||
cles are divided into particles of content and articles of expression; the only
|
||
deterritorialized flows are disjointed and reterritorialized. Continuum of
|
||
intensities, combined emission of particles or signs-particles, conjunction
|
||
of deterritorialized flows: these are the three factors proper to the plane of
|
||
consistency; they are brought about by the abstract machine and are consti-
|
||
tutive of destratification. Now there is no hint in all of this of a chaotic
|
||
white night or an undifferentiated black night. There are rules, rules of
|
||
"plan(n)ing," of diagramming, as we will see later on, or elsewhere. The
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 71
|
||
|
||
abstract machine is not random; the continuities, emissions and combina-
|
||
tions, and conjunctions do not occur in just any fashion.
|
||
A final distinction must now be noted. Not only does the abstract
|
||
machine have different simultaneous states accounting for the complex-
|
||
ity of what takes place on the plane of consistency, but the abstract
|
||
machine should not be confused with what we call a concrete machinic
|
||
assemblage. The abstract machine sometimes develops upon the plane of
|
||
consistency, whose continuums, emissions, and conjugations it con-
|
||
structs, and sometimes remains enveloped in a stratum whose unity of
|
||
composition and force of attraction or prehension it defines. The
|
||
machinic assemblage is something entirely different from the abstract
|
||
machine, even though it is very closely connected with it. First, on a stra-
|
||
tum, it performs the coadaptations of content and expression, ensures
|
||
biunivocal relationships between segments of content and segments of
|
||
expression, and guides the division of the stratum into epistrata and
|
||
parastrata. Next, between strata, it ensures the relation to whatever
|
||
serves as a substratum and brings about the corresponding changes in
|
||
organization. Finally, it is in touch with the plane of consistency because
|
||
it necessarily effectuates the abstract machine on a particular stratum,
|
||
between strata, and in the relation between the strata and the plane. An
|
||
assemblage (for example, the smith's anvil among the Dogons) is neces-
|
||
sary for the articulations of the organic stratum to come about. An assem-
|
||
blage is necessary for the relation between two strata to come about. And
|
||
an assemblage is necessary for organisms to be caught within and perme-
|
||
ated by a social field that utilizes them: Must not the Amazons amputate a
|
||
breast to adapt the organic stratum to a warlike technological stratum, as
|
||
though at the behest of a fearsome woman-bow-steppe assemblage?
|
||
Assemblages are necessary for states offeree and regimes of signs to inter-
|
||
twine their relations. Assemblages are necessary in order for the unity of
|
||
composition enveloped in a stratum, the relations between a given stra-
|
||
tum and the others, and the relation between these strata and the plane of
|
||
consistency to be organized rather than random. In every respect,
|
||
machinic assemblages effectuate the abstract machine insofar as it is
|
||
developed on the plane of consistency or enveloped in a stratum. The
|
||
most important problem of all: given a certain machinic assemblage,
|
||
what is its relation of effectuation with the abstract machine? How does it
|
||
effectuate it, with what adequation? Classify assemblages. What we call
|
||
the mechanosphere is the set of all abstract machines and machinic
|
||
assemblages outside the strata, on the strata, or between strata.
|
||
The system of the strata thus has nothing to do with signifier and signi-
|
||
fied, base and superstructure, mind and matter. All of these are ways of
|
||
reducing the strata to a single stratum, or of closing the system in on itself
|
||
72 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
by cutting it off from the plane of consistency as destratification. We had to
|
||
summarize before we lost our voice. Challenger was finishing up. His voice
|
||
had become unbearably shrill. He was suffocating. His hands were becom-
|
||
ing elongated pincers that had become incapable of grasping anything but
|
||
could still vaguely point to things. Some kind of matter seemed to be pour-
|
||
ing out from the double mask, the two heads; it was impossible to tell
|
||
whether it was getting thicker or more watery. Some of the audience had
|
||
returned, but only shadows and prowlers. "You hear that? It's an animal's
|
||
voice." So the summary would have to be quick, the terminology would
|
||
have to be set down as well as possible, for no good reason. There was a first
|
||
group of notions: the Body without Organs or the destratified Plane of
|
||
Consistency; the Matter of the Plane, that which occurs on the body or
|
||
plane (singular, nonsegmented multiplicities composed of intensive con-
|
||
tinuums, emissions of particles-signs, conjunctions of flows); and the
|
||
abstract Machine, or abstract Machines, insofar as they construct that
|
||
body or draw that plane or "diagram" what occurs (lines of flight, or abso-
|
||
lute deterritorializations).
|
||
Then there was the system of the strata. On the intensive continuum, the
|
||
strata fashion forms and form matters into substances. In combined emis-
|
||
sions, they make the distinction between expressions and contents, units of
|
||
expression and units of content, for example, signs and particles. In con-
|
||
junctions, they separate flows, assigning them relative movements and
|
||
diverse territorialities, relative deterritorializations and complementary
|
||
reterritorializations. Thus the strata set up everywhere double articula-
|
||
tions animated by movements: forms and substances of content and forms
|
||
and substances of expression constituting segmentary multiplicities with
|
||
relations that are determinable in every case. Such are the strata. Each stra-
|
||
tum is a double articulation of content and expression, both of which are
|
||
really distinct and in a state of reciprocal presupposition. Content and
|
||
expression intermingle, and it is two-headed machinic assemblages that
|
||
place their segments in relation. What varies from stratum to stratum is the
|
||
nature of the real distinction between content and expression, the nature of
|
||
the substances as formed matters, and the nature of the relative move-
|
||
ments. We may make a summary distinction between three major types of
|
||
real distinction: the real-formal distinction between orders of magnitude,
|
||
with the establishment of a resonance of expression (induction); the real-
|
||
real distinction between different subjects, with the establishment of a
|
||
linearity of expression (transduction); and the real-essential distinction
|
||
between different attributes or categories, with the establishment of a
|
||
superlinearity of expression (translation).
|
||
Each stratum serves as the substratum for another stratum. Each stra-
|
||
tum has a unity of composition defined by its milieu, substantial elements,
|
||
10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS D 73
|
||
|
||
and formal traits (Ecumenon). But it divides into parastrata according to
|
||
its irreducible forms and associated milieus, and into epistrata according
|
||
to its layers of formed substances and intermediary milieus. Epistrata and
|
||
parastrata must themselves be thought of as strata. A machinic assemblage
|
||
is an interstratum insofar as it regulates the relations between strata, as well
|
||
as the relations between contents and expressions on each stratum, in
|
||
conformity with the preceding divisions. A single assemblage can borrow
|
||
from different strata, and with a certain amount of apparent disorder;
|
||
conversely, a stratum or element of a stratum can join others in function-
|
||
ing in a different assemblage. Finally, the machinic assemblage is a
|
||
metastratum because it is also in touch with the plane of consistency and
|
||
necessarily effectuates the abstract machine. The abstract machine exists
|
||
enveloped in each stratum, whose Ecumenon or unity of composition it
|
||
defines, and developed on the plane of consistency, whose destratification
|
||
it performs (the Planomenon). Thus when the assemblages fit together the
|
||
variables of a stratum as a function of its unity, they also bring about a spe-
|
||
cific effectuation of the abstract machine as it exists outside the strata.
|
||
Machinic assemblages are simultaneously located at the intersection of the
|
||
contents and expression on each stratum, and at the intersection of all of
|
||
the strata with the plane of consistency. They rotate in all directions, like
|
||
beacons.
|
||
It was over. Only later on would all of this take on concrete meaning. The
|
||
double-articulated mask had come undone, and so had the gloves and the
|
||
tunic, from which liquids escaped. As they streamed away they seemed to
|
||
eat at the strata of the lecture hall, which was filled with fumes of olibanum
|
||
and "hung with strangely figured arras." Disarticulated, deterritorialized,
|
||
Challenger muttered that he was taking the earth with him, that he was
|
||
leaving for the mysterious world, his poison garden. He whispered some-
|
||
thing else: it is by headlong flight that things progress and signs proliferate.
|
||
Panic is creation. A young woman cried out, her face "convulsed with a
|
||
wilder, deeper, and more hideous epilepsy of stark panic than they had seen
|
||
on human countenance before." No one had heard the summary, and no
|
||
one tried to keep Challenger from leaving. Challenger, or what remained of
|
||
him, slowly hurried toward the plane of consistency, following a bizarre tra-
|
||
jectory with nothing relative left about it. He tried to slip into an assem-
|
||
blage serving as a drum-gate, the particle Clock with its intensive clicking
|
||
and conjugated rhythms hammering out the absolute: "The figure slumped
|
||
oddly into a posture scarcely human, and began a curious, fascinated sort
|
||
of shuffle toward the coffin-shaped clock The figure had now reached
|
||
the abnormal clock, and the watchers saw through the dense fumes a
|
||
blurred black claw fumbling with the tall, hieroglyphed door. The fumbling
|
||
made a queer, clicking sound. Then the figure entered the coffin-shaped
|
||
74 D 10,000 B.C.: THE GEOLOGY OF MORALS
|
||
|
||
case and pulled the door shut after i t . . . . The abnormal clicking went on,
|
||
beating out the dark, cosmic rhythm which underlies all mystical gate-
|
||
openings"32—the Mechanosphere, or rhizosphere.
|
||
4. November 20, 1923—Postulates of
|
||
Linguistics
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
The Order-word Assemblage
|
||
|
||
|
||
I. "Language Is Informational and Comiminicational"
|
||
When the schoolmistress instructs her students on a rule of grammar or
|
||
arithmetic, she is not informing them, any more than she is informing her-
|
||
self when she questions a student. She does not so much instruct as
|
||
"insign," give orders or commands. A teacher's commands are not external
|
||
or additional to what he or she teaches us. They do not flow from primary
|
||
significations or result from information: an order always and already con-
|
||
cerns prior orders, which is why ordering is redundancy. The compulsory
|
||
education machine does not communicate information; it imposes upon
|
||
the child semiotic coordinates possessing all of the dual foundations of
|
||
75
|
||
76 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
grammar (masculine-feminine, singular-plural, noun-verb, subject of the
|
||
statement-subject of enunciation, etc.). The elementary unit of language—
|
||
the statement—is the order-word.1 Rather than common sense, a faculty
|
||
for the centralization of information, we must define an abominable
|
||
faculty consisting in emitting, receiving, and transmitting order-words.
|
||
Language is made not to be believed but to be obeyed, and to compel obedi-
|
||
ence. "The baroness has not the slightest intention of convincing me of her
|
||
sincerity; she is simply indicating that she prefers to see me pretend to
|
||
agree."2 We see this in police or government announcements, which often
|
||
have little plausibility or truthfulness, but say very clearly what should be
|
||
observed and retained. The indifference to any kind of credibility exhib-
|
||
ited by these announcements often verges on provocation. This is proof
|
||
that the issue lies elsewhere. Let people say...: that is all language
|
||
demands. Spengler notes that the fundamental forms of speech are not the
|
||
statement of a judgment or the expression of a feeling, but "the command,
|
||
the expression of obedience, the assertion, the question, the affirmation or
|
||
negation," very short phrases that command life and are inseparable from
|
||
enterprises and large-scale projects: "Ready?" "Yes." "Go ahead."3 Words
|
||
are not tools, but we give children language, pens, and notebooks as we give
|
||
workers shovels and pickaxes. A rule of grammar is a power marker before
|
||
it is a syntactical marker. The order does not refer to prior significations or
|
||
to a prior organization of distinctive units. Quite the opposite. Informa-
|
||
tion is only the strict minimum necessary for the emission, transmission,
|
||
and observation of orders as commands. One must be just informed
|
||
enough not to confuse "Fire!" with "Fore!" or to avoid the unfortunate situ-
|
||
ation of the teacher and the student as described by Lewis Carroll (the
|
||
teacher, at the top of the stairs, asks a question that is passed on by servants,
|
||
who distort it at each step of the way, and the student, below in the court-
|
||
yard, returns an answer that is also distorted at each stage of the trip back).
|
||
Language is not life; it gives life orders. Life does not speak; it listens and
|
||
waits.4 Every order-word, even a father's to his son, carries a little death
|
||
sentence—a Judgment, as Kafka put it.
|
||
The hard part is to specify the status and scope of the order-word. It is
|
||
not a question of the origin of language, since the order-word is only a
|
||
language-function, a function coextensive with language. If language
|
||
always seems to presuppose itself, if we cannot assign it a nonlinguistic
|
||
point of departure, it is because language does not operate between some-
|
||
thing seen (or felt) and something said, but always goes from saying to say-
|
||
ing. We believe that narrative consists not in communicating what one has
|
||
seen but in transmitting what one has heard, what someone else said to
|
||
you. Hearsay. It does not even suffice to invoke a vision distorted by pas-
|
||
sion. The "first" language, or rather the first determination of language, is
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 77
|
||
|
||
not the trope or metaphor but indirect discourse. The importance some
|
||
have accorded metaphor and metonymy proves disastrous for the study of
|
||
language. Metaphors and metonymies are merely effects; they are a part of
|
||
language only when they presuppose indirect discourse. There are many
|
||
passions in a passion, all manner of voices in a voice, murmurings, speak-
|
||
ing in tongues: that is why all discourse is indirect, and the translative
|
||
movement proper to language is that of indirect discourse.5 Benveniste
|
||
denies that the bee has language, even though it has an organic coding pro-
|
||
cess and even uses tropes. It has no language because it can communicate
|
||
what it has seen but not transmit what has been communicated to it. A bee
|
||
that has seen a food source can communicate the message to bees that did
|
||
not see it, but a bee that has not seen it cannot transmit the message to oth-
|
||
ers that did not see it.6 Language is not content to go from a first party to a
|
||
second party, from one who has seen to one who has not, but necessarily
|
||
goes from a second party to a third party, neither of whom has seen. It is in
|
||
this sense that language is the transmission of the word as order-word, not
|
||
the communication of a sign as information. Language is a map, not a trac-
|
||
ing. But how can the order-word be a function coextensive with language
|
||
when the order, the command, seems tied to a restricted type of explicit
|
||
proposition marked by the imperative?
|
||
Austin's famous theses clearly demonstrate that the various extrinsic
|
||
relations between action and speech by which a statement can describe an
|
||
action in an indicative mode or incite it in an imperative mode, etc., are not
|
||
all there is. There are also intrinsic relations between speech and certain
|
||
actions that are accomplished by sayingthem (the performative: I swear by
|
||
saying "I swear"), and more generally between speech and certain actions
|
||
that are accomplished in speaking (the illocutionary: I ask a question by
|
||
saying "Is ... ?" I make a promise by saying "I love you ..."; I give a com-
|
||
mand by using the imperative, etc.). These acts internal to speech, these
|
||
immanent relations between statements and acts, have been termed
|
||
implicit or nondiscursive presuppositions, as opposed to the potentially
|
||
explicit assumptions by which a statement refers to other statements or an
|
||
external action (Ducrot). The theory of the performative sphere, and the
|
||
broader sphere of the illocutionary, has had three important and immedi-
|
||
ate consequences: (1) It has made it impossible to conceive of language as a
|
||
code, since a code is the condition of possibility for all explanation. It has
|
||
also made it impossible to conceive of speech as the communication of
|
||
information: to order, question, promise, or affirm is not to inform some-
|
||
one about a command, doubt, engagement, or assertion but to effectuate
|
||
these specific, immanent, and necessarily implicit acts. (2) It has made it
|
||
impossible to define semantics, syntactics, or even phonematics as scien-
|
||
tific zones of language independent of pragmatics. Pragmatics ceases to be
|
||
78 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
a "trash heap," pragmatic determinations cease to be subject to the alterna-
|
||
tive: fall outside language, or answer to explicit conditions that syntacticize
|
||
and semanticize pragmatic determinations. Instead, pragmatics becomes
|
||
the presupposition behind all of the other dimensions and insinuates itself
|
||
into everything. (3) It makes it impossible to maintain the distinction
|
||
between language and speech because speech can no longer be defined sim-
|
||
ply as the extrinsic and individual use of a primary signification, or the var-
|
||
iable application of a preexisting syntax. Quite the opposite, the meaning
|
||
and syntax of language can no longer be defined independently of the
|
||
speech acts they presuppose.7
|
||
It is true that it is still difficult to see how speech acts or implicit presup-
|
||
positions can be considered a function coextensive with language. It is all
|
||
the more difficult if one starts with the performative (that which one does
|
||
by saying it) and moves by extension to the illocutionary (that which one
|
||
does in speaking). For it is always possible to thwart that move. The
|
||
performative can be walled in by explaining it by specific syntactic and
|
||
semantic characteristics avoiding any recourse to a generalized prag-
|
||
matics. According to Benveniste, for example, the performative relates not
|
||
to acts but instead to a property ofself-referentiality of terms (the true per-
|
||
sonal pronouns, I, Y O U . . . , defined as shifters). By this account, a
|
||
preexistent structure of subjectivity, or intersubjectivity, in language,
|
||
rather than presupposing speech acts, is adequate to account for them.8
|
||
Benveniste thus defines language as communicational rather than infor-
|
||
mational; this properly linguistic intersubjectivity, or subjectification,
|
||
explains all the rest, in other words, everything that is brought into being by
|
||
saying it. The question is whether subjective communication is any better a
|
||
linguistic notion than ideal information. Oswald Ducrot has set forth the
|
||
reasons that have led him to reverse Benveniste's schema: The phenome-
|
||
non ofself-referentiality cannot account for the performative. The oppo-
|
||
site is the case; it is "the fact that certain statements are socially devoted to
|
||
the accomplishment of certain actions" that explains self-referentiality.
|
||
The performative itself is explained by the illocutionary, not the opposite.
|
||
It is the illocutionary that constitutes the nondiscursive or implicit presup-
|
||
positions. And the illocutionary is in turn explained by collective assem-
|
||
blages of enunciation, by juridical acts or equivalents of juridical acts,
|
||
which, far from depending on subjectification proceedings or assignations
|
||
of subjects in language, in fact determine their distribution. Communica-
|
||
tion is no better a concept than information; intersubjectivity gets us no
|
||
further than signifiance in accounting for these "statements-acts" assem-
|
||
blages that in each language delimit the role and range of subjective mor-
|
||
phemes.9 (We will see that the analysis of indirect discourse confirms this
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 79
|
||
|
||
point of view since it shows that subjectifications are not primary but
|
||
result from a complex assemblage.)
|
||
We call order-words, not a particular category of explicit statements (for
|
||
example, in the imperative), but the relation of every word or every state-
|
||
ment to implicit presuppositions, in other words, to speech acts that are,
|
||
and can only be, accomplished in the statement. Order-words do not con-
|
||
cern commands only, but every act that is linked to statements by a "social
|
||
obligation." Every statement displays this link, directly or indirectly. Ques-
|
||
tions, promises, are order-words. The only possible definition of language
|
||
is the set of all order-words, implicit presuppositions, or speech acts cur-
|
||
rent in a language at a given moment.
|
||
The relation between the statement and the act is internal, immanent,
|
||
but it is not one of identity. Rather, it is a relation of redundancy. The order-
|
||
word itself is the redundancy of the act and the statement. Newspapers,
|
||
news, proceed by redundancy, in that they tell us what we "must" think,
|
||
retain, expect, etc. Language is neither informational nor communica-
|
||
tional. It is not the communication of information but something quite dif-
|
||
ferent: the transmission of order-words, either from one statement to
|
||
another or within each statement, insofar as each statement accomplishes
|
||
an act and the act is accomplished in the statement. The most general
|
||
schema of information science posits in principle an ideal state of maxi-
|
||
mum information and makes redundancy merely a limitative condition
|
||
serving to decrease this theoretical maximum in order to prevent it from
|
||
being drowned out by noise. We are saying that the redundancy of the
|
||
order-word is instead primary and that information is only the minimal
|
||
condition for the transmission of order-words (which is why the opposition
|
||
to be made is not between noise and information but between all the
|
||
indisciplines at work in language, and the order-word as discipline or
|
||
"grammaticality"). Redundancy has two forms, frequency and resonance;
|
||
the first concerns the signifiance of information, the second (I = I) con-
|
||
cerns the subjectivity of communication. It becomes apparent that infor-
|
||
mation and communication, and even signifiance and subjectification, are
|
||
subordinate to redundancy. A distinction is sometimes made between
|
||
information and communication; some authors envision an abstract
|
||
signifiance of information and an abstract subjectification of communica-
|
||
tion. None of this, however, yields an implicit or primary form of language.
|
||
There is no signifiance independent of dominant significations, nor is
|
||
there subjectification independent of an established order of subjection.
|
||
Both depend on the nature and transmission of order-words in a given
|
||
social field.
|
||
There is no individual enunciation. There is not even a subject of enun-
|
||
ciation. Yet relatively few linguists have analyzed the necessarily social
|
||
80 O NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
character of enunciation.' ° The problem is that it is not enough to establish
|
||
that enunciation has this social character, since it could be extrinsic; there-
|
||
fore too much or too little is said about it. The social character of enuncia-
|
||
tion is intrinsically founded only if one succeeds in demonstrating how
|
||
enunciation in itself implies collective assemblages. It then becomes clear
|
||
that the statement is individuated, and enunciation subjectified, only to
|
||
the extent that an impersonal collective assemblage requires it and deter-
|
||
mines it to be so. It is for this reason that indirect discourse, especially
|
||
"free" indirect discourse, is of exemplary value: there are no clear, distinc-
|
||
tive contours; what comes first is not an insertion of variously individ-
|
||
uated statements, or an interlocking of different subjects of enunciation,
|
||
but a collective assemblage resulting in the determination of relative
|
||
subjectification proceedings, or assignations of individuality and their
|
||
shifting distributions within discourse. Indirect discourse is not explained
|
||
by the distinction between subjects; rather, it is the assemblage, as it freely
|
||
appears in this discourse, that explains all the voices present within a single
|
||
voice, the glimmer of girls in a monologue by Charlus, the languages in a
|
||
language, the order-words in a word. The American murderer "Son of
|
||
Sam" killed on the prompting of an ancestral voice, itself transmitted
|
||
through the voice of a dog. The notion of collective assemblage of enuncia-
|
||
tion takes on primary importance since it is what must account for the
|
||
social character. We can no doubt define the collective assemblage as the
|
||
redundant complex of the act and the statement that necessarily accom-
|
||
plishes it. But this is still only a nominal definition; it does not even enable
|
||
us to justify our previous position that redundancy is irreducible to a sim-
|
||
ple identity (or that there is no simple identity between the statement and
|
||
the act). If we wish to move to a real definition of the collective assemblage,
|
||
we must ask of what consist these acts immanent to language that are in
|
||
redundancy with statements or constitute order-words.
|
||
These acts seem to be defined as the set of all incorporeal transforma-
|
||
tions current in a given society and attributed to the bodies of that society.
|
||
We may take the word "body" in its broadest sense (there are mental bod-
|
||
ies, souls are bodies, etc.). We must, however, distinguish between the
|
||
actions and passions affecting those bodies, and acts, which are only
|
||
noncorporeal attributes or the "expressed" of a statement. When Ducrot
|
||
asks what an act consists of, he turns precisely to the juridical assemblage,
|
||
taking the example of the judge's sentence that transforms the accused into
|
||
a convict. In effect, what takes place beforehand (the crime of which some-
|
||
one is accused), and what takes place after (the carrying out of the penalty),
|
||
are actions-passions affecting bodies (the body of the property, the body of
|
||
the victim, the body of the convict, the body of the prison); but the transfor-
|
||
mation of the accused into a convict is a pure instantaneous act or incorpo-
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 81
|
||
|
||
real attribute that is the expressed of the judge's sentence.11 Peace and war
|
||
are states or interminglings of very different kinds of bodies, but the decla-
|
||
ration of a general mobilization expresses an instantaneous and incorpo-
|
||
real transformation of bodies. Bodies have an age, they mature and grow
|
||
old; but majority, retirement, any given age category, are incorporeal trans-
|
||
formations that are immediately attributed to bodies in particular socie-
|
||
ties. "You are no longer a child": this statement concerns an incorporeal
|
||
transformation, even if it applies to bodies and inserts itself into their
|
||
actions and passions. The incorporeal transformation is recognizable by
|
||
its instantaneousness, its immediacy, by the simultaneity of the statement
|
||
expressing the transformation and the effect the transformation produces;
|
||
that is why order-words are precisely dated, to the hour, minute, and sec-
|
||
ond, and take effect the moment they are dated. Love is an intermingling of
|
||
bodies that can be represented by a heart with an arrow through it, by a
|
||
union of souls, etc., but the declaration "I love you" expresses a noncor-
|
||
poreal attribute of bodies, the lover's as well as that of the loved one. Eating
|
||
bread and drinking wine are interminglings of bodies; communing with
|
||
Christ is also an intermingling of bodies, properly spiritual bodies that are
|
||
no less "real" for being spiritual. But the transformation of the body of the
|
||
bread and the wine into the body and blood of Christ is the pure expressed
|
||
of a statement attributed to the bodies. In an airplane hijacking, the threat
|
||
of a hijacker brandishing a revolver is obviously an action; so is the execu-
|
||
tion of the hostages, if it occurs. But the transformation of the passengers
|
||
into hostages, and of the plane-body into a prison-body, is an instantane-
|
||
ous incorporeal transformation, a "mass media act" in the sense in which
|
||
the English speak of "speech acts." The order-words or assemblages of
|
||
enunciation in a given society (in short, the illocutionary) designate this
|
||
instantaneous relation between statements and the incorporeal transfor-
|
||
mations or noncorporeal attributes they express.
|
||
The instantaneousness of the order-word, which can be projected to
|
||
infinity, placed at the origin of society, is quite strange; for Rousseau, for
|
||
example, the passage from the state of nature to the social state is like a leap
|
||
in place, an incorporeal transformation occurring at zero hour. Real his-
|
||
tory undoubtedly recounts the actions and passions of the bodies that
|
||
develop in a social field; it communicates them in a certain fashion; but it
|
||
also transmits order-words, in other words, pure acts intercalated into that
|
||
development. History will never be rid of dates. Perhaps economics or
|
||
financial analysis best demonstrates the presence and instantaneousness
|
||
of these decisive acts in an overall process (that is why statements defi-
|
||
nitely do not belong to ideology, but are already at work in what is suppos-
|
||
edly the domain of the economic base). The galloping inflation in
|
||
Germany after 1918 was a crisis affecting the monetary body, and many
|
||
82 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
other bodies besides; but the sum of the "circumstances" suddenly made
|
||
possible a semiotic transformation that, although indexed to the body of
|
||
the earth and material assets, was still a pure act or incorporeal trans-
|
||
formation—November 20, 1923.. .'2
|
||
The assemblages are in constant variation, are themselves constantly
|
||
subject to transformations. First, the circumstances must be taken into
|
||
account: Benveniste clearly demonstrates that a performative statement is
|
||
nothing outside of the circumstances that make it performative. Anybody
|
||
can shout, "I declare a general mobilization," but in the absence of an effec-
|
||
tuated variable giving that person the right to make such a statement it is an
|
||
act of peurility or insanity, not an act of enunciation. This is also true of "I
|
||
love you," which has neither meaning nor subject nor addressee outside of
|
||
circumstances that not only give it credibility but make it a veritable
|
||
assemblage, a power marker, even in the case of an unhappy love (it is still
|
||
by a will to power that one obeys ...). The general term "circumstances"
|
||
should not leave the impression that it is a question only of external cir-
|
||
cumstances. "I swear" is not the same when said in the family, at school, in
|
||
a love affair, in a secret society, or in court: it is not the same thing, and nei-
|
||
ther is it the same statement; it is not the same bodily situation, and neither
|
||
is it the same incorporeal transformation. The transformation applies to
|
||
bodies but is itself incorporeal, internal to enunciation. There are variables
|
||
of expression that establish a relation between language and the outside, but
|
||
precisely because they are immanent to language. As long as linguistics
|
||
confines itself to constants, whether syntactical, morphological, or pho-
|
||
nological, it ties the statement to a signifier and enunciation to a subject
|
||
and accordingly botches the assemblage; it consigns circumstances to the
|
||
exterior, closes language in on itself, and makes pragmatics a residue. Prag-
|
||
matics, on the other hand, does not simply appeal to external circum-
|
||
stances: it brings to light variables of expression or of enunciation that are
|
||
so many internal reasons for language not to close itself off. As Volosinov
|
||
[Bakhtin] says, as long as linguistics extracts constants, it is incapable of help-
|
||
ing us understand how a single word can be a complete enunciation; there
|
||
must be "an extra something" that "remains outside of the scope of the entire
|
||
set of linguistic categories and definitions," even though it is still entirely
|
||
within the purview of the theory of enunciation or language.'3 The order-word
|
||
is precisely that variable that makes the word as such an enunciation. The
|
||
instantaneousness of the order-word, its immediacy, gives it a power of varia-
|
||
tion in relation to the bodies to which the transformation is attributed.
|
||
Pragmatics is a politics of language. A study such as Jean-Pierre Faye's
|
||
on the constitution of Nazi statements in the German social field is in this
|
||
respect exemplary (and cannot be directly transferred to the constitution
|
||
of Fascist statements in Italy). Transformational research of this kind is
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 83
|
||
|
||
concerned with the variation of the order-words and noncorporeal attri-
|
||
butes linked to social bodies and effectuating immanent acts. We may take
|
||
as another example, under different conditions, the formation of a prop-
|
||
erly Leninist type of statement in Soviet Russia, basing ourselves on a text
|
||
by Lenin entitled "On Slogans" (1917). This text constituted an incorpo-
|
||
real transformation that extracted from the masses a proletarian class as an
|
||
assemblage of enunciation before the conditions were present for the prole-
|
||
tariat to exist as a body. A stroke of genius from the First Marxist Interna-
|
||
tional, which "invented" a new type of class: Workers of the world, unite!14
|
||
Taking advantage of the break with the Social Democrats, Lenin invented
|
||
or decreed yet another incorporeal transformation that extracted from the
|
||
proletarian class a vanguard as an assemblage of enunciation and was
|
||
attributed to the "Party," a new type of party as a distinct body, at the risk of
|
||
falling into a properly bureaucratic system of redundancy. The Leninist
|
||
wager, an act of audacity? Lenin declared that the slogan (mot d'ordre) "All
|
||
power to the Soviets" was valid only from the 27th of February to the 4th of
|
||
July for the peacetime development of the Revolution, and no longer held
|
||
in the state of war; the passage from peace to war implied this transforma-
|
||
tion, not just from the masses to a guiding proletariat, but from the prole-
|
||
tariat to a directing vanguard. July 4 exactly the power of the Soviets came
|
||
to an end. All of the external circumstances can be assigned: the war as well
|
||
as the insurrection that forced Lenin to flee to Finland. But the fact
|
||
remains that the incorporeal transformation was uttered on the 4th of July,
|
||
prior to the organization of the body to which it would be attributed,
|
||
namely, the Party itself. "Every particular slogan must be deduced from the
|
||
totality of the specific features of a definite political situation."15 If the
|
||
objection is leveled that these specific features pertain to politics and not
|
||
linguistics, it must be observed how thoroughly politics works language
|
||
from within, causing not only the vocabulary but also the structure and all
|
||
of the phrasal elements to vary as the order-words change. A type of state-
|
||
ment can be evaluated only as a function of its pragmatic implications, in
|
||
other words, in relation to the implicit presuppositions, immanent acts, or
|
||
incorporeal transformations it expresses and which introduce new config-
|
||
urations of bodies. True intuition is not a judgment of grammaticality but
|
||
an evaluation of internal variables of enunciation in relation to the aggre-
|
||
gate of the circumstances.
|
||
We have gone from explicit commands to order-words as implicit pre-
|
||
suppositions; from order-words to the immanent acts or incorporeal trans-
|
||
formations they express; and from there to the assemblages of enunciation
|
||
whose variables they are. To the extent these variables enter at a given
|
||
moment into determinable relations, the assemblages combine in a regime
|
||
of signs or a semiotic machine. It is obvious that a society is plied by several
|
||
84 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
semiotics, that its regimes are in fact mixed. Moreover, at a later time there
|
||
will arise new order-words that will modify the variables and will not yet be
|
||
part of a known regime. Thus the order-word is redundancy in several
|
||
ways: as a function of the process of transmission essential to it, and in
|
||
itself, from the time it is emitted, in its "immediate" relation with the act or
|
||
transformation it effectuates. The order-word is already redundancy even
|
||
when it is in rupture with a particular semiotic. That is why every state-
|
||
ment of a collective assemblage of enunciation belongs to indirect dis-
|
||
course. Indirect discourse is the presence of a reported statement within
|
||
the reporting statement, the presence of an order-word within the word.
|
||
Language in its entirety is indirect discourse. Indirect discourse in no way
|
||
supposes direct discourse; rather, the latter is extracted from the former, to
|
||
the extent that the operations of signifiance and proceedings of subjec-
|
||
tification in an assemblage are distributed, attributed, and assigned, or
|
||
that the variables of the assemblage enter into constant relations, however
|
||
temporarily. Direct discourse is a detached fragment of a mass and is born
|
||
of the dismemberment of the collective assemblage; but the collective
|
||
assemblage is always like the murmur from which I take my proper name,
|
||
the constellation of voices, concordant or not, from which I draw my voice.
|
||
I always depend on a molecular assemblage of enunciation that is not given
|
||
in my conscious mind, any more than it depends solely on my apparent
|
||
social determinations, which combine many heterogeneous regimes of
|
||
signs. Speaking in tongues. To write is perhaps to bring this assemblage of
|
||
the unconscious to the light of day, to select the whispering voices, to gather
|
||
the tribes and secret idioms from which I extract something I call my Self
|
||
(Moi). I is an order-word. A schizophrenic said: "I heard voices say: he is
|
||
conscious of life."16 In this sense, there is indeed a schizophrenic cogito, but
|
||
it is a cogito that makes self-consciousness the incorporeal transformation
|
||
of an order-word, or a result of indirect discourse. My direct discourse is
|
||
still the free indirect discourse running through me, coming from other
|
||
worlds or other planets. That is why so many artists and writers have been
|
||
tempted by the seance table. When we ask what faculty is specific to the
|
||
order-word, we must indeed attribute to it some strange characteristics: a
|
||
kind of instantaneousness in the emission, perception, and transmission of
|
||
order-words; a wide variability, and a power of forgetting permitting one to
|
||
feel absolved of the order-words one has followed and then abandoned in
|
||
order to welcome others; a properly ideal or ghostly capacity for the appre-
|
||
hension of incorporeal transformations; an aptitude for grasping language
|
||
as an immense indirect discourse.'7 The faculty of the cuer and the cued, of
|
||
the song that always holds a tune within a tune in a relation of redundancy;
|
||
a faculty that is in truth mediumistic, glossolalic, or xenoglossic.
|
||
Let us return to the question of how this defines a language-function, a
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 85
|
||
|
||
function coextensive with language. It is evident that order-words, collec-
|
||
tive assemblages, or regimes of signs cannot be equated with language. But
|
||
they effectuate its condition of possibility (the superlinearity of expres-
|
||
sion), they fulfill in each instance this condition of possibility; without
|
||
them, language would remain a pure virtuality (the superlinear character
|
||
of indirect discourse). Doubtless, the assemblages vary, undergo transfor-
|
||
mation. But they do not necessarily vary by language, they do not corre-
|
||
spond to the various languages. A language seems to be defined by the
|
||
syntactical, semantic, phonological constants in its statements; the collec-
|
||
tive assemblage, on the contrary, concerns the usage of these constants in
|
||
relation to variables internal to enunciation itself (variables of expression,
|
||
immanent acts, or incorporeal transformations). Different constants, dif-
|
||
ferent languages, may have the same usage; the same constants in a given
|
||
language may have different usages, successively or even simultaneously.
|
||
We cannot content ourselves with a duality between constants as linguistic
|
||
factors that are explicit or potentially explicit, and variables as extrinsic,
|
||
nonlinguistic factors. For the pragmatic variables of usage are internal to
|
||
enunciation and constitute the implicit presuppositions of language. Thus
|
||
if the collective assemblage is in each instance coextensive with the linguis-
|
||
tic system considered, and to language as a whole, it is because it expresses
|
||
the set of incorporeal transformations that effectuate the condition of pos-
|
||
sibility of language and utilize the elements of the linguistic system. The
|
||
language-function thus defined is neither informational nor communi-
|
||
cational; it has to do neither with signifying information nor with
|
||
intersubjective communication. And it is useless to abstract a signifiance
|
||
outside information, or a subjectivity outside communication. For the
|
||
subjectification proceedings and movement of signifiance relate to
|
||
regimes of signs, or collective assemblages. The language-function is the
|
||
transmission of order-words, and order-words relate to assemblages, just as
|
||
assemblages relate to the incorporeal transformations constituting the var-
|
||
iables of the function. Linguistics is nothing without a pragmatics
|
||
(semiotic or political) to define the effectuation of the condition of possibil-
|
||
ity of language and the usage of linguistic elements.
|
||
|
||
II. "There Is an Abstract Machine of Language That
|
||
Does Not Appeal to Any 'Extrinsic' Factor"
|
||
If in a social field we distinguish the set of corporeal modifications and the
|
||
set of incorporeal transformations, we are presented, despite the variety in
|
||
each of the sets, with two formalizations, one of content, the other of
|
||
expression. For content is not opposed to form but has its own formal-
|
||
ization: the hand-tool pole, or the lesson of things. It is, however, opposed
|
||
86 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
to expression, inasmuch as expression also has its own formalization: the
|
||
face-language pole, the lesson of signs. Precisely because content, like
|
||
expression, has a form of its own, one can never assign the form of expres-
|
||
sion the function of simply representing, describing, or averring a corre-
|
||
sponding content: there is neither correspondence nor conformity. The
|
||
two formalizations are not of the same nature; they are independent, heter-
|
||
ogeneous. The Stoics were the first to theorize this independence: they dis-
|
||
tinguished between the actions and passions of bodies (using the word
|
||
"body" in the broadest sense, as applying to any formed content) and
|
||
incorporeal acts (the "expressed" of the statements). The form of expres-
|
||
sion is constituted by the warp of expresseds, and the form of content by the
|
||
woof of bodies. When knife cuts flesh, when food or poison spreads
|
||
through the body, when a drop of wine falls into water, there is an intermin-
|
||
gling of bodies; but the statements, "The knife is cutting the flesh," "I am
|
||
eating," "The water is turning red," express incorporeal transformations of
|
||
an entirely different nature (events).18 The genius of the Stoics was to have
|
||
taken this paradox as far as it could go, up to the point of insanity and cyni-
|
||
cism, and to have grounded it in the most serious of principles: their reward
|
||
was to be the first to develop a philosophy of language.
|
||
The paradox gets us nowhere unless, like the Stoics, we add that incorpo-
|
||
real transformations, incorporeal attributes, apply to bodies, and only to
|
||
bodies. They are the expressed of statements but are attributed to bodies.
|
||
The purpose is not to describe or represent bodies; bodies already have
|
||
proper qualities, actions and passions, souls, in short forms, which are
|
||
themselves bodies. Representations are bodies too! If noncorporeal attri-
|
||
butes apply to bodies, if there are good grounds for making a distinction
|
||
between the incorporeal expressed "to become red" and the corporeal
|
||
quality "red," etc., it has nothing to with representation. We cannot even
|
||
say that the body or state of things is the "referent" of the sign. In expressing
|
||
the noncorporeal attribute, and by that token attributing it to the body, one
|
||
is not representing or referring but intervening in a way; it is a speech act.
|
||
The independence of the two kinds of forms, forms of expression and
|
||
forms of content, is not contradicted but confirmed by the fact that the
|
||
expressions or expresseds are inserted into or intervene in contents, not to
|
||
represent them but to anticipate them or move them back, slow them down
|
||
or speed them up, separate or combine them, delimit them in a different
|
||
way. The warp of the instantaneous transformations is always inserted into
|
||
the woof of the continuous modifications. (Hence the significance of dates
|
||
for the Stoics. From what moment can it be said that someone is bald? In
|
||
what sense does a statement of the type "There will be a naval battle tomor-
|
||
row" constitute a date or order-word?) The night of August 4, July 4,1917,
|
||
November 20, 1923: What incorporeal transformation is expressed by
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 87
|
||
|
||
these dates, incorporeal yet attributed to bodies, inserted into them? The
|
||
independence of the form of expression and the form of content is not the
|
||
basis for a parallelism between them or a representation of one by the other,
|
||
but on the contrary a parceling of the two, a manner in which expressions
|
||
are inserted into contents, in which we ceaselessly jump from one register
|
||
to another, in which signs are at work in things themselves just as things
|
||
extend into or are deployed through signs. An assemblage of enunciation
|
||
does not speak "of things; it speaks on the same level as states of things and
|
||
states of content. So that the same x, the same particle, may function either
|
||
as a body that acts and undergoes actions or as a sign constituting an act or
|
||
order-word, depending on which form it is taken up by (for example, the
|
||
theoretico-experimental aggregate of physics). In short, the functional in-
|
||
dependence of the two forms is only the form of their reciprocal presup-
|
||
position, and of the continual passage from one to the other. We are never
|
||
presented with an interlinkage of order-words and a causality of contents
|
||
each in its own right; nor do we see one represent the other, with the second
|
||
serving as referent. On the contrary, the independence of the two lines is
|
||
distributive, such that a segment of one always forms a relay with a segment
|
||
of the other, slips into, introduces itself into the other. We constantly pass
|
||
from order-words to the "silent order" of things, as Foucault puts it, and
|
||
vice versa.
|
||
But when we use a word as vague as "intervene," when we say that
|
||
expressions intervene or insert themselves into contents, are we not still
|
||
prey to a kind of idealism in which the order-word instantaneously falls
|
||
from the sky? What we must determine is not an origin but points of inter-
|
||
vention or insertion in the framework of the reciprocal presupposition of
|
||
the two forms. Both forms of content and forms of expression are insepara-
|
||
ble from a movement of deterritorialization that carries them away. Both
|
||
expression and content are more or less deterritorialized, relatively
|
||
deterritorialized, according to the particular state of their form. In this
|
||
respect, one cannot posit a primacy of expression over content, or content
|
||
over expression. Sometimes the semiotic components are more deter-
|
||
ritorialized than the material components, and sometimes the reverse. For
|
||
example, a mathematical complex of signs may be more deterritorialized
|
||
than a set of particles; conversely, the particles may have experimental
|
||
effects that deterritorialize the semiotic system. A criminal action may be
|
||
deterritorializing in relation to the existing regime of signs (the earth cries
|
||
for revenge and crumbles beneath my feet, my offense is too great); but the
|
||
sign that expresses the act of condemnation may in turn be deter-
|
||
ritorializing in relation to all actions and reactions ("a fugitive and a
|
||
vagabond shall thou be in the earth" [Gen. 4:12], you cannot even be
|
||
killed). In short, there are degrees of deterritorialization that quantify the
|
||
88 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
respective forms and according to which contents and expression are
|
||
conjugated, feed into each other, accelerate each other, or on the contrary
|
||
become stabilized and perform a reterritorialization. What we call circum-
|
||
stances or variables are these degrees themselves. There are variables of
|
||
content, or proportions in the interminglings or aggregations of bodies, and
|
||
there are variables of expression, factors internal to enunciation. Germany,
|
||
toward November 20, 1923: on the one hand, the deterritorializing infla-
|
||
tion of the monetary body and, on the other, in response to the inflation, a
|
||
semiotic transformation of the reichsmark into the rentenmark, making
|
||
possible a reterritorialization. Russia, toward July 4,1917: on the one hand
|
||
proportions of a state of "bodies" Soviets-provisional government, and on
|
||
the other the elaboration of a Bolshevik incorporeal semiotic, accelerating
|
||
things and contributing to the action of the detonating body of the Party. In
|
||
short, the way an expression relates to a content is not by uncovering or rep-
|
||
resenting it. Rather, forms of expression and forms of content communi-
|
||
cate through a conjunction of their quanta of relative deterritorialization,
|
||
each intervening, operating in the other.
|
||
We may draw some general conclusions on the nature of Assemblages
|
||
from this. On a first, horizontal, axis, an assemblage comprises two seg-
|
||
ments, one of content, the other of expression. On the one hand it is a
|
||
machinic assemblage of bodies, of actions and passions, an intermingling
|
||
of bodies reacting to one another; on the other hand it is a collective assem-
|
||
blage of enunciation, of acts and statements, of incorporeal transforma-
|
||
tions attributed to bodies. Then on a vertical axis, the assemblage has both
|
||
territorial sides, or reterritorialized sides, which stabilize it, and cutting
|
||
edges of deterritorialization, which carry it away. No one is better than
|
||
Kafka at differentiating the two axes of the assemblage and making them
|
||
function together. On the one hand, the ship-machine, the hotel-machine,
|
||
the circus-machine, the castle-machine, the court-machine, each with its
|
||
own intermingled pieces, gears, processes, and bodies contained in one
|
||
another or bursting out of containment (see the head bursting through the
|
||
roof)-19 On the other hand, the regime of signs or of enunciation: each
|
||
regime with its incorporeal transformations, acts, death sentences and
|
||
judgments, proceedings, "law." It is obvious that statements do not repre-
|
||
sent machines: the Stoker's discourse does not describe stoking as a body; it
|
||
has its own form, and a development without resemblance.20 Yet it is
|
||
attributed to bodies, to the whole ship as a body. A discourse of submission
|
||
to order-words; a discourse of discussion, claims, accusation, and defense.
|
||
On the second axis, what is compared or combined of the two aspects, what
|
||
always inserts one into the other, are the sequenced or conjugated degrees
|
||
of deterritorialization, and the operations of reterritorialization that stabi-
|
||
lize the aggregate at a given moment. K., the K.-function, designates the
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 89
|
||
|
||
line of flight or deterritorialization that carries away all of the assemblages
|
||
but also undergoes all kinds of reterritorializations and redundancies—
|
||
redundancies of childhood, village-life, love, bureaucracy, etc.
|
||
The tetravalence of the assemblage. Taking the feudal assemblage as an
|
||
example, we would have to consider the interminglings of bodies defining
|
||
feudalism: the body of the earth and the social body; the body of the over-
|
||
lord, vassal, and serf; the body of the knight and the horse and their new
|
||
relation to the stirrup; the weapons and tools assuring a symbiosis of
|
||
bodies—a whole machinic assemblage. We would also have to consider
|
||
statements, expressions, the juridical regime of heraldry, all of the incorpo-
|
||
real transformations, in particular, oaths and their variables (the oath of
|
||
obedience, but also the oath of love, etc.): the collective assemblage of
|
||
enunciation. On the other axis, we would have to consider the feudal
|
||
territorialities and reterritorializations, and at the same time the line of
|
||
deterritorialization that carries away both the knight and his mount, state-
|
||
ments and acts. We would have to consider how all this combines in the
|
||
Crusades.
|
||
It would be an error to believe that content determines expression by
|
||
causal action, even if expression is accorded the power not only to "reflect"
|
||
content but to react upon it in an active way. This kind of ideological con-
|
||
ception of the statement, which subordinates it to a primary economic con-
|
||
tent, runs into all kinds of difficulties inherent to dialectics. First, although
|
||
it may be possible to conceive of a causal action moving from content to
|
||
expression, the same cannot be said for the respective forms, the form of
|
||
content and the form of expression. We must recognize that expression is
|
||
independent and that this is precisely what enables it to react upon con-
|
||
tents. This independence, however, has been poorly conceived. If contents
|
||
are said to be economic, the form of content cannot be said to be economic
|
||
and is reduced to a pure abstraction, namely, the production of goods and
|
||
the means of that production considered in themselves. Similarly, if ex-
|
||
pressions are said to be ideological, the form of expression is not said to be
|
||
ideological and is reduced to language as abstraction, as the availability of a
|
||
good shared by all. Those who take this approach claim to characterize
|
||
contents and expressions by all the struggles and conflicts pervading them
|
||
in two different forms, but these forms themselves are exempt from strug-
|
||
gle and conflict, and the relation between them remains entirely indeter-
|
||
minate.21 The only way to define the relation is to revamp the theory of
|
||
ideology by saying that expressions and statements intervene directly in
|
||
productivity, in the form of a production of meaning or sign-value. The
|
||
category of production doubtless has the advantage of breaking with
|
||
schemas of representation, information, and communication. But is it any
|
||
more adequate than these schemas? Its application to language is very
|
||
90 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
ambiguous in that it appeals to an ongoing dialectical miracle of the
|
||
transformation of matter into meaning, content into expression, the social
|
||
process into a signifying system.
|
||
We think the material or machinic aspect of an assemblage relates not to
|
||
the production of goods but rather to a precise state of intermingling of
|
||
bodies in a society, including all the attractions and repulsions, sympathies
|
||
and antipathies, alterations, amalgamations, penetrations, and expan-
|
||
sions that affect bodies of all kinds in their relations to one another. What
|
||
regulates the obligatory, necessary, or permitted interminglings of bodies
|
||
is above all an alimentary regime and a sexual regime. Even technology
|
||
makes the mistake of considering tools in isolation: tools exist only in rela-
|
||
tion to the interminglings they make possible or that make them possible.
|
||
The stirrup entails a new man-horse symbiosis that at the same time entails
|
||
new weapons and new instruments. Tools are inseparable from symbioses
|
||
or amalgamations defining a Nature-Society machinic assemblage. They
|
||
presuppose a social machine that selects them and takes them into its "phy-
|
||
lum": a society is defined by its amalgamations, not by its tools. Similarly,
|
||
the semiotic or collective aspect of an assemblage relates not to a produc-
|
||
tivity of language but to regimes of signs, to a machine of expression whose
|
||
variables determine the usage of language elements. These elements do not
|
||
stand on their own any more than tools do. There is a primacy of the
|
||
machinic assemblage of bodies over tools and goods, a primacy of the col-
|
||
lective assemblage of enunciation over language and words. The articula-
|
||
tion of the two aspects of the assemblage is effected by the movements of
|
||
deterritorialization that quantify their forms. That is why a social field is
|
||
defined less by its conflicts and contradictions than by the lines of flight
|
||
running through it. An assemblage has neither base nor superstructure,
|
||
neither deep structure nor superficial structure; it flattens all of its dimen-
|
||
sions onto a single plane of consistency upon which reciprocal presupposi-
|
||
tions and mutual insertions play themselves out.
|
||
The other mistake (which is combined with the first as needed) is to
|
||
believe in the adequacy of the form of expression as a linguistic system.
|
||
This system may be conceived as a signifying phonological structure, or as
|
||
a deep syntactical structure. In either case, it is credited with engendering
|
||
semantics, therefore of fulfilling expression, whereas contents are rele-
|
||
gated to the arbitrariness of a simple "reference" and pragmatics to the
|
||
exteriority of nonlinguistic factors. What all of these undertakings have in
|
||
common is to erect an abstract machine of language, but as a synchronic set
|
||
of constants. We will not object that the machine thus conceived is too
|
||
abstract. On the contrary, it is not abstract enough, it remains "linear." It
|
||
remains on an intermediate level of abstraction allowing it to consider lin-
|
||
guistic factors in themselves, independently of nonlinguistic factors, and
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 91
|
||
|
||
to treat those linguistic factors as constants. But if the abstraction is taken
|
||
further, one necessarily reaches a level where the pseudoconstants of lan-
|
||
guage are superseded by variables of expression internal to enunciation
|
||
itself; these variables of expression are then no longer separable from the
|
||
variables of content with which they are in perpetual interaction. If the
|
||
external pragmatics of nonlinguistic factors must be taken into considera-
|
||
tion, it is because linguistics itself is inseparable from an internal prag-
|
||
matics involving its own factors. It is not enough to take into account the
|
||
signified, or even the referent, because the very notions of signification
|
||
and reference are bound up with a supposedly autonomous and constant
|
||
structure. There is no use constructing a semantics, or even recognizing a
|
||
certain validity to pragmatics, if they are still pretreated by a phonological
|
||
or syntactical machine. For a true abstract machine pertains to an assem-
|
||
blage in its entirety: it is defined as the diagram of that assemblage. It is not
|
||
language based but diagrammatic and superlinear. Content is not a signi-
|
||
fied nor expression a signifier; rather, both are variables of the assemblage.
|
||
We get nowhere until the pragmatic, but also semantic, syntactical, and
|
||
phonological determinations are directly linked to the assemblages of
|
||
enunciation upon which they depend. Chomsky's abstract machine retains
|
||
an arborescent model and a linear ordering of linguistic elements in sen-
|
||
tences and sentence combinations. But as soon as pragmatic values or
|
||
internal variables are taken into account, in particular with respect to indi-
|
||
rect discourse, one is obliged to bring "hypersentences" into play or to con-
|
||
struct "abstract objects" (incorporeal transformations). This implies
|
||
superlinearity, in other words, a plane whose elements no longer have a
|
||
fixed linear order: the rhizome model.22 From this standpoint, the inter-
|
||
penetration of language and the social field and political problems lies at
|
||
the deepest level of the abstract machine, not at the surface. The abstract
|
||
machine as it relates to the diagram of the assemblage is never purely a mat-
|
||
ter of language, except for lack of sufficient abstraction. It is language that
|
||
depends on the abstract machine, not the reverse. At most, we may dis-
|
||
tinguish in the abstract machine two states of the diagram, one in which
|
||
variables of content and expression are distributed according to their het-
|
||
erogeneous forms in reciprocal presupposition on a plane of consistency,
|
||
and another in which it is no longer even possible to distinguish between
|
||
variables of content and expression because the variability of that same
|
||
plane has prevailed over the duality of forms, rendering them "indis-
|
||
cernible." (The first state relates to still relative movements of deterritori-
|
||
alization; in the second, an absolute threshold of deterritorialization has
|
||
been reached.)
|
||
92 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
III. "There Are Constants or Universals of Language That Enable Us to
|
||
Define It as a Homogeneous System"
|
||
The question of structural invariants—and the very idea of structure is
|
||
inseparable from invariants, whether atomic or relational—is essential to
|
||
linguistics. It is what allows linguistics to claim a basis in pure scientificity,
|
||
to be nothing but science ... safe from any supposedly external or prag-
|
||
matic factor. The question of invariants assumes several closely connected
|
||
forms: (1) the constants of a language (phonological, by commutativity;
|
||
syntactical, by transformativity; semantic, by generativity); (2) the uni-
|
||
versals of language (by decomposition of the phoneme into distinctive
|
||
features; of syntax into fundamental constituents; of signification into
|
||
minimal semantic elements); (3) trees linking constants to one another,
|
||
with binary relations between trees (see Chomsky's linear arborescent
|
||
method); (4) competence, in principle coextensive with language and
|
||
defined by judgments of grammaticality; (5) homogeneity, bearing on ele-
|
||
ments and relations as well as intuitive judgments; (6) synchrony, which
|
||
erects an "in-itself' and a "for-itself' of language, perpetually moving from
|
||
the objective system to the subjective consciousness that apprehends its
|
||
principle (that of the linguist himself or herself).
|
||
One can juggle all of these factors, subtract some or even add new ones.
|
||
They go together, however, because the essentials of all of them are present
|
||
on the level of any one. For example, the distinction between speech and
|
||
language is recapitulated in the distinction between competence and per-
|
||
formance, but at the level of grammaticality. If it is objected that the dis-
|
||
tinction between competence and performance is entirely relative (a
|
||
linguistic competence can be economic, religious, political, or aesthetic,
|
||
etc.; the teaching competence of a grade school teacher may be only a per-
|
||
formance in relation to the judgment of an inspector or government regula-
|
||
tions), linguists respond that they are willing to multiply levels of
|
||
competence, and even to introduce pragmatic values into the system.
|
||
Brekle, for example, proposes adding an "idiosyncratic performatory com-
|
||
petence" factor tied to a whole constellation of linguistic, psychological, or
|
||
sociological factors. But what use is this injection of pragmatics if
|
||
pragmatics is in turn considered to have constants or universals of its own?
|
||
And in what way are expressions like "I," "promise," "know" more univer-
|
||
sal than "greet," "name," or "condemn"?23 Similarly, when efforts are
|
||
made to make Chomsky's trees bud and to shatter linear order, as long as
|
||
the pragmatic components marking the ruptures are placed above the tree
|
||
or effaced from the derivation nothing has really been accomplished, one
|
||
has failed to constitute a rhizome.24 In truth, the nature of the abstract
|
||
machine is the most general problem: there is no reason to tie the abstract
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS O 93
|
||
|
||
to the universal or the constant, or to efface the singularity of abstract
|
||
machines insofar as they are built around variables and variations.
|
||
The debate between Chomsky and Labov will give us a better under-
|
||
standing of what the issue is. Every language is an essentially heterogene-
|
||
ous reality; linguists know this and say so. But this is a factual remark.
|
||
Chomsky asks only that one carve from this aggregate a homogeneous or
|
||
standard system as a basis for abstraction or idealization, making possible
|
||
a scientific study of principles. Limiting oneself to standard English is thus
|
||
not the issue, for even a linguist who studies Black English or the English of
|
||
the ghettos is obliged to extract a standard system guaranteeing the con-
|
||
stancy and homogeneity of the object under study (no science can operate
|
||
any other way, they say). Thus Chomsky pretends to believe that by assert-
|
||
ing his interest in the variable features of language, Labov is situating him-
|
||
self in a de facto pragmatics external to linguistics.25 Labov, however, has
|
||
other ambitions. When he brings to light lines of inherent variation, he does
|
||
not see them simply as "free variants" pertaining to pronunciation, style,
|
||
or nonpertinent features that lie outside the system and leave the homoge-
|
||
neity of the system intact; neither does he see them as a de facto mix
|
||
between two systems, each homogeneous in its own right, as if the speaker
|
||
moved from one to the other. He refuses the alternative linguistics set up
|
||
for itself: assigning variants to different systems, or relegating them to a
|
||
place outside the structure. It is the variation itself that is systematic, in the
|
||
sense in which musicians say that "the theme is the variation." Labov sees
|
||
variation as a de jure component affecting each system from within, send-
|
||
ing it cascading or leaping on its own power and forbidding one to close it
|
||
off, to make it homogeneous in principle. Labov does consider variables of
|
||
all kinds, phonetic, phonological, syntactical, semantic, stylistic. Yet it
|
||
would seem difficult to accuse him of missing the distinction between the
|
||
de jure and the de facto—or between linguistics and stylistics, or
|
||
synchrony and diachrony, or pertinent and nonpertinent features, or com-
|
||
petence and performance, or the grammaticality of language and the
|
||
agrammaticality of speech. Although this may be hardening his positions,
|
||
we would say rather that Labov proposes a different distribution of the de
|
||
facto and the de jure, and especially a different conception of the de jure
|
||
itself and of abstraction. He takes the example of a young black person
|
||
who, in a very short series of phrases, seems to pass from the Black English
|
||
system to the standard system eighteen times. Is it not the abstract distinc-
|
||
tion between the two systems that proves arbitrary and insufficient? For
|
||
the majority of the forms belongs to one or the other only by virtue of the
|
||
fortuities of a given sequence. Must it not be admitted that every system is
|
||
in variation and is defined not by its constants and homogeneity but on the
|
||
94 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
contrary by a variability whose characteristics are immanent, continuous,
|
||
and regulated in a very specific mode (variable or optional rules)?25
|
||
How can we conceptualize this continuous variation at work within a
|
||
language, even if it means overstepping the limits Labov sets for himself as
|
||
well as the conditions of scientificity invoked by linguistics? In the course
|
||
of a single day, an individual repeatedly passes from language to language.
|
||
He successively speaks as "father to son" and as a boss; to his lover, he
|
||
speaks an infantilized language; while sleeping he is plunged into an oniric
|
||
discourse, then abruptly returns to a professional language when the tele-
|
||
phone rings. It will be objected that these variations are extrinsic, that it is
|
||
still the same language. But that is to prejudge the question. First, it is not
|
||
certain that the phonology is the same, nor the syntax, nor the semantics.
|
||
Second, the whole question is whether this supposedly identical language
|
||
is defined by invariants or, on the contrary, by the line of continuous varia-
|
||
tion running through it. Some linguists have suggested that linguistic
|
||
change occurs less by systemic rupture than by a gradual modification of
|
||
frequency, by a coexistence and continuity of different usages. Take as an
|
||
example the statement, "I swear!" It is a different statement depending on
|
||
whether it is said by a child to his or her father, by a man in love to his loved
|
||
one, or by a witness before the court. These are like three sequences. (Or
|
||
Messiaen's four "amen"s stretched over seven sequences.) Once again,
|
||
there is no reason to say that the variables are merely situational, and that
|
||
the statement remains constant in principle. Not only are there as many
|
||
statements as there are effectuations, but all of the statements are present
|
||
in the effectuation of one among them, so that the line of variation is vir-
|
||
tual, in other words, real without being actual, and consequently continu-
|
||
ous regardless of the leaps the statement makes. To place the statement in
|
||
continuous variation is to send it through all the prosodic, semantic, syn-
|
||
tactical, and phonological variables that can affect it in the shortest
|
||
moment of time (the smallest interval). Build the continuum of "I swear!"
|
||
with the corresponding transformations. This is the standpoint of
|
||
pragmatics, but a pragmatics internal to language, immanent, including
|
||
variations of linguistic elements of all kinds. For example, Kafka's line of
|
||
the three proceedings: the father's proceedings in the family, the engage-
|
||
ment proceedings at the hotel; and the court proceedings. There is a con-
|
||
stant tendency to seek a "reduction": everything is explained by the
|
||
situation of the child in relation to its father, or of the man in relation to
|
||
castration, or of the citizen in relation to the law. But this is to content one-
|
||
self with extracting a pseudoconstant of content, which is no better than
|
||
extracting a pseudoconstant of expression. Placing-in-variation allows us
|
||
to avoid these dangers, because it builds a continuum or medium without
|
||
beginning or end. Continuous variation should not be confused with the
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 95
|
||
|
||
continuous or discontinuous character of the variable itself: the order-
|
||
word, a continuous variation for a discontinuous variable . . . A variable
|
||
can be continuous over a portion of its trajectory, then leap or skip, without
|
||
that affecting its continuous variation; what this does is impose an absent
|
||
development as an "alternative continuity" that is virtual yet real.
|
||
A constant or invariant is defined less by its permanence and duration
|
||
than by its function as a center, if only relative. In the tonal or diatonic sys-
|
||
tem of music, laws of resonance and attraction determine centers valid for
|
||
all modes and endowed with stability and attractive power (pouvoir). These
|
||
centers therefore organize distinct, distinctive, forms that are clearly estab-
|
||
lished for a certain amount of time: a linear, codified, centered system of
|
||
the arborescent type. It is true that the minor "mode" gives tonal music a
|
||
decentered, runaway, fugitive character due to the nature of its intervals
|
||
and the lesser stability of its chords. This mode thus has the ambiguity of
|
||
undergoing operations that align it to a major model or standard at the
|
||
same time as it continues to display a certain modal power (puissance) irre-
|
||
ducible to tonality, as though music set out on a journey and garnered all
|
||
resurgences, phantoms of the Orient, imaginary lands, traditions from all
|
||
over. But temperament, tempered chromaticism has an even greater ambi-
|
||
guity: stretching the action of the center to the most distant tones, but also
|
||
preparing the disaggregation of the central principle, replacing the cen-
|
||
tered forms of continuous development with a form that constantly dis-
|
||
solves and transforms itself. When development subordinates form and
|
||
spans the whole, as in Beethoven, variation begins to free itself and
|
||
becomes identified with creation. But when chromaticism is unleashed,
|
||
becomes a generalized chromaticism, turns back against temperament,
|
||
affecting not only pitches but all sound components—durations, intensi-
|
||
ties, timbre, attacks—it becomes impossible to speak of a sound form
|
||
organizing matter; it is no longer even possible to speak of a continuous
|
||
development of form. Rather, it is a question of a highly complex and elab-
|
||
orate material making audible nonsonorous forces. The couple matter-
|
||
form is replaced by the coupling material-forces. The synthesizer has taken
|
||
the place of the old "a priori synthetic judgment," and all functions change
|
||
accordingly. By placing all its components in continuous variation, music
|
||
itself becomes a superlinear system, a rhizome instead of a tree, and enters
|
||
the service of a virtual cosmic continuum of which even holes, silences,
|
||
ruptures, and breaks are a part. Thus the important thing is certainly not to
|
||
establish a pseudobreak between the tonal system and atonal music; the
|
||
latter, on the contrary, in breaking away from the tonal system, only carried
|
||
temperament to its ultimate conclusion (although no Viennese stopped
|
||
there). The essential thing is almost the opposite movement: the ferment in
|
||
the tonal system itself (during much of the nineteenth and twentieth cen-
|
||
96 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
turies) that dissolved temperament and widened chromaticism while pre-
|
||
serving a relative tonality, which reinvented new modalities, brought a new
|
||
amalgamation of major and minor, and in each instance conquered realms
|
||
of continuous variation for this variable or that. This ferment came to the
|
||
forefront and made itself heard in its own right; and, through the molecular
|
||
material thus wrought, it made audible the nonsonorous forces of the
|
||
cosmos that have always agitated music—a bit of Time in the pure state,27 a
|
||
grain of absolute Intensity... The words "tonal," "modal," "atonal" do not
|
||
mean much. Music is not alone in being art as cosmos and in drawing the
|
||
virtual lines of an infinite variation.
|
||
Once again, the objection will be raised that music is not a language, that
|
||
the components of sound are not pertinent features of language, that there
|
||
is no correspondence between the two. We are not suggesting any corre-
|
||
spondence. We keep asking that the issue be left open, that any presup-
|
||
posed distinction be rejected. This especially applies to the language-
|
||
speech distinction, which is used to relegate all kinds of variables at work
|
||
within expression and enunciation to a position outside language. The
|
||
Voice-Music relation proposed by Jean-Jacques Rousseau, on the other
|
||
hand, could have taken not only phonetics and prosody but all of linguistics
|
||
in a different direction. The voice in music has always been a privileged
|
||
axis of experimentation, playing simultaneously on language and sound.
|
||
Music has linked the voice to instruments in various ways; but as long as
|
||
the voice is song, its main role is to "hold" sound, it functions as a constant
|
||
circumscribed on a note and accompanied by the instrument. Only when
|
||
the voice is tied to timbre does it reveal a tessitura that renders it heter-
|
||
ogeneous to itself and gives it a power of continuous variation: it is then
|
||
no longer accompanied, but truly "machined," it belongs to a musical
|
||
machine that prolongs or superposes on a single plane parts that are spo-
|
||
ken, sung, achieved by special effects, instrumental, or perhaps electronic-
|
||
ally generated. This is the sound plane of a generalized "glissando"
|
||
implying the constitution of a statistical space in which each variable has,
|
||
not an average value, but a probability of frequency that places it in contin-
|
||
uous variation with the other variables.28 Luciano Berio's Visage (Face)
|
||
and Dieter Schnebel's Glossolalie (Speaking in tongues) are typical exam-
|
||
ples of this. And despite what Berio himself says, it is less a matter of using
|
||
pseudoconstants to produce a simulacrum of language or a metaphor for
|
||
the voice than of attaining that secret neuter language without constants
|
||
and entirely in indirect discourse where the synthesizer and the instrument
|
||
speak no less than the voice, and the voice plays no less than the instru-
|
||
ment. It should not be thought that music has forgotten how to sing in a
|
||
now mechanical and atomized world; rather, an immense coefficient of
|
||
variation is affecting and carrying away all of the phatic, aphatic, linguistic,
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 97
|
||
|
||
poetic, instrumental, or musical parts of a single sound assemblage—"a
|
||
simple scream suffusing all degrees" (Thomas Mann). There are many pro-
|
||
cedures for placing the voice in variation, not only Sprechgesang (speech-
|
||
song), which constantly leaves pitch behind by descent or ascent, but also
|
||
circular breathing techniques and zones of resonance in which several
|
||
voices seem to issue from the same mouth. Secret languages are very
|
||
significant in this connection, in learned as well as popular music. Certain
|
||
ethnomusicologists have found extraordinary cases (in Dahomey, for
|
||
example) where a first, diatonic, vocal part is superseded by a chromatic
|
||
descent into a secret language that slips from one sound to the next in a con-
|
||
tinuous fashion, modulating a sound continuum into smaller and smaller
|
||
intervals until it becomes a "parlando" all of the intervals of which blur
|
||
together—and then the diatonic part is itself transposed according to the
|
||
chromatic levels of a terraced architecture, the song sometimes interrupted
|
||
by a parlando, by a simple conversation lacking definite pitch.29 It is per-
|
||
haps characteristic of secret languages, slangs, jargons, professional lan-
|
||
guages, nursery rhymes, merchants' cries to stand out less for their lexical
|
||
inventions or rhetorical figures than for the way in which they effect con-
|
||
tinuous variations of the common elements of language. They are chro-
|
||
matic languages, close to a musical notation. A secret language does not
|
||
merely have a hidden cipher or code still operating by constants and form-
|
||
ing a subsystem; it places the public language's system of variables in a state
|
||
ofvariation.
|
||
This is what we are getting at: a generalized chromaticism. Placing ele-
|
||
ments of any nature in continuous variation is an operation that will per-
|
||
haps give rise to new distinctions, but takes none as final and has none in
|
||
advance. On the contrary, this operation in principle bears on the voice,
|
||
speech, language, and music simultaneously. There is no reason to make
|
||
prior, principled distinctions. Linguistics in general is still in a kind of
|
||
major mode, still has a sort of diatonic scale and a strange taste for domi-
|
||
nants, constants, and universals. All languages, in the meantime, are in
|
||
immanent continuous variation: neither synchrony nor diachrony, but
|
||
asynchrony, chromaticism as a variable and continuous state of language.
|
||
For a chromatic linguistics according pragmatism its intensities and
|
||
values.
|
||
What is called a style can be the most natural thing in the world; it is
|
||
nothing other than the procedure of a continuous variation. Of the dual-
|
||
isms established by linguistics, there are few with a more shaky foundation
|
||
than the separation between linguistics and stylistics: Because a style is not
|
||
an individual psychological creation but an assemblage of enunciation, it
|
||
unavoidably produces a language within a language. Take an arbitrary list
|
||
of authors we are fond of: Kafka once again, Beckett, Gherasim Luca, Jean-
|
||
98 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
Luc Godard. It will be noted that they are all more or less in a bilingual situ-
|
||
ation: Kafka, the Czechoslovakian Jew writing in German; Beckett, the
|
||
Irishman writing in English and French; Luca, originally from Romania;
|
||
Godard and his will to be Swiss. But this is only circumstantial, an oppor-
|
||
tunity, and the opportunity can be found elsewhere. It will also be noted
|
||
that many of them are not only or not primarily writers (Beckett and
|
||
theater and television, Godard and film and television, Luca and his
|
||
audiovisual machines). The reason for this is that when one submits lin-
|
||
guistic elements to a treatment producing continuous variation, when one
|
||
introduces an internal pragmatics into language, one is necessarily led to
|
||
treat nonlinguistic elements such as gestures and instruments in the same
|
||
fashion, as if the two aspects of pragmatics joined on the same line of varia-
|
||
tion, in the same continuum. Moreover, the idea perhaps comes first from
|
||
outside, with language following only later, as with the necessarily exterior
|
||
sources of a style. But the essential thing is that each of these authors has his
|
||
own procedure of variation, his own widened chromaticism, his own mad
|
||
production of speeds and intervals. The creative stammering of Gherasim
|
||
Luca, in the poem "Passionnement" (Passionately).30 Godard's is another
|
||
kind of stammering. In theater: Robert Wilson's whispering, without defi-
|
||
nite pitch, and Carmelo Bene's ascending and descending variations.31 It's
|
||
easy to stammer, but making language itself stammer is a different affair; it
|
||
involves placing all linguistic, and even nonlinguistic, elements in varia-
|
||
tion, both variables of expression and variables of content. A new form of
|
||
redundancy. AND ... AND . . . AND . . . There has always been a struggle in
|
||
language between the verb etre (to be) and the conjunction et (and) between
|
||
est and et (is and and [which in French are identical in pronunciation—
|
||
Trans.]) It is only in appearance that these two terms are in accord and
|
||
combine, for the first acts in language as a constant and forms the diatonic
|
||
scale of language, while the second places everything in variation, consti-
|
||
tuting the lines of a generalized chromaticism. From one to the other,
|
||
everything shifts. Writers in British or American English have been more
|
||
conscious than the French of this struggle and the stakes involved, and of
|
||
the valence of the "and."32 It was Proust who said that "masterpieces are
|
||
written in a kind of foreign language." That is the same as stammering,
|
||
making language stammer rather than stammering in speech. To be a for-
|
||
eigner, but in one's own tongue, not only when speaking a language other
|
||
than one's own. To be bilingual, multilingual, but in one and the same lan-
|
||
guage, without even a dialect or patois. To be a bastard, a half-breed, but
|
||
through a purification of race. That is when style becomes a language. That
|
||
is when language becomes intensive, a pure continuum of values and inten-
|
||
sities. That is when all of language becomes secret, yet has nothing to hide,
|
||
as opposed to when one carves out a secret subsystem within language. One
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 99
|
||
|
||
attains this result only by sobriety, creative subtraction. Continuous varia-
|
||
tion has only ascetic lines, a touch of herb and pure water.
|
||
It is possible to take any linguistic variable and place it in variation fol-
|
||
lowing a necessarily virtual continuous line between two of its states. We
|
||
are no longer in the situation of linguists who expect the constants of lan-
|
||
guage to experience a kind of mutation or undergo the effects of changes
|
||
accumulated in speech alone. Lines of change or creation are fully and
|
||
directly a part of the abstract machine. Hjelmslev remarked that a language
|
||
necessarily includes unexploited possibilities or potentialities and that the
|
||
abstract machine must include these possibilities or potentialities.33
|
||
"Potential" and "virtual" are not at all in opposition to "real"; on the con-
|
||
trary, the reality of the creative, or the placing-in-continuous variation of
|
||
variables, is in opposition only to the actual determination of their con-
|
||
stant relations. Each time we draw a line of variation, the variables are of a
|
||
particular nature (phonological, syntactical or grammatical, semantic, and
|
||
so on), but the line itself is apertinent, asyntactic or agrammatical,
|
||
asemantic. Agrammaticality, for example, is no longer a contingent char-
|
||
acteristic of speech opposed to the grammaticality of language; rather, it is
|
||
the ideal characteristic of a line placing grammatical variables in a state of
|
||
continuous variation. Let us take Nicolas Ruwet's examples of certain sin-
|
||
gular expressions of Cummings's: "he danced his did," or "they went their
|
||
came." It is possible to reconstitute the variations through which the gram-
|
||
matical variables pass in virtuality in order to end up as agrammatical
|
||
expressions of this kind ("he did his dance," "he danced his dance," "he
|
||
danced what he did,"...; "they went as they came," "they went their
|
||
way," .. .).34 In spite of Ruwet's structural interpretation, we should avoid
|
||
taking the view that the atypical expression is produced by the successive
|
||
correct forms. It is instead the atypical expression that produces the
|
||
placing-in-variation of the correct forms, uprooting them from their state
|
||
as constants. The atypical expression constitutes a cutting edge of
|
||
deterritorialization of language, it plays the role of tensor; in other words, it
|
||
causes language to tend toward the limit of its elements, forms, or notions,
|
||
toward a near side or a beyond of language. The tensor effects a kind of
|
||
transit! vization of the phrase, causing the last term to react upon the pre-
|
||
ceding term, back through the entire chain. It assures an intensive and
|
||
chromatic treatment of language. An expression as simple as AND . . . can
|
||
play the role of tensor for all of language. In this sense, AND is less a
|
||
conjunction than the atypical expression of all of the possible conjunctions
|
||
it places in continuous variation. The tensor, therefore, is not reducible
|
||
either to a constant or a variable, but assures the variation of the variable
|
||
by subtracting in each instance the value of the constant (n - 1). Tensors
|
||
coincide with no linguistic category; nevertheless they are pragmatic
|
||
100 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
values essential to both assemblages of enunciation and indirect dis-
|
||
courses.35
|
||
Some believe that these variations do not express the usual labor of cre-
|
||
ation in language and remain marginal, confined to poets, children, and
|
||
lunatics. That is because they wish to define the abstract machine by con-
|
||
stants that can be modified only secondarily, by a cumulative effect or
|
||
syntagmatic mutation. But the abstract machine of language is not univer-
|
||
sal, or even general, but singular; it is not actual, but virtual-real; it has, not
|
||
invariable or obligatory rules, but optional rules that ceaselessly vary with
|
||
the variation itself, as in a game in which each move changes the rules. That
|
||
is why abstract machines and assemblages of enunciation are complemen-
|
||
tary, and present in each other. The abstract machine is like the diagram of
|
||
an assemblage. It draws lines of continuous variation, while the concrete
|
||
assemblage treats variables and organized their highly diverse relations as a
|
||
function of those lines. The assemblage negotiates variables at this or that
|
||
level of variation, according to this or that degree of deterritorialization,
|
||
and determines which variables will enter into constant relations or obey
|
||
obligatory rules and which will serve instead as a fluid matter for variation.
|
||
We should not conclude from this that the assemblage brings only a certain
|
||
resistance or inertia to bear against the abstract machine; for even "con-
|
||
stants" are essential to the determination of the virtualities through which
|
||
the variation passes, they are themselves optionally chosen. There is
|
||
indeed braking and resistance at a certain level, but at another level of the
|
||
assemblage there is nothing but a come-and-go between different types of
|
||
variables, and corridors of passage traveled in both directions: the varia-
|
||
bles effectuate the machine in unison, in the sum of their relations. There is
|
||
therefore no basis for a distinction between a constant and collective lan-
|
||
guage, and variable and individual speech acts. The abstract machine is
|
||
always singular, designated by the proper mane of a group or individual,
|
||
while the assemblage of enunciation is always collective, in the individual
|
||
as in the group. The Lenin abstract machine, and the Bolshevik collective
|
||
assemblage .. . The same goes for literature, for music. There is no primacy
|
||
of the individual; there is instead an indissolubility of a singular Abstract
|
||
and a collective Concrete. The abstract machine does not exist indepen-
|
||
dently of the assemblage, any more than the assemblage functions inde-
|
||
pendently of the machine.
|
||
|
||
IV. "Language Can Be Scientifically Studied Only under the Conditions
|
||
of a Standard or Major Language"
|
||
Since everybody knows that language is a heterogeneous, variable reality,
|
||
what is the meaning of the linguists' insistence on carving out a homoge-
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 101
|
||
|
||
neous system in order to make a scientific study possible? It is a question of
|
||
extracting a set of constants from the variables, or of determining constant
|
||
relations between variables (this is already evident in the phonologists'
|
||
concept of commutativity). But the scientific model taking language as an
|
||
object of study is one with the political model by which language is homog-
|
||
enized, centralized, standardized, becoming a language of power, a major
|
||
or dominant language. Linguistics can claim all it wants to be science,
|
||
nothing but pure science—it wouldn't be the first time that the order of
|
||
pure science was used to secure the requirements of another order. What is
|
||
grammaticality, and the sign S, the categorical symbol that dominates
|
||
statements? It is a power marker before it is a syntactical marker, and
|
||
Chomsky's trees establish constant relations between power variables.
|
||
Forming grammatically correct sentences is for the normal individual the
|
||
prerequisite for any submission to social laws. No one is supposed to be
|
||
ignorant of grammaticality; those who are belong in special institu-
|
||
tions. The unity of language is fundamentally political. There is no mother
|
||
tongue, only a power takeover by a dominant language that at times
|
||
advances along a broad front, and at times swoops down on diverse centers
|
||
simultaneously. We can conceive of several ways for a language to homoge-
|
||
nize, centralize: the republican way is not necessarily the same as the royal
|
||
way, and is not the least harsh.36 The scientific enterprise of extracting con-
|
||
stants and constant relations is always coupled with the political enterprise
|
||
of imposing them on speakers and transmitting order-words.
|
||
Speak white and loud
|
||
yes what a wonderful language
|
||
for hiring
|
||
giving orders
|
||
appointing the hour of death in the works
|
||
and of the break that refreshes . . .
|
||
Must a distinction then be made between two kinds of languages, "high"
|
||
and "low," major and minor? The first would be defined precisely by the
|
||
power (pouvoir) of constants, the second by the power (puissance) of varia-
|
||
tion. We do not simply wish to make an opposition between the unity of a
|
||
major language and the multiplicity of dialects. Rather, each dialect has a
|
||
zone of transition and variation; or better, each minor language has a prop-
|
||
erly dialectical zone of variation. According to Malmberg, it is rare to find
|
||
clear boundaries on dialect maps; instead, there are transitional and
|
||
limitrophe zones, zones of indiscernibility. It is also said that "the
|
||
Quebecois language is so rich in modulations and variations of regional
|
||
accents and in games with tonic accents that it sometimes seems, with no
|
||
exaggeration, that it would be better preserved by musical notation than by
|
||
102 n NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
any system of spelling."37 The very notion of dialect is quite questionable.
|
||
Moreover, it is relative because one needs to know in relation to what major
|
||
language it exercises its function: for example, the Quebecois language
|
||
must be evaluated not only in relation to standard French but also in rela-
|
||
tion to major English, from which it borrows all kinds of phonetic and syn-
|
||
tactical elements, in order to set them in variation. The Bantu dialects
|
||
must be evaluated not only in relation to the mother tongue but also in rela-
|
||
tion to Afrikaans as a major language, and English as a counter-major lan-
|
||
guage preferred by blacks.38 In short, the notion of dialect does not
|
||
elucidate that of minor language, but the other way around; it is the minor
|
||
language that defines dialects through its own possibilities for variation.
|
||
Should we identify major and minor languages on the basis of regional situ-
|
||
ations of bilingualism or multilingualism including at least one dominant
|
||
language and one dominated language, or a world situation giving certain
|
||
languages an imperialist power over others (for example, the role of Ameri-
|
||
can English today)?
|
||
At least two things prevent us from adopting this point of view. As
|
||
Chomsky notes, a dialect, ghetto language, or minor language is not
|
||
immune to the kind of treatment that draws a homogeneous system from it
|
||
and extracts constants: Black English has its own grammar, which is not
|
||
defined by a sum of mistakes or infractions against standard English; but
|
||
that grammar can be studied only by applying to it the same rules of study
|
||
that are applied to standard English. In this sense, the notions of major and
|
||
minor seem to have no linguistic relevance. When French lost its world-
|
||
wide major function it lost nothing of its constancy and homogeneity, its
|
||
centralization. Conversely, Afrikaans attained homogeneity when it was a
|
||
locally minor language struggling against English. Even politically, espe-
|
||
cially politically, it is difficult to see how the upholders of a minor language
|
||
can operate if not by giving it (if only by writing in it) a constancy and
|
||
homogeneity making it a locally major language capable of forcing official
|
||
recognition (hence the political role of writers who assert the rights of a
|
||
minor language). But the opposite argument seems more compelling: the
|
||
more a language has or acquires the characteristics of a major language, the
|
||
more it is affected by continuous variations that transpose it into a
|
||
"minor" language. It is futile to criticize the worldwide imperialism of a
|
||
language by denouncing the corruptions it introduces into other languages
|
||
(for example, the purists' criticisms of English influences in French, the
|
||
petit-bourgeois or academic denunciation of "Franglais"). For if a lan-
|
||
guage such as British English or American English is major on a world
|
||
scale, it is necessarily worked upon by all the minorities of the world, using
|
||
very diverse procedures of variation. Take the way Gaelic and Irish English
|
||
set English in variation. Or the way Black English and any number of
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 103
|
||
|
||
"ghetto languages" set American English in variation, to the point that
|
||
New York is virtually a city without a language. (Furthermore, American
|
||
English could not have constituted itself without this linguistic labor of the
|
||
minorities.) Or the linguistic situation in the old Austrian empire: German
|
||
was a major language in relation to the minorities, but as such it could not
|
||
avoid being treated by those minorities in a way that made it a minor
|
||
language in relation to the German of the Germans. There is no language
|
||
that does not have intralinguistic, endogenous, internal minorities. So at
|
||
the most general level of linguistics, Chomsky's and Labov's positions are
|
||
constantly passing and converting into each other. Chomsky can say that
|
||
even a minor, dialectical, or ghetto language cannot be studied unless
|
||
invariants are extracted from it and "extrinsic or mixed" variables are
|
||
eliminated; and Labov can respond that even a standard or major language
|
||
cannot be studied independently of "inherent" variations, which are pre-
|
||
cisely neither mixed nor extrinsic. You will never find a homogeneous sys-
|
||
tem that is not still or already affected by a regulated, continuous, immanent
|
||
process of variation (why does Chomsky pretend not to understand this?).
|
||
There are not, therefore, two kinds of languages but two possible treat-
|
||
ments of the same language. Either the variables are treated in such a way
|
||
as to extract from them constants and constant relations or in such a way as
|
||
to place them in continuous variation. We were wrong to give the impres-
|
||
sion at times that constants existed alongside variables, linguistic con-
|
||
stants alongside variables of enunciation: that was only for convenience of
|
||
presentation. For it is obvious that the constants are drawn from the varia-
|
||
bles themselves; universals in linguistics have no more existence in them-
|
||
selves than they do in economics and are always concluded from a
|
||
universalization or a rendering-uniform involving variables. Constant is
|
||
not opposed to variable; it is a treatment of the variable opposed to the other
|
||
kind of treatment, or continuous variation. So-called obligatory rules cor-
|
||
respond to the first kind of treatment, whereas optional rules concern the
|
||
construction of a continuum of variation. Moreover, there are a certain
|
||
number of categories or distinctions that cannot be invoked, that are inap-
|
||
plicable and useless as a basis for objections because they presuppose the
|
||
first treatment and are entirely subordinated to the quest for constants: for
|
||
example, language as opposed to speech; synchrony as opposed to
|
||
diachrony; competence as opposed to performance; distinctive features as
|
||
opposed to nondistinctive (or secondarily distinctive) features. For
|
||
nondistinctive features, whether prosodic, stylistic, or pragmatic, are not
|
||
only omnipresent variables, in contrast to the presence or absence of a con-
|
||
stant; they are not only superlinear and "suprasegmental" elements, in
|
||
contrast to linear segmental elements; their very characteristics give them
|
||
the power to place all the elements of language in a state of continuous
|
||
104 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
variation—for example, the impact of tone on phonemes, accent on mor-
|
||
phemes, or intonation on syntax. These are not secondary features but
|
||
another treatment of language that no longer operates according to the pre-
|
||
ceding categories.
|
||
"Major" and "minor" do not qualify two different languages but rather
|
||
two usages or functions of language. Bilingualism, of course, provides a
|
||
good example, but once again we use it simply for the sake of convenience.
|
||
Doubtless, in the Austrian empire Czech was a minor language in relation
|
||
to German; but the German of Prague already functioned as a potentially
|
||
minor language in relation to the German of Vienna or Berlin; and Kafka, a
|
||
Czechoslovakian Jew writing in German, submits German to creative
|
||
treatment as a minor language, constructing a continuum of variation,
|
||
negotiating all of the variables both to constrict the constants and to
|
||
expand the variables: make language stammer, or make it "wail," stretch
|
||
tensors through all of language, even written language, and draw from it
|
||
cries, shouts, pitches, durations, timbres, accents, intensities. Two con-
|
||
joined tendencies in so-called minor languages have often been noted: an
|
||
impoverishment, a shedding of syntactical and lexical forms; but simulta-
|
||
neously a strange proliferation of shifting effects, a taste for overload and
|
||
paraphrase. This applies to the German of Prague, Black English, and
|
||
Quebecois. But with rare exceptions, the interpretation of the linguists has
|
||
been rather malevolent, invoking a consubstantial poverty and preciosity.
|
||
The alleged poverty is in fact a restriction of constants and the overload an
|
||
extension of variations functioning to deploy a continuum sweeping up all
|
||
components. The poverty is not a lack but a void or ellipsis allowing one to
|
||
sidestep a constant instead of tackling it head on, or to approach it from
|
||
above or below instead of positioning oneself within it. And the overload is
|
||
not a rhetorical figure, a metaphor, or symbolic structure; it is a mobile par-
|
||
aphrase bearing witness to the unlocalized presence of an indirect dis-
|
||
course at the heart of every statement. From both sides we see a rejection of
|
||
reference points, a dissolution of constant form in favor of differences in
|
||
dynamic. The closer a language gets to this state, the closer it comes not
|
||
only to a system of musical notation, but also to music itself.39
|
||
Subtract and place in variation, remove and place in variation: a single
|
||
operation. Minor languages are characterized not by overload and poverty
|
||
in relation to a standard or major language, but by a sobriety and variation
|
||
that are like a minor treatment of the standard language, a becoming-
|
||
minor of the major language. The problem is not the distinction between
|
||
major and minor language; it is one of a becoming. It is a question not of
|
||
reterritorializing oneself on a dialect or a patois but of deterritorializing
|
||
the major language. Black Americans do not oppose Black to English, they
|
||
transform the American English that is their own language into Black
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 105
|
||
|
||
English. Minor languages do not exist in themselves: they exist only in rela-
|
||
tion to a major language and are also investments of that language for the
|
||
purpose of making it minor. One must find the minor language, the dialect
|
||
or rather idiolect, on the basis of which one can make one's own major lan-
|
||
guage minor. That is the strength of authors termed "minor," who are in
|
||
fact the greatest, the only greats: having to conquer one's own language, in
|
||
other words, to attain that sobriety in the use of a major language, in order
|
||
to place it in a state of continuous variation (the opposite of regionalism). It
|
||
is in one's own language that one is bilingual or multilingual. Conquer the
|
||
major language in order to delineate in it as yet unknown minor languages.
|
||
Use the minor language to send the major language racing. Minor authors
|
||
are foreigners in their own tongue. If they are bastards, if they experience
|
||
themselves as bastards, it is due not to a mixing or intermingling of lan-
|
||
guages but rather to a subtraction and variation of their own language
|
||
achieved by stretching tensors through it.
|
||
The notion of minority is very complex, with musical, literary, linguis-
|
||
tic, as well as juridical and political, references. The opposition between
|
||
minority and majority is not simply quantitative. Majority implies a con-
|
||
stant, of expression or content, serving as a standard measure by which to
|
||
evaluate it. Let us suppose that the constant or standard is the average
|
||
adult-white-heterosexual-European-male-speaking a standard language
|
||
(Joyce's or Ezra Pound's Ulysses). It is obvious that "man" holds the
|
||
majority, even if he is less numerous than mosquitoes, children, women,
|
||
blacks, peasants, homosexuals, etc. That is because he appears twice, once
|
||
in the constant and again in the variable from which the constant is
|
||
extracted. Majority assumes a state of power and domination, not the other
|
||
way around. It assumes the standard measure, not the other way around.
|
||
Even Marxism "has almost always translated hegemony from the point of
|
||
view of the national worker, qualified, male and over thirty-five."40 A
|
||
determination different from that of the constant will therefore be consid-
|
||
ered minoritarian, by nature and regardless of number, in other words, a
|
||
subsystem or an outsystem. This is evident in all the operations, electoral
|
||
or otherwise, where you are given a choice, but on the condition that your
|
||
choice conform to the limits of the constant ("you mustn't choose to
|
||
change society..."). But at this point, everything is reversed. For the
|
||
majority, insofar as it is analytically included in the abstract standard, is
|
||
never anybody, it is always Nobody—Ulysses—whereas the minority is
|
||
the becoming of everybody, one's potential becoming to the extent that one
|
||
deviates from the model. There is a majoritarian "fact," but it is the ana-
|
||
lytic fact of Nobody, as opposed to the becoming-minoritarian of every-
|
||
body. That is why we must distinguish between: the majoritarian as a
|
||
constant and homogeneous system; minorities as subsystems; and the
|
||
106 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
minoritarian as a potential, creative and created, becoming. The problem
|
||
is never to acquire the majority, even in order to install a new constant.
|
||
There is no becoming-majoritarian; majority is never becoming. All
|
||
becoming is minoritarian. Women, regardless of their numbers, are a
|
||
minority, definable as a state or subset; but they create only by making pos-
|
||
sible a becoming over which they do not have ownership, into which they
|
||
themselves must enter; this is a becoming-woman affecting all of human-
|
||
kind, men and women both. The same goes for minor languages: they are
|
||
not simply sublanguages, idiolects or dialects, but potential agents of the
|
||
major language's entering into a becoming-minoritarian of all of its dimen-
|
||
sions and elements. We should distinguish between minor languages, the
|
||
major language, and the becoming-minor of the major language. Minori-
|
||
ties, of course, are objectively definable states, states of language, ethnicity,
|
||
or sex with their own ghetto territorialities, but they must also be thought
|
||
of as seeds, crystals of becoming whose value is to trigger uncontrollable
|
||
movements and deterritorializations of the mean or majority. That is why
|
||
Pasolini demonstrated that the essential thing, precisely in free indirect
|
||
discourse, is to be found neither in language A, nor in language B, but "in
|
||
language X, which is none other than language A in the actual process of
|
||
becoming language B."41 There is a universal figure of minoritarian con-
|
||
sciousness as the becoming of everybody, and that becoming is creation.
|
||
One does not attain it by acquiring the majority. The figure to which we are
|
||
referring is continuous variation, as an amplitude that continually over-
|
||
steps the representative threshold of the majoritarian standard, by excess
|
||
or default. In erecting the figure of a universal minoritarian consciousness,
|
||
one addresses powers (puissances) of becoming that belong to a different
|
||
realm from that of Power (Pouvoir) and Domination. Continuous variation
|
||
constitutes the becoming-minoritarian of everybody, as opposed to the
|
||
majoritarian Fact of Nobody. Becoming-minoritarian as the universal fig-
|
||
ure of consciousness is called autonomy. It is certainly not by using a minor
|
||
language as a dialect, by regionalizing or ghettoizing, that one becomes
|
||
revolutionary; rather, by using a number of minority elements, by connect-
|
||
ing, conjugating them, one invents a specific, unforeseen, autonomous be-
|
||
coming.42
|
||
The major and minor mode are two different treatments of language,
|
||
one of which consists in extracting constants from it, the other in placing it
|
||
in continuous variation. The order-word is the variable of enunciation that
|
||
effectuates the condition of possibility of language and defines the usage of
|
||
its elements according to one of the two treatments; we must therefore
|
||
return to it as the only "metalanguage" capable of accounting for this dou-
|
||
ble direction, this double treatment of variables. The problem of the func-
|
||
tions of language is in general poorly formulated because this order-word
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 107
|
||
|
||
variable, which subsumes all possible functions, is overlooked. Following
|
||
Canetti's suggestions, we may begin from the following pragmatic situa-
|
||
tion: the order-word is a death sentence; it always implies a death sentence,
|
||
even if it has been considerably softened, becoming symbolic, initiatory,
|
||
temporary, etc. Order-words bring immediate death to those who receive
|
||
the order, or potential death if they do not obey, or a death they must them-
|
||
selves inflict, take elsewhere. A father's orders to his son, "You will do
|
||
this," "You will not do that," cannot be separated from the little death sen-
|
||
tence the son experiences on a point of his person. Death, death; it is the
|
||
only judgment, and it is what makes judgment a system. The verdict. But
|
||
the order-word is also something else, inseparably connected: it is like a
|
||
warning cry or a message to flee. It would be oversimplifying to say that
|
||
flight is a reaction against the order-word; rather, it is included in it, as its
|
||
other face in a complex assemblage, its other component. Canetti is right to
|
||
invoke the lion's roar, which enunciates flight and death simultaneously.43
|
||
The order-word has two tones. The prophet receives order-words just as
|
||
much in taking flight as in longing for death: Jewish prophetism fused the
|
||
wish to be dead and the flight impulse with the divine order-word.
|
||
Now if we consider the first aspect of the order-word, in other words,
|
||
death as the expressed of the statement, it clearly meets the preceding
|
||
requirements: even though death essentially concerns bodies, is attributed
|
||
to bodies, its immediacy, its instantaneousness, lends it the authentic char-
|
||
acter of an incorporeal transformation. What precedes and follows it may
|
||
be an extensive system of actions and passions, a slow labor of bodies; in
|
||
itself, it is neither action nor passion, but a pure act, a pure transformation
|
||
that enunciation fuses with the statement, the sentence. That man is dead
|
||
. . . You are already dead when you receive the order-word ... In effect,
|
||
death is everywhere, as that ideal, uncrossable boundary separating bod-
|
||
ies, their forms, and states, and as the condition, even initiatory, even sym-
|
||
bolic, through which a subject must pass in order to change its form or
|
||
state. This is the sense in which Canetti speaks of "enantiomorphosis":44 a
|
||
regime that involves a hieratic and immutable Master who at every
|
||
moment legislates by constants, prohibiting or strictly limiting metamor-
|
||
phoses, giving figures clear and stable contours, setting forms in opposi-
|
||
tion two by two and requiring subjects to die in order to pass from one form
|
||
to the other. It is always by means of something incorporeal that a body sep-
|
||
arates and distinguishes itself from another. The figure, insofar as it is the
|
||
extremity of a body, is the noncorporeal attribute that limits and completes
|
||
that body: death is the Figure. It is through death that a body reaches com-
|
||
pletion not only in time but in space, and it is through death that its lines
|
||
form or outline a shape. There are dead spaces just as there are dead times.
|
||
"If [enantiomorphosis is] practiced often the whole world shrivels....
|
||
108 D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
Social prohibitions against metamorphosis are perhaps the most impor-
|
||
tant of all. . . . Death itself, the strictest of all boundaries, is what is inter-
|
||
posed between classes."45 In a regime of this kind, any new body requires
|
||
the erection of an opposable form, as well as the formation of distinct sub-
|
||
jects; death is the general incorporeal transformation attributed to all bod-
|
||
ies from the standpoint of their forms and substances (for example, the
|
||
body of the Party cannot come into its own without an operation of
|
||
enantiomorphosis, and without the formation of new activists, which
|
||
assumes the elimination of the first generation).
|
||
It is true that we are bringing in considerations of content as well as
|
||
expression. For even at the moment when the two planes are most distinct,
|
||
as the regime of bodies and the regime of signs in an assemblage, they are
|
||
still in reciprocal presupposition. The incorporeal transformation is the
|
||
expressed of order-words, but also the attribute of bodies. Not only do lin-
|
||
guistic variables of expression enter into relations of formal opposition or
|
||
distinction favorable to the extraction of constants; nonlinguistic variables
|
||
of content do also. As Hjelmslev notes, an expression is divided, for exam-
|
||
ple, into phonic units in the same way a content is divided into social, zoo-
|
||
logical, or physical units ("calf divides into young-bovine-male).46 The
|
||
network of binarities, or arborescences, is applicable to both sides. There
|
||
is, however, no analytic resemblance, correspondence, or conformity
|
||
between the two planes. But their independence does not preclude isomor-
|
||
phism, in other words, the existence of the same kind of constant relations
|
||
on both sides. It is by virtue of this type of relations that linguistic and
|
||
nonlinguistic elements are inseparable from the start, despite their absence
|
||
of correspondence. The elements of content give the interminglings of bod-
|
||
ies clear contours at the same time as the elements of expression give the
|
||
noncorporeal expresseds a power of sentencing or judgment. These ele-
|
||
ments are all abstract or deterritorialized to different degrees, but in each
|
||
instance they effect a reterritorialization of the overall assemblage on cer-
|
||
tain order-words and contours. Indeed, the significance of the doctrine of
|
||
synthetic judgment is to have demonstrated that there is an a priori link
|
||
(isomorphism) between Sentence and Figure, form of expression and form
|
||
of content.
|
||
If we consider the other aspect of the order-word, flight rather than
|
||
death, it appears that variables are in a new state, that of continuous varia-
|
||
tion. An incorporeal transformation is still attributed to bodies, but it is
|
||
now a passage to the limit: that is the only way, not to eliminate death, but
|
||
to reduce it or make it a variation itself. This movement pushes language to
|
||
its own limits, while bodies are simultaneously caught up in a movement of
|
||
metamorphosis of their contents or a process of exhaustion causing them
|
||
to reach or overstep the limit of their figures. This is an appropriate place to
|
||
NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS D 109
|
||
|
||
bring up the opposition between minor sciences and major sciences: for
|
||
example, the tendency of the broken line to become a curve, a whole opera-
|
||
tive geometry of the trait and movement, a pragmatic science of placings-
|
||
in-variation that operates in a different manner than the royal or major
|
||
science of Euclid's invariants and travels a long history of suspicion and
|
||
even repression (we will return to this question later).47 The smallest inter-
|
||
val is always diabolical: the master of metamorphoses is opposed to the
|
||
invariant hieratic king. It is as though an intense matter or a continuum of
|
||
variation were freed, here in the internal tensors of language, there in the
|
||
internal tensions of content. The idea of the smallest interval does not
|
||
apply to figures of the same nature; it implies at least a curve and a straight
|
||
line, a circle and a tangent. We witness a transformation of substances and
|
||
a dissolution of forms, a passage to the limit or flight from contours in favor
|
||
of fluid forces, flows, air, light, and matter, such that a body or a word does
|
||
not end at a precise point. We witness the incorporeal power of that intense
|
||
matter, the material power of that language. A matter more immediate,
|
||
more fluid, and more ardent than bodies or words. In continuous variation
|
||
the relevant distinction is no longer between a form of expression and a
|
||
form of content but between two inseparable planes in reciprocal presup-
|
||
position. The relativity of the distinction between them is now fully rea-
|
||
lized on the plane of consistency, where the assemblage is swept up by a
|
||
now absolute deterritorialization. Absolute, however, does not mean
|
||
undifferentiated: differences, now "infinitely small," are constituted in a
|
||
single matter serving both for expression as incorporeal power and for con-
|
||
tent as limitless corporeality. The relation of presupposition between vari-
|
||
ables of content and expression no longer requires two forms: the
|
||
placing-in-variation of the variables instead draws the two forms together
|
||
and effects the conjunction of cutting edges of deterritorialization on both
|
||
sides; this occurs on the plane of a single liberated matter that contains no
|
||
figures, is deliberately unformed, and retains in expression and in content
|
||
only those cutting edges, tensors, and tensions. Gestures and things, voices
|
||
and sounds, are caught up in the same "opera," swept away by the same
|
||
shifting effects of stammering, vibrato, tremolo, and overspilling. A syn-
|
||
thesizer places all of the parameters in continuous variation, gradually
|
||
making "fundamentally heterogeneous elements end up turning into each
|
||
other in some way." The moment this conjunction occurs there is a com-
|
||
mon matter. It is only at this point that one reaches the abstract machine, or
|
||
the diagram of the assemblage. The synthesizer has replaced judgment,
|
||
and matter has replaced the figure or formed substance. It is no longer even
|
||
appropriate to group biological, physicochemical, and energetic intensi-
|
||
ties on the one hand, and mathematical, aesthetic, linguistic, informa-
|
||
tional, semiotic intensities, etc., on the other. The multiplicity of systems
|
||
H O D NOVEMBER 20, 1923: POSTULATES OF LINGUISTICS
|
||
|
||
of intensities conjugates or forms a rhizome throughout the entire assem-
|
||
blage the moment the assemblage is swept up by these vectors or tensions of
|
||
flight. For the question was not how to elude the order-word but how to
|
||
elude the death sentence it envelops, how to develop its power of escape,
|
||
how to prevent escape from veering into the imaginary or falling into a
|
||
black hole, how to maintain or draw out the revolutionary potentiality of
|
||
the order-word. Hofmannsthal adopts the order-word, "Germany, Ger-
|
||
many!", or the need to reterritorialize, even in a "melancholy mirror." But
|
||
beneath this order-word he hears another, as if the old German "figures"
|
||
were mere constants that were then effaced to uncover a relation with
|
||
nature and life all the more profound for being variable. When should this
|
||
relation to life be a hardening, when submission? At what moment is rebel-
|
||
lion called for and at what moment surrender or impassibility? When is dry
|
||
speech necessary and when exuberance or amusement?48 Whatever the
|
||
breaks and ruptures, only continuous variation brings forth this virtual
|
||
line, this virtual continuum of life, "the essential element of the real
|
||
beneath the everyday." There is a splendid statement in one of Herzog's
|
||
films. The main character asks himself a question and then says, Who will
|
||
answer this answer? Actually, there is no question, answers are all one ever
|
||
answers. To the answer already contained in a question (cross-exam-
|
||
ination, competition, plebiscite, etc.) one should respond with questions
|
||
from another answer. One should bring forth the order-word of the order-
|
||
word. In the order-word, life must answer the answer of death, not by flee-
|
||
ing, but by making flight act and create. There are pass-words beneath
|
||
order-words. Words that pass, words that are components of passage,
|
||
whereas order-words mark stoppages or organized, stratified composi-
|
||
tions. A single thing or word undoubtedly has this twofold nature: it is nec-
|
||
essary to extract one from the other—to transform the compositions of
|
||
order into components of passage.
|
||
5. 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: On Several Regimes
|
||
of Signs
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
The Order of the Ark of the Israelites
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
A New Regime
|
||
|
||
We call any specific formalization of expression a regime of signs, at least
|
||
when the expression is linguistic. A regime of signs constitutes a semiotic
|
||
system. But it appears difficult to analyze semiotic systems in themselves:
|
||
there is always a form of content that is simultaneously inseparable from
|
||
and independent of the form of expression, and the two forms pertain to
|
||
assemblages that are not principally linguistic. However, one can proceed
|
||
as though the formalization of expression were autonomous and self-
|
||
sufficient. Even if that is done, there is such diversity in the forms of
|
||
expression, such a mixture of these forms, that it is impossible to attach
|
||
any particular privilege to the form or regime of the "signifier." If we call
|
||
the signifying semiotic system semiology, then semiology is only one
|
||
regime of signs among others, and not the most important one. Hence the
|
||
necessity of a return to pragmatics, in which language never has universal-
|
||
ity in itself, self-sufficient formalization, a general semiology, or a meta-
|
||
111
|
||
112 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
language. Thus it is the study of the signifying regime that first testifies to
|
||
the inadequacy of linguistic presuppositions, and in the very name of
|
||
regimes of signs.
|
||
There is a simple general formula for the signifying regime of the sign
|
||
(the signifying sign): every sign refers to another sign, and only to another
|
||
sign, ad infinitum. That is why, at the limit, one can forgo the notion of the
|
||
sign, for what is retained is not principally the sign's relation to a state of
|
||
things it designates, or to an entity it signifies, but only the formal relation
|
||
of sign to sign insofar as it defines a so-called signifying chain. The
|
||
limitlessness of signifiance replaces the sign. When denotation (here, des-
|
||
ignation and signification taken together) is assumed to be part of connota-
|
||
tion, one is wholly within this signifying regime of the sign. Not much
|
||
attention is paid to indexes, in other words, the territorial states of things
|
||
constituting the designatable. Not much attention is paid to icons, that is,
|
||
operations of reterritorialization constituting the signifiable. Thus the sign
|
||
has already attained a high degree of relative deterritorialization; it is
|
||
thought of as a symbol in a constant movement of referral from sign to sign.
|
||
The signifier is the sign in redundancy with the sign. All signs are signs of
|
||
signs. The question is not yet what a given sign signifies but to which other
|
||
signs it refers, or which signs add themselves to it to form a network with-
|
||
out beginning or end that projects its shadow onto an amorphous atmo-
|
||
spheric continuum. It is this amorphous continuum that for the moment
|
||
plays the role of the "signified," but it continually glides beneath the
|
||
signifier, for which it serves only as a medium or wall: the specific forms of
|
||
all contents dissolve in it. The atmospherization or mundanization of con-
|
||
tents. Contents are abstracted. This is the situation Levi-Strauss describes:
|
||
the world begins to signify before anyone knows what it signifies; the signi-
|
||
fied is given without being known.1 Your wife looked at you with a funny
|
||
expression. And this morning the mailman handed you a letter from the
|
||
IRS and crossed his fingers. Then you stepped in a pile of dog shit. You saw
|
||
two sticks on the sidewalk positioned like the hands of a watch. They were
|
||
whispering behind your back when you arrived at the office. It doesn't mat-
|
||
ter what it means, it's still signifying. The sign that refers to other signs is
|
||
struck with a strange impotence and uncertainty, but mighty is the signifier
|
||
that constitutes the chain. The paranoiac shares this impotence of the
|
||
deterritorialized sign assailing him from every direction in the gliding
|
||
atmosphere, but that only gives him better access to the superpower of the
|
||
signifier, through the royal feeling of wrath, as master of the network
|
||
spreading through the atmosphere. The paranoid despotic regime: they are
|
||
attacking me and making me suffer, but I can guess what they're up to, I'm
|
||
one step ahead of them, I've always known, I have power even in my impo-
|
||
tence. "I'll get them."
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 113
|
||
|
||
Nothing is ever over and done with in a regime of this kind. It's made for
|
||
that, it's the tragic regime of infinite debt, to which one is simultaneously
|
||
debtor and creditor. A sign refers to another sign, into which it passes and
|
||
which carries it into still other signs. "To the point that it returns in a circu-
|
||
lar fashion ..." Not only do signs form an infinite network, but the net-
|
||
work of signs is infinitely circular. The statement survives its object, the
|
||
name survives its owner. Whether it passes into other signs or is kept in
|
||
reserve for a time, the sign survives both its state of things and its signified;
|
||
it leaps like an animal or a dead person to regain its place in the chain and
|
||
invest a new state, a new signified, from which it will in turn extricate
|
||
itself.2 A hint of the eternal return. There is a whole regime of roving, float-
|
||
ing statements, suspended names, signs lying in wait to return and be
|
||
propelled by the chain. The signifier as the self-redundancy of the deterri-
|
||
torialized sign, a funereal world of terror.
|
||
But what counts is less this circularity of signs than the multiplicity of
|
||
the circles or chains. The sign refers not only to other signs in the same cir-
|
||
cle, but to signs in other circles or spirals as well. Robert Lowie describes
|
||
how Crow and Hopi men react differently when their wives cheat on them
|
||
(the Crow are nomadic hunters and the Hopi sedentaries with an imperial
|
||
tradition): "A Crow Indian whose wife has cheated on him slashes her face,
|
||
whereas the Hopi who has fallen victim to the same misfortune, without
|
||
losing his calm, withdraws and prays for drought and famine to descend on
|
||
the village." It is easy to see where the paranoia resides, the despotic ele-
|
||
ment or signifying regime, or again, as Levi-Strauss says, "the bigotry": "In
|
||
effect, for a Hopi everything is connected: a social disturbance or a domes-
|
||
tic incident calls into question the system of the universe, the levels of
|
||
which are united by multiple correspondences; a disruption on one plane is
|
||
only intelligible, and morally tolerable, as a projection of other disruptions
|
||
involving other levels."3 The Hopi jump from one circle to another, or from
|
||
one sign to another on a different spiral. One leaves the village or the city,
|
||
only to return. The jumps may be regulated not only by presignifying ritu-
|
||
als but also by a whole imperial bureaucracy passing judgment on their
|
||
legitimacy. The jumps are not made at random, they are not without rules.
|
||
Not only are they regulated, but some are prohibited: Do not overstep the
|
||
outermost circle, do not approach the innermost circle .. . There is a dis-
|
||
tinction between circles because, although all signs refer to each other only
|
||
to the extent that they are deterritorialized, oriented toward the same cen-
|
||
ter of signifiance, distributed throughout an amorphous continuum, they
|
||
have different speeds of deterritorialization attesting to a place of origin
|
||
(temple, palace, house, street, village, bush, etc.), and they have differential
|
||
relations maintaining the distinction between circles or constituting
|
||
thresholds in the atmosphere of the continuum (private and public, family
|
||
114 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
incident and social disorder). Moreover, the distribution of these thresh-
|
||
olds and circles changes according to the case. Deception is fundamental to
|
||
the system. Jumping from circle to circle, always moving the scene, playing
|
||
it out somewhere else: such is the hysteric operation of the deceiver as sub-
|
||
ject, answering to the paranoid operation of the despot installed in his cen-
|
||
ter of signifiance.
|
||
There is one other aspect: the signifying regime is not simply faced with
|
||
the task of organizing into circles signs emitted from every direction; it
|
||
must constantly assure the expansion of the circles or spiral, it must pro-
|
||
vide the center with more signifier to overcome the entropy inherent in the
|
||
system and to make new circles blossom or replenish the old. Thus a secon-
|
||
dary mechanism in the service of signifiance is necessary: interpretance or
|
||
interpretation. This time the signifier assumes a new figure: it is no longer
|
||
the amorphous continuum that is given without being known and across
|
||
which the network of signs is strung. A portion of signified is made to corre-
|
||
spond to a sign or group of signs for which that signified has been deemed
|
||
suitable, thus making it knowable. To the syntagmatic axis of the sign refer-
|
||
ring to other signs is added a paradigmatic axis on which the sign, thus for-
|
||
malized, fashions for itself a suitable signified (once again there is
|
||
abstraction of the content, but in a new way). The interpretive priest, the
|
||
seer, is one of the despot-god's bureaucrats. A new aspect of deception
|
||
arises, the deception of the priest: interpretation is carried to infinity and
|
||
never encounters anything to interpret that is not already itself an interpre-
|
||
tation. The signified constantly reimparts signifier, recharges it or pro-
|
||
duces more of it. The form always comes from the signifier. The ultimate
|
||
signified is therefore the signifier itself, in its redundancy or "excess." It is
|
||
perfectly futile to claim to transcend interpretation or even communica-
|
||
tion through the production of signifier, because communication and
|
||
interpretation are what always serve to reproduce and produce signifier.
|
||
That is certainly not the way to revive the notion of production. The dis-
|
||
covery of the psychoanalyst-priests (a discovery every kind of priest or seer
|
||
made in their time) was that interpretation had to be subordinated to
|
||
signifiance, to the point that the signifier would impart no signified with-
|
||
out the signified reimparting signifier in its turn. Actually, there is no
|
||
longer even any need to interpret, but that is because the best interpreta-
|
||
tion, the weightiest and most radical one, is an eminently significant
|
||
silence. It is well known that although psychoanalysts have ceased to speak,
|
||
they interpret even more, or better yet, fuel interpretation on the part of the
|
||
subject, who jumps from one circle of hell to the next. In truth, signifiance
|
||
and interpretosis are the two diseases of the earth or the skin, in other
|
||
words, humankind's fundamental neurosis.
|
||
There is not much to say about the center of signifiance, or the Signifier
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 115
|
||
|
||
in person, because it is a pure abstraction no less than a pure principle; in
|
||
other words, it is nothing. Lack or excess, it hardly matters. It comes to the
|
||
same thing to say that the sign refers to other signs ad inf initum and that the
|
||
infinite set of all signs refers to a supreme signifier. At any rate, this pure
|
||
formal redundancy of the signifier could not even be conceptualized if it
|
||
did not have its own substance of expression, for which we must find a
|
||
name: faciality. Not only is language always accompanied by faciality
|
||
traits, but the face crystallizes all redundancies, it emits and receives,
|
||
releases and recaptures signifying signs. It is a whole body unto itself: it is
|
||
like the body of the center of signifiance to which all of the deterritorialized
|
||
signs affix themselves, and it marks the limit of their deterritorialization.
|
||
The voice emanates from the face; that is why, however fundamentally
|
||
important the writing machine is in the imperial bureaucracy, what is writ-
|
||
ten retains an oral or nonbook character. The face is the Icon proper to the
|
||
signifying regime, the reterritorialization internal to the system. The
|
||
signifier reterritorializes on the face. The face is what gives the signifier
|
||
substance; it is what fuels interpretation, and it is what changes, changes
|
||
traits, when interpretation reimparts signifier to its substance. Look, his
|
||
expression changed. The signifier is always facialized. Faciality reigns
|
||
materially over that whole constellation of signifiances and interpretations
|
||
(psychologists have written extensively on the baby's relations to the moth-
|
||
er's face, and sociologists on the role of the face in mass media and adver-
|
||
tising). The despot-god has never hidden his face, far from it: he makes
|
||
himself one, or even several. The mask does not hide the face, it is the face.
|
||
The priest administers the face of the god. With the despot, everything is
|
||
public, and everything that is public is so by virtue of the face. Lies and
|
||
deception may be a fundamental part of the signifying regime, but secrecy
|
||
is not.4 Conversely, when the face is effaced, when the faciality traits dis-
|
||
appear, we can be sure that we have entered another regime, other zones
|
||
infinitely muter and more imperceptible where subterranean becomings-
|
||
animal occur, becomings-molecular, nocturnal deterritorializations over-
|
||
spilling the limits of the signifying system. The despot or god brandishes
|
||
the solar face that is his entire body, as the body of the signifier. He looked
|
||
at me queerly, he knitted his brow, what did I do to make him change
|
||
expression? I have her picture in front of me, it's as if she were watching me
|
||
... Surveillance by the face, as Strindberg said. Overcoding by the signifier,
|
||
irradiation in all directions, unlocalized omnipresence.
|
||
Finally, the face or body of the despot or god has something like a
|
||
counterbody: the body of the tortured, or better, of the excluded. There is
|
||
no question that these two bodies communicate, for the body of the despot
|
||
is sometimes subjected to trials of humiliation or even torture, or of exile
|
||
and exclusion. "At the opposite pole one might imagine placing the body of
|
||
116 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
the condemned man; he, too, has his legal status; he gives rise to his own
|
||
ceremonial... not in order to ground the surplus power possessed by the
|
||
person of the sovereign, but in order to code the lack of power with which
|
||
those subjected to punishment are marked. In the darkest region of the
|
||
political field the condemned man outlines the symmetrical, inverted fig-
|
||
ure of the king."5 The one who is tortured is fundamentally one who loses
|
||
his or her face, entering into a becoming-animal, a becoming-molecular the
|
||
ashes of which are thrown to the wind. But it appears that the one who is
|
||
tortured is not at all the final term, but rather the first step before exclu-
|
||
sion. Oedipus, at least, understood that. He tortured himself, gouged out
|
||
his own eyes, then went away. The rite, the becoming-animal of the scape-
|
||
goat clearly illustrates this: a first expiatory animal is sacrificed, but a sec-
|
||
ond is driven away, sent out into the desert wilderness. In the signifying
|
||
regime, the scapegoat represents a new form of increasing entropy in the
|
||
system of signs: it is charged with everything that was "bad" in a given
|
||
period, that is, everything that resisted signifying signs, everything that
|
||
eluded the referral from sign to sign through the different circles; it also
|
||
assumes everything that was unable to recharge the signifier at its center
|
||
and carries off everything that spills beyond the outermost circle. Finally,
|
||
and especially, it incarnates that line of flight the signifying regime cannot
|
||
tolerate, in other words, an absolute deterritorialization; the regime must
|
||
block a line of this kind or define it in an entirely negative fashion precisely
|
||
because it exceeds the degree of deterritorialization of the signifying sign,
|
||
however high it may be. The line of flight is like a tangent to the circles of
|
||
signifiance and the center of the signifier. It is under a curse. The goat's
|
||
anus stands opposite the face of the despot or god. Anything that threatens
|
||
to put the system to flight will be killed or put to flight itself. Anything that
|
||
exceeds the excess of the signifier or passes beneath it will be marked with a
|
||
negative value. Your only choice will be between a goat's ass and the face of
|
||
the god, between sorcerers and priests. The complete system, then, consists
|
||
of the paranoid face or body of the despot-god in the signifying center of the
|
||
temple; the interpreting priests who continually recharge the signified in
|
||
the temple, transforming it into signifier; the hysterical crowd of people
|
||
outside, clumped in tight circles, who jump from one circle to another; the
|
||
faceless, depressive scapegoat emanating from the center, chosen, treated,
|
||
and adorned by the priests, cutting across the circles in its headlong flight
|
||
into the desert. This excessively hasty overview is applicable not only to the
|
||
imperial despotic regime but to all subjected, arborescent, hierarchical,
|
||
centered groups: political parties, literary movements, psychoanalytic
|
||
associations, families, conjugal units, etc. The photo, faciality, redun-
|
||
dancy, signifiance, and interpretation are at work everywhere. The dreary
|
||
world of the signifier; its archaism with an always contemporary function;
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 117
|
||
|
||
its essential deception, connoting all of its aspects; its profound antics.
|
||
The signifier reigns over every domestic squabble, and in every State
|
||
apparatus.
|
||
The signifying regime of the sign is defined by eight aspects or princi-
|
||
ples: (1) the sign refers to another sign, ad infinitum (the limitlessness of
|
||
signifiance, which deterritorializes the sign); (2) the sign is brought back by
|
||
other signs and never ceases to return (the circularity of the deterrito-
|
||
rialized sign); (3) the sign jumps from circle to circle and constantly dis-
|
||
places the center at the same time as it ties into it (the metaphor or hysteria
|
||
of signs); (4) the expansion of the circles is assured by interpretations that
|
||
impart signified and reimpart signifier (the interpretosis of the priest); (5)
|
||
the infinite set of signs refers to a supreme signifier presenting itself as both
|
||
lack and excess (the despotic signifier, the limit of the system's deterrito-
|
||
rialization); (6) the form of the signifier has a substance, or the signifier has
|
||
a body, namely, the Face (the principle of faciality traits, which constitute a
|
||
reterritorialization); (7) the system's line of flight is assigned a negative
|
||
value, condemned as that which exceeds the signifying regime's power of
|
||
deterritorialization (the principle of the scapegoat); (8) the regime is one of
|
||
universal deception, in its jumps, in the regulated circles, in the seer's regu-
|
||
lation of interpretations, in the publicness of the facialized center, and in
|
||
the treatment of the line of flight.
|
||
Not only is this semiotic system not the first, but we see no reason to
|
||
accord it any particular privilege from the standpoint of an abstract evolu-
|
||
tionism. We would like to indicate very briefly certain characteristics of the
|
||
other two semiotic systems. First, the so-called primitive, presignifying
|
||
semiotic, which is much closer to "natural" codings operating without
|
||
signs. There is no reduction to faciality as the sole substance of expression:
|
||
there is no elimination of forms of content through abstraction of the signi-
|
||
fied. To the extent that there is still abstraction of content from a strictly
|
||
semiotic point of view, it fosters a pluralism or polyvocality of forms of
|
||
expression that prevents any power takeover by the signifier and preserves
|
||
expressive forms particular to content; thus forms of corporeality,
|
||
gesturality, rhythm, dance, and rite coexist heterogeneously with the vocal
|
||
form.6 A variety of forms and substances of expression intersect and form
|
||
relays. It is a segmentary but plurilinear, multidimensional semiotic that
|
||
wards off any kind of signifying circularity. Segmentarity is the law of the
|
||
lineages. Here, the sign owes its degree of relative deterritorialization not
|
||
to a perpetual referral to other signs but rather to a confrontation between
|
||
the territorialities and compared segments from which each sign is
|
||
extracted (the camp, the bush, the moving of the camp). Not only is the
|
||
polyvocality of statements preserved, but it is possible to finish with a
|
||
statement: A name that has been used up is abolished, a situation quite
|
||
118 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
unlike the placing in reserve or transformation occurring in the signifying
|
||
semiotic. The meaning of cannibalism in a presignifying regime is pre-
|
||
cisely this: eating the name, a semiography that is fully a part of a semiotic
|
||
in spite of its relation to content (the relation is an expressive one).7 It
|
||
should not be thought that a semiotic of this kind functions by ignorance,
|
||
repression, or foreclosure of the signifier. On the contrary, it is animated by
|
||
a keen presentiment of what is to come. It does not need to understand it to
|
||
fight against it. It is wholly destined by its very segmentarity and poly-
|
||
vocality to avert the already-present threat: universalizing abstraction,
|
||
erection of the signifier, circularity of statements, and their correlates, the
|
||
State apparatus, the instatement of the despot, the priestly caste, the scape-
|
||
goat, etc. Every time they eat a dead man, they can say: one more the State
|
||
won't get.
|
||
There is another semiotic, the countersignifying semiotic (whose most
|
||
notable representatives are the fearsome, warlike, and animal-raising
|
||
nomads, as opposed to hunter nomads, who belong to the previous
|
||
semiotic). This time, the semiotic proceeds less by segmentarity than by
|
||
arithmetic and numeration. Of course, the number already played a role of
|
||
great importance in the division and union of segmentary lineages; it also
|
||
had a function of decisive importance in the signifying imperial bureau-
|
||
cracy. But that was a kind of number that represented or signified, a num-
|
||
ber "incited, produced, caused by something other than itself." On the
|
||
contrary, a numerical sign that is not produced by something outside the
|
||
system of marking it institutes, which marks a mobile and plural distribu-
|
||
tion, which itself determines functions and relations, which arrives at
|
||
arrangements rather than totals, distributions rather than collections,
|
||
which operates more by breaks, transitions, migration, and accumulation
|
||
than by combining units—a sign of this kind would appear to belong to the
|
||
semiotic of a nomad war machine directed against the State apparatus. The
|
||
numbering number.8 Its numerical organization into tens, fifties, hun-
|
||
dreds, thousands, etc., and the associated spatial organization were obvi-
|
||
ously adopted by State armies, but basically bear witness to a military
|
||
system specific to the great nomads of the steppes, from the Hyksos to the
|
||
Mongols. They were superposed upon the principle of lineage. Secrecy and
|
||
spying are important elements of the war machine's semiotic of Numbers.
|
||
The role of Numbers in the Bible is not unrelated to the nomads, since
|
||
Moses got the idea from his father-in-law, Jethro the Kenite: he used it as an
|
||
organizational principle for the march and migration, and applied it him-
|
||
self to the military domain. In this countersignifying regime, the imperial
|
||
despotic line of flight is replaced by a line of abolition that turns back
|
||
against the great empires, cuts across them and destroys them, or else con-
|
||
quers them and integrates with them to form a mixed semiotic.
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 119
|
||
|
||
We would like to go into greater detail on a fourth regime of signs, the
|
||
postsignifying regime, which has different characteristics opposing it to
|
||
signifiance and is defined by a unique procedure, that of "subjecti-
|
||
fication."
|
||
There are many regimes of signs. Our own list is arbitrarily limited.
|
||
There is no reason to identify a regime or a semiotic system with a people
|
||
or historical moment. There is such mixture within the same period or the
|
||
same people that we can say no more than that a given people, language,
|
||
or period assures the relative dominance of a certain regime. Perhaps all
|
||
semiotics are mixed and not only combine with various forms of content
|
||
but also combine different regimes of signs. Presignifying elements are
|
||
always active in the signifying regime; countersignifying elements are
|
||
always present and at work within it; and postsignifying elements are
|
||
already there. Even that is to mark too much temporality. The semiotics
|
||
and their mixtures may appear in a history of confrontation and inter-
|
||
mingling of peoples, but also in languages in which there are several com-
|
||
peting functions, or in a psychiatric hospital in which different forms of
|
||
insanity coexist among the patients or even combine in a single patient; or
|
||
in an ordinary conversation in which people are speaking the same
|
||
tongue but different languages (all of a sudden a fragment of an unex-
|
||
pected semiotic surfaces). We are not suggesting an evolutionism, we are
|
||
not even doing history. Semiotic systems depend on assemblages, and it is
|
||
the assemblages that determine that a given people, period, or language,
|
||
and even a given style, fashion, pathology, or minuscule event in a limited
|
||
situation, can assure the predominance of one semiotic or another. We
|
||
are trying to make maps of regimes of signs: we can turn them around or
|
||
retain selected coordinates or dimensions, and depending on the case we
|
||
will be dealing with a social formation, a pathological delusion (d'elire), a
|
||
historical event, etc. We will see this on another occasion when we deal
|
||
with a dated social system, "courtly love," and then switch to a private
|
||
enterprise called "masochism." We can also combine maps or separate
|
||
them. To make the distinction between two types of semiotics (for exam-
|
||
ple, the postsignifying regime and the signifying regime), we must con-
|
||
sider very diverse domains simultaneously.
|
||
In the first years of the twentieth century, psychiatry, at the height of its
|
||
clinical skills, confronted the problem of nonhallucinatory delusions in
|
||
which mental integrity is retained without "intellectual diminishment."
|
||
There was a first major grouping, paranoid or interpretive delusions,
|
||
which already subsumed various aspects. But the question of the possible
|
||
independence of another group was prefigured in Esquirol's monomania
|
||
and Kraepelin's querulous delusion, and later defined by Serieux and
|
||
Capgras as grievance delusion, and by Clerambault as passional delusion
|
||
120 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
("querulousness or seeking redress, jealousy, erotomania"). Basing our-
|
||
selves on very fine studies of Serieux and Capgras on the one hand, and
|
||
Clerambault on the other (the latter took the distinction furthest), we will
|
||
contrast a paranoid-interpretive ideal regime of signifiance with a
|
||
passional, postsignifying subjective regime. The first regime is defined by
|
||
an insidious onset and a hidden center bearing witness to endogenous
|
||
forces organized around an idea; by the development of a network stretch-
|
||
ing across an amorphous continuum, a gliding atmosphere into which the
|
||
slightest incident may be carried; by an organization of radiating circles
|
||
expanding by circular irradiation in all directions, and in which the indi-
|
||
vidual jumps from one point to another, one circle to another, approaches
|
||
the center then moves away, operates prospectively and retrospectively;
|
||
and by a transformation of the atmosphere, as a function of variable traits
|
||
or secondary centers clustered around a principal nucleus. The second
|
||
regime, on the contrary, is defined by a decisive external occurrence, by a
|
||
relation with the outside that is expressed more as an emotion than an idea,
|
||
and more as effort or action than imagination ("active delusion rather than
|
||
ideational delusion"); by a limited constellation operating in a single sec-
|
||
tor, by a "postulate" or "concise formula" serving as the point of departure
|
||
for a linear series or proceeding that runs its course, at which point a new
|
||
proceeding begins. In short, it operates by the linear and temporal succes-
|
||
sion of finite proceedings, rather than by the simultaneity of circles in unlim-
|
||
ited expansion.9
|
||
This story of two kinds of delusions without intellectual diminishment
|
||
is of great importance. For it is not a disruption of a preexisting discipline
|
||
of psychiatry; it lies at the heart of the constitution of the psychiatrist in the
|
||
nineteenth century and explains why he or she was from the start what he
|
||
or she has been ever since: the psychiatrist was born cornered, caught
|
||
between legal, police, humanitarian demands, accused of not being a true
|
||
doctor, suspected of mistaking the sane for mad and the mad for sane, prey
|
||
to quandaries of conscience, the last Hegelian belle ame. If we consider the
|
||
two types of intact delusions, we can say that people in the first group seem
|
||
to be completely mad, but aren't: President Schreber developed his radiat-
|
||
ing paranoia and relations with God in every direction, but he was not mad
|
||
in that he remained capable of managing his wealth wisely and distinguish-
|
||
ing between circles. At the other pole are those who do not seem mad in any
|
||
way, but are, as borne out by their sudden actions, such as quarrels, arsons,
|
||
murders (Esquirol's four great monomanias, erotic, intellectual, arson,
|
||
and homocidal, already belong in this category). In short, psychiatry was
|
||
not at all constituted in relation to the concept of madness, or even as a
|
||
modification of that concept, but rather by its split in these two opposite
|
||
directions. And is it not our own double image, all of ours, that psychiatry
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 121
|
||
|
||
thus reveals: seeming mad without "being it, then being it without seeming
|
||
it? (This twofold assertion is also psychoanalysis's point of departure, its
|
||
way of linking into psychiatry: we seem to be mad but aren't, observe the
|
||
dream; we are mad but don't seem to be, observe everyday life.) Thus psy-
|
||
chiatrists were alternately in the position of on the one hand pleading for
|
||
tolerance and understanding, underscoring the uselessness of confine-
|
||
ment, appealing for open-door asylums; and on the other arguing for
|
||
stepped-up surveillance and special high-security asylums, stricter mea-
|
||
sures necessitated by the fact that the mad seemed not to be.10 Is it by
|
||
chance that the distinction between the two major kinds of delusions, idea-
|
||
tional and active, in many ways recapitulates the distinction between the
|
||
classes (paranoiacs do not particularly need to be committed, they are usu-
|
||
ally bourgeois, whereas monomaniacs, passional redress-seekers, are most
|
||
often from the working and rural classes, or are marginal, as in the case of
|
||
political assassins)." A class with radiant, irradiating ideas (but of course!)
|
||
against a class reduced to linear, sporadic, partial, local actions . . . All par-
|
||
anoiacs are not bourgeois, all passionals or monomaniacs are not proletar-
|
||
ian. But God and his psychiatrists are charged with recognizing, among
|
||
these de facto mixes, those who preserve, even in delusion, the class-based
|
||
social order, and those who sow disorder, even strictly localized, such as
|
||
haystack fires, parental murders, declasse love and aggression.
|
||
We are trying, then, to make a distinction between a paranoid, signify-
|
||
ing, despotic regime of signs and a passional or subjective, postsignifying,
|
||
authoritarian regime. Authoritarian is assuredly not the same as despotic,
|
||
passional is not the same as paranoid, and subjective is not the same as sig-
|
||
nifying. What happens in the second regime, by comparison with the signi-
|
||
fying regime as we have already defined it? In the first place, a sign or
|
||
packet of signs detaches from the irradiating circular network and sets to
|
||
work on its own account, starts running a straight line, as though swept into
|
||
a narrow, open passage. Already the signifying system drew a line of flight
|
||
or deterritorialization exceeding the specific index of its deterritorialized
|
||
signs, but the system gave that line a negative value and sent the scapegoat
|
||
fleeing down it. Here, it seems that the line receives a positive sign, as
|
||
though it were effectively occupied and followed by a people who find in it
|
||
their reason for being or destiny. Once again, we are not, of course, doing
|
||
history: we are not saying that a people invents this regime of signs, only
|
||
that at a given moment a people effectuates the assemblage that assures the
|
||
relative dominance of that regime under certain historical conditions (and
|
||
that regime, that dominance, that assemblage may be assured under other
|
||
conditions, for example, pathological, literary, romantic, or entirely mun-
|
||
dane). We are not saying that a people is possessed by a given type of
|
||
delusion but that the map of a delusion, its coordinates considered, may
|
||
122 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
coincide with the map of a people, its coordinates considered. The para-
|
||
noid Pharaoh and the passional Hebrew? In the case of the Jewish people, a
|
||
group of signs detaches from the Egyptian imperial network of which it was
|
||
a part and sets off down a line of flight into the desert, pitting the most
|
||
authoritarian of subjectivities against despotic signifiance, the most
|
||
passional and least interpretive of delusions against interpretational
|
||
paranoid delusion, in short, a linear "proceeding and grievance" against
|
||
the irradiating circular network. Your grievance, your proceeding: that is
|
||
Moses' word to his people, and the proceedings come one after the other
|
||
along a line of Passion.12 From this Kafka derives his own conception of
|
||
querulousness or the proceeding, and the succession of linear segments:
|
||
the father-proceeding, hotel-proceeding, ship-proceeding, court-pro-
|
||
ceeding . ..
|
||
We cannot overlook the most fundamental or extensive event in the his-
|
||
tory of the Jewish people: the destruction of the Temple, in two stages (587
|
||
B.C. and A.D. 70). The whole history of the Temple—the mobility and fra-
|
||
gility of the ark, then the construction of a House by Solomon, its recon-
|
||
struction under Darius, etc.—has meaning only in relation to renewed
|
||
proceedings of destruction, the two supreme moments of which came with
|
||
Nebuchadnezzar and Titus. A temple, mobile, fragile, or destroyed: the ark
|
||
is no more than a little portable packet of signs. An entirely negative line of
|
||
flight occupied by the animal or scapegoat laden with all the dangers
|
||
threatening the signifier has become an impossibility. Let misfortune
|
||
befall us: this formula punctuates Jewish history. It is we who must follow
|
||
the most deterritorialized line, the line of the scapegoat, but we will change
|
||
its sign, we will turn it into the positive line of our subjectivity, our Passion,
|
||
our proceeding or grievance. We will be our own scapegoat. We will be the
|
||
lamb: "The God who, like a lion, was given blood sacrifice must be shoved
|
||
into the background, and the sacrificed god must occupy the fore-
|
||
ground. . . . God became the animal that was slain, instead of the animal
|
||
that does the slaying."13 We will follow, we will wed the tangent separating
|
||
the land from the waters, we will separate the circular network from the
|
||
gliding continuum, we will make the line of separation our own, in order to
|
||
forge our path along it and dissociate the elements of the signifier (the dove
|
||
of the ark). A narrow line of march, an in-between that is not a mean but a
|
||
slender line. There is a Jewish specificity, immediately affirmed in a
|
||
semiotic system. This semiotic, however, is no less mixed than any other.
|
||
On the one hand, it is intimately related to the countersignifying regime of
|
||
the nomads (the Hebrews had a nomadic past, a continuing relationship
|
||
with the nomadic numerical organization that inspired them, and their
|
||
own particular becoming-nomad; their line of deterritorialization owed
|
||
much to the military line of nomadic destruction).14 On the other hand, it
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 123
|
||
|
||
has an essential relation to the signifying semiotic itself, for which the
|
||
Hebrews and their God would always be nostalgic: reestablish an imperial
|
||
society and integrate with it, enthrone a king like everybody else (Samuel),
|
||
rebuild a temple that would finally be solid (David and Solomon,
|
||
Zachariah), erect the spiral of the Tower of Babel and find the face of God
|
||
again; not just bring the wandering to a halt, but overcome the diaspora,
|
||
which itself exists only as a function of an ideal regathering. We only have
|
||
space to indicate what, in this mixed semiotic, bears witness to the new
|
||
postsignifying subjective or passional regime.
|
||
Faciality undergoes a profound transformation. The god averts his face,
|
||
which must be seen by no one; and the subject, gripped by a veritable fear of
|
||
the god, averts his or her face in turn. The averted faces, in profile, replace
|
||
the frontal view of the radiant face. It is this double turning away that draws
|
||
the positive line of flight. The prophet is the main figure in this assemblage;
|
||
he needs a sign to guarantee the word of God, he is himself marked by a sign
|
||
indicating the special regime to which he belongs. It is Spinoza who has
|
||
elaborated the profoundest theory of prophetism, taking into account the
|
||
semiotic proper to it. Cain, who turns away from the God who turns away
|
||
from him, already follows the line of deterritorialization, protected by a
|
||
sign allowing him to escape death. The mark of Cain. A punishment worse
|
||
than imperial death? The Jewish God invented the reprieve, existence in
|
||
reprieve, indefinite postponement.^ But He also invented the positivity of
|
||
alliance, or the covenant, as the new relation with the deity, since the sub-
|
||
ject remains alive. Abel, whose name is vanity, is nothing; Cain is the true
|
||
man. This is very different from the system of rigging or deception animat-
|
||
ing the face of the signifier, the interpretation of the seer and the displace-
|
||
ments of the subject. It is the regime of betrayal, universal betrayal, in
|
||
which the true man never ceases to betray God just as God betrays man,
|
||
with the wrath of God defining the new positivity. Before his death, Moses
|
||
receives the words of the great song of betrayal. Even the prophet, unlike
|
||
the seer-priest, is fundamentally a traitor and thus fulfills God's order bet-
|
||
ter than anyone who remained faithful could. God calls upon Jonah to go to
|
||
Nineveh to entreat the inhabitants, who had repeatedly betrayed God, to
|
||
mend their ways. But Jonah's first act is to take off in the opposite direc-
|
||
tion; he also betrays God, fleeing "far from the face of Adonai."16 He takes
|
||
a ship for Tarshish and sleeps, like a righteous man. The tempest sent by
|
||
God causes him to be thrown into the sea, where he is swallowed by the
|
||
great fish and vomited out at the boundary between land and water, the
|
||
limit of separation or line of flight earlier occupied by the dove of the Ark
|
||
(Jonah, precisely, is the word for dove). But Jonah, in fleeing from the face
|
||
of God, did exactly what God had wanted: he took the evil of Nineveh
|
||
upon himself; he did it even more effectively than God had wanted, he
|
||
124 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
anticipated God. That is why he slept like a righteous man. God let him
|
||
live, temporarily protected by the tree of Cain, but then made the tree die
|
||
because Jonah had renewed the covenant by occupying the line of flight.17
|
||
Jesus universalizes the system of betrayal: he betrays the God of the Jews,
|
||
he betrays the Jews, he is betrayed by God ("Why hast thou forsaken me?"
|
||
[Matthew 27:46; Mark 15:34—Trans.]), he is betrayed by Judas, the true
|
||
man. He took evil upon himself, but the Jews who kill him also take it upon
|
||
themselves. Jesus is asked for a sign of his divine descendance: he invokes
|
||
the sign of Jonah [Luke 11:29—Trans.]. Cain, Jonah, and Jesus constitute
|
||
three great linear proceedings along which signs rush and form relays.
|
||
There are many others. Everywhere a double turning away on a line of
|
||
flight.
|
||
When a prophet declines the burden God entrusts to him (Moses,
|
||
Jeremiah, Isaiah, etc.), it is not because the burden would have been too
|
||
heavy, as with an imperial oracle or seer who refuses a dangerous mission.
|
||
It is instead a case like Jonah's, who by hiding and fleeing and betraying
|
||
anticipates the will of God more effectively than if he had obeyed. The
|
||
prophet is always being forced by God, literally violated by him, much
|
||
more than inspired by him. The prophet is not a priest. The prophet does
|
||
not know how to talk, God puts the words in his mouth: word-ingestion, a
|
||
new form of semiophagy. Unlike the seer, the prophet interprets nothing:
|
||
his delusion is active rather than ideational or imaginative, his relation to
|
||
God is passional and authoritative rather than despotic and signifying; he
|
||
anticipates and detects the powers (puissances) of the future rather than
|
||
applying past and present powers (pouvoirs). Faciality traits no longer func-
|
||
tion to prevent the formation of a line of flight, or to form a body of
|
||
signifiance controlling that line and sending only a faceless goat down it.
|
||
Rather, it is faciality itself that organizes the line of flight, in the face-off
|
||
between two countenances that become gaunt and turn away in profile.
|
||
Betrayal has become an idee fixe, the main obsession, replacing the deceit
|
||
of the paranoiac and the hysteric. The "persecutor-persecuted" relation
|
||
has no relevance whatsoever: its meaning is altogether different in the
|
||
authoritarian passional regime than in the despotic paranoid regime.
|
||
Something is still bothering us: the story of Oedipus. Oedipus is almost
|
||
unique in the Greek world. The whole first part is imperial, despotic, para-
|
||
noid, interpretive, divinatory. But the whole second part is Oedipus's wan-
|
||
dering, his line of flight, the double turning away of his own face and that of
|
||
God. Rather than very precise limits to be crossed in order, or which one
|
||
does not have the right to cross (hybris), there is a concealed limit toward
|
||
which Oedipus is swept. Rather than interpretive signifying irradiation,
|
||
there is a subjective linear proceeding permitting Oedipus to keep a secret,
|
||
but only as a residue capable of starting a new linear proceeding. Oedipus,
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 125
|
||
|
||
his name is atheos: he invents something worse than death or exile, he wan-
|
||
ders and survives on a strangely positive line of separation or deterri-
|
||
torialization. Holderlin and Heidegger see this as the birth of the double
|
||
turning away, the change of face, and also the birth of modern tragedy, for
|
||
which they bizarrely credit the Greeks: the outcome is no longer murder or
|
||
sudden death but survival under reprieve, unlimited postponement.18
|
||
Nietzsche suggests that Oedipus, as opposed to Prometheus, was the
|
||
Semitic myth of the Greeks, the glorification of Passion or passivity.'9 Oe-
|
||
dipus: Greek Cain. Let us return to psychoanalysis. It was not by chance
|
||
that Freud pounced upon Oedipus. Psychoanalysis is a definite case of a
|
||
mixed semiotic: a despotic regime of signifiance and interpretation, with
|
||
irradiation of the face, but also an authoritarian regime of subjectification
|
||
and prophetism, with a turning away of the face (the positioning of the psy-
|
||
choanalyst behind the patient suddenly assumes its full significance).
|
||
Recent efforts to explain that a "signifier represents the subject for another
|
||
signifier" are typically syncretic: a linear proceeding of subjectivity along
|
||
with a circular development of the signifier and interpretation. Two abso-
|
||
lutely different regimes of signs in a mix. But the worst, most underhanded
|
||
of powers are founded on it.
|
||
One more remark on the story of authoritarian passional betrayal, as
|
||
opposed to despotic paranoid deception. Everything is infamy, but Borges
|
||
botched his history of universal infamy.20 He should have distinguished
|
||
between the great realm of deceptions and the great realm of betrayals. And
|
||
also between the various figures of betrayal. There is, in effect, a second fig-
|
||
ure of betrayal that springs up at certain places at certain times, but always
|
||
as a function of a variable assemblage with new components. Christianity
|
||
is a particularly important case of a mixed semiotic, with its signifying
|
||
imperial combination together with its postsignifying Jewish subjectivity.
|
||
It transforms both the ideal signifying system and the postsignifying
|
||
passional system. It invents a new assemblage. Heresies are still a part of
|
||
deception, just as orthodoxy is a part of signifiance. But there are heresies
|
||
that are more than heresies and profess pure treason, for example, the
|
||
Buggers; it is not by chance that the Bulgars played a special role.21 Beware
|
||
the Bulgars, as Monsieur Plume would say. The problem is one of territori-
|
||
alities in relation to deep movements of deterritorialization. England,
|
||
another territoriality or another deterritorialization: Cromwell, every-
|
||
where a traitor, a straight line of passional subjectification opposed to the
|
||
royal center of signifiance and the intermediary circles: the dictator against
|
||
the despot. Richard III, the deformed, the twisted, whose ideal is to betray
|
||
everything: he confronts Lady Anne in a face-off in which the two counte-
|
||
nances turn away, but each knows she or he is the other's, destined for the
|
||
other. This is unlike Shakespeare's other historical dramas, in which kings
|
||
126 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
and assassins deceive in order to take power but then become good kings.
|
||
That kind are men of the State. Richard III comes from elsewhere: his ven-
|
||
tures, including those with women, derive more from a war machine than
|
||
from a State apparatus. He is the traitor, springing from the great nomads
|
||
and their secrecy. He says so from the beginning, when he mentions a secret
|
||
project infinitely surpassing the conquest of power. He wants to return the
|
||
war machine both to the fragile State and pacified couples. The only one to
|
||
guess is Lady Anne, fascinated, terrified, consenting. Elizabethan theater
|
||
is full of these traitorous characters who aspire to be absolute traitors, in
|
||
opposition to the deceptions of the man of the court or even of the State.
|
||
How many betrayals accompanied the great discoveries of Christen-
|
||
dom, the discovery of new lands and continents! Lines of deterrito-
|
||
rialization on which small groups betray everything, their companions, the
|
||
king, the indigenous peoples, the neighboring explorer, in the mad hope of
|
||
founding, with a woman of their family, a race that would finally be pure
|
||
and represent a new beginning. Herzog's film, Aguirre, is very Shakespear-
|
||
ean. Aguirre asks, How can one be a traitor everywhere and in everything?
|
||
I'm the only traitor here. No more deception, it's time for betrayal. What a
|
||
grandiose dream! I will be the last traitor, the total traitor, and therefore the
|
||
last man.
|
||
Then there was the Reformation: the extraordinary figure of Luther, as
|
||
traitor to all things and all people; his personal relation with the Devil
|
||
resulting in betrayal, through good deeds as well as bad.
|
||
These new figures of betrayal always return to the Old Testament: I am
|
||
the wrath of God. But betrayal has become humanist, it does not fall
|
||
between God and his own men; it relies on God, but falls between the men
|
||
of God and the others, denounced as deceivers. In the end, there is only one
|
||
man of God or of the wrath of God, a single betrayer against all deceivers.
|
||
But every deceiver is mixed, and which does not take him- or herself to be
|
||
the one? And what betrayer does not say to him- or herself at some point
|
||
that he or she was nothing but a deceiver after all? (See the strange case of
|
||
Maurice Sachs.)
|
||
It is clear that the book, or what takes its place, has a different meaning
|
||
in the signifying paranoid regime than in the postsignifying passional
|
||
regime. In the first case, there is an emission of the despotic signifier, and
|
||
its interpretation by scribes and priests, which fixes the signified and
|
||
reimparts signifier; but there is also, from sign to sign, a movement from
|
||
one territory to another, a circulation assuring a certain speed of
|
||
deterritorialization (for example, the circulation of an epic, or the rivalry
|
||
between several cities for the birth of a hero, or, once again, the role of
|
||
scribe-priests in exchanges of territorialities and genealogies).22 What
|
||
takes the place of the book always has an external model, a referent, face,
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 127
|
||
|
||
family, or territory that preserves the book's oral character. On the con-
|
||
trary, in the passional regime the book seems to be internalized, and to
|
||
internalize everything: it becomes the sacred written Book. It takes the
|
||
place of the face and God, who hides his face and gives Moses the inscribed
|
||
stone tablets. God manifests himself through trumpets and the Voice, but
|
||
what is heard in sound is the nonface, just as what is seen in the book are
|
||
words. The book has become the body of passion, just as the face was the
|
||
body of the signifier. It is now the book, the most deterritorialized of
|
||
things, that fixes territories and genealogies. The latter are what the book
|
||
says, and the former the place at which the book is said. The function of
|
||
interpretation has totally changed. Or it disappears entirely in favor of a
|
||
pure and literal recitation forbidding the slightest change, addition, or
|
||
commentary (the famous "stultify yourself of the Christians belongs to
|
||
this passional line; the Koran goes the furthest in this direction). Or else
|
||
interpretation survives but becomes internal to the book itself, which loses
|
||
its circulatory function for outside elements: for example, the different
|
||
types of coded interpretation are fixed according to axes internal to the
|
||
book; interpretation is organized according to correspondences between
|
||
two books, such as the Old and New Testaments, and may even induce a
|
||
third book suffused by the same element of interiority.23 Finally, interpre-
|
||
tation may reject all intermediaries or specialists and become direct, since
|
||
the book is written both in itself and in the heart, once as a point of
|
||
subjectification and again in the subject (the Reformation conception of
|
||
the book). In any case, this is the point of departure for the delusional pas-
|
||
sion of the book as origin and finality of the world. The unique book, the
|
||
total work, all possible combinations inside the book, the tree-book, the
|
||
cosmos-book: all of these platitudes so dear to the avant-gardes, which cut
|
||
the book off from its relations with the outside, are even worse than the
|
||
chant of the signifier. Of course, they are entirely bound up with a mixed
|
||
semiotic. But in truth they have a particularly pious origin. Wagner,
|
||
Mallarme, and Joyce, Marx and Freud: still Bibles. If passional delusion is
|
||
profoundly monomaniacal, monomania for its part found a fundamental
|
||
element of its assemblage in monotheism and the Book. The strangest cult.
|
||
This is how things are in the passional regime, or the regime of
|
||
subjectification. There is no longer a center of signifiance connected to
|
||
expanding circles or an expanding spiral, but a point of subjectification
|
||
constituting the point of departure of the line. There is no longer a
|
||
signifier-signified relation, but a subject of enunciation issuing from the
|
||
point of subjectification and a subject of the statement in a determinable
|
||
relation to the first subject. There is no longer sign-to-sign circularity, but a
|
||
linear proceeding into which the sign is swept via subjects. We may con-
|
||
sider these three diverse realms.
|
||
128 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
1. The Jews as opposed to the empires. God withdraws his face, becom-
|
||
ing a point of subjectification for the drawing of a line of flight or
|
||
deterritorialization; Moses is the subject of enunciation, constituted on the
|
||
basis of the tablets of God that replace the face; the Jewish people consti-
|
||
tute the subject of the statement, for betrayal as well as for a new land, and
|
||
enter an ever-renewed covenant or linear "proceeding" rather than a circu-
|
||
lar expansion.
|
||
2. So-called modern, or Christian, philosophy. Descartes as opposed to
|
||
ancient philosophy. There is a primacy of the idea of the infinite as an
|
||
absolutely necessary point of subjectification. The Cogito, consciousness,
|
||
the "I think" is the subject of enunciation that reflects its own use and
|
||
conceives of itself following a line of deterritorialization represented by
|
||
methodical doubt. The subject of the statement is the union of the soul and
|
||
the body, or feeling, guaranteed in a complex way by the cogito, and per-
|
||
forms the necessary reterritorializations. The cogito is a proceeding that
|
||
must always be recommenced, haunted by the possibility of betrayal, a
|
||
deceitful God, and an evil Genius. When Descartes says, I can infer "I
|
||
think therefore I am" but not "I walk therefore I am," he is initiating the
|
||
distinction between the two subjects (what still-Cartesian contemporary
|
||
linguists call a shifter, even though they find traces of the second subject in
|
||
the first).
|
||
3. Nineteenth-century psychiatry: monomania distinguished from
|
||
mania; subjective delusion separated from ideational delusions; "posses-
|
||
sion" replacing sorcery; a slow elaboration of passional delusion, as dis-
|
||
tinct from paranoia . . . The schema of passional delusion according to
|
||
Clerambault is as follows: the Postulate as the point of subjectification
|
||
(He loves me); pride as the tonality of the subject of enunciation (de-
|
||
lusional pursuit of the loved one); Spite, Rancor (a result of a reversion
|
||
to the subject of the statement). Passional delusion is a veritable cogito. In
|
||
the foregoing example of erotomania, as well as in jealousy and querulous
|
||
delusion, Clerambault stresses that a sign must follow a segment or linear
|
||
proceeding through to the end before it can begin another, whereas the
|
||
signs in paranoid delusion form an endless, self-adjusting network devel-
|
||
oping in all directions. The cogito also follows a linear temporal proceed-
|
||
ing needing to be recommenced. The history of the Jews is punctuated by
|
||
catastrophes after each of which there were just enough survivors to start
|
||
a new proceeding. In the course of a proceeding, while there is linear
|
||
movement the plural is often used, whereas there is a return to the Singu-
|
||
lar as soon as there is a pause or stoppage marking the end of one move-
|
||
ment before another begins.24 Fundamental segmentarity: one proceed-
|
||
ing must end (and its termination must be marked) before another begins,
|
||
to enable another to begin.
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 129
|
||
|
||
The point of subj edification is the origin of the passional line of the
|
||
postsignifying regime. The point of subjectification can be anything. It
|
||
must only display the following characteristic traits of the subjective
|
||
semiotic: the double turning away, betrayal, and existence under reprieve.
|
||
For anorexics, food plays this role (anorexics do not confront death but
|
||
save themselves by betraying food, which is equally a traitor since it is sus-
|
||
pected of containing larvae, worms, and microbes). A dress, an article of
|
||
underwear, a shoe are points of subjectification for a fetishist. So is a
|
||
faciality trait for someone in love, but the meaning of faciality has
|
||
changed; it is no longer the body of the signifier but has become the point
|
||
of departure for a deterritorialization that puts everything else to flight. A
|
||
thing, an animal, will do the trick. There are cogitos on everything. "A
|
||
pair of eyes set far apart, a head hewn of quartz, a haunch that seemed to
|
||
live its own l i f e . . . . Whenever the beauty of the female becomes irresisti-
|
||
ble, it is traceable to a single quality":25 a point of subjectification in the
|
||
departure of a passional line. Moreover, several points coexist in a given
|
||
individual or group, which are always engaged in several distinct and not
|
||
always compatible linear proceedings. The various forms of education or
|
||
"normalization" imposed upon an individual consist in making him or
|
||
her change points of subjectification, always moving toward a higher,
|
||
nobler one in closer conformity with the supposed ideal. Then from the
|
||
point of subjectification issues a subject of enunciation, as a function of a
|
||
mental reality determined by that point. Then from the subject of enunci-
|
||
ation issues a subject of the statement, in other words, a subject bound to
|
||
statements in conformity with a dominant reality (of which the mental
|
||
reality just mentioned is a part, even when it seems to oppose it). What is
|
||
important, what makes the postsignifying passional line a line of subjecti-
|
||
fication or subjection, is the constitution, the doubling of the two sub-
|
||
jects, and the recoiling of one into the other, of the subject of enunciation
|
||
into the subject of the statement (the linguists acknowledge this when
|
||
they speak of the "imprint of the process of enunciation in the state-
|
||
ment"). Signifiance brought about uniformity in the substance of enunci-
|
||
ation; now subjectivity effects an individuation, collective or particular.
|
||
Substance has become subject, as they say. The subject of enunciation
|
||
recoils into the subject of the statement, to the point that the subject of the
|
||
statement resupplies subject of enunciation for another proceeding. The
|
||
subject of the statement has become the "respondent" or guarantor of the
|
||
subject of enunciation, through a kind of reductive echolalia, in a
|
||
biunivocal relation. This relation, this recoiling, is also that of mental
|
||
reality into the dominant reality. There is always an appeal to a dominant
|
||
reality that functions from within (already in the Old Testament, and dur-
|
||
ing the Reformation, with trade and capitalism). There is no longer even a
|
||
130 n 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
need for a transcendent center of power; power is instead immanent and
|
||
melds with the "real," operating through normalization. A strange inven-
|
||
tion: as if in one form the doubled subject were the causeof the statements
|
||
of which, in its other form, it itself is a part. This is the paradox of the
|
||
legislator-subject replacing the signifying despot: the more you obey the
|
||
statements of the dominant reality, the more in command you are as sub-
|
||
ject of enunciation in mental reality, for in the end you are only obeying
|
||
yourself! You are the one in command, in your capacity as a rational
|
||
being. A new form of slavery is invented, namely, being slave to oneself, or
|
||
to pure "reason," the Cogito. Is there anything more passional than pure
|
||
reason? Is there a colder, more extreme, more self-interested passion than
|
||
the Cogito?
|
||
Althusser clearly brings out this constitution of social individuals as
|
||
subjects: he calls it interpellation ("Hey you, over there!") and calls the
|
||
point of subjectification the Absolute Subject; he analyzes the "specular
|
||
doubling" of subjects and for purposes of demonstration uses the example
|
||
of God, Moses, and the Jewish people.26 Linguists like Benveniste adopt a
|
||
curious linguistic personology that is very close to the Cogito: the You,
|
||
which can doubtless designate the person one is addressing, but more
|
||
importantly, a point of subjectification on the basis of which each of us is
|
||
constituted as a subject. The /as subject of enunciation, designating the
|
||
person that utters and reflects its own use in the statement ("the empty
|
||
nonreferential sign"); this is the I appearing in propositions of the type "I
|
||
believe, I assume, I think..." Finally, the I as subject of the statement,
|
||
indicating a state for which a She or He could always be substituted ("I suf-
|
||
fer, I walk, I breathe, I feel.. .").27 This is not, however, a question of a lin-
|
||
guistic operation, for a subject is never the condition of possibility of
|
||
language or the cause of the statement: there is no subject, only collective
|
||
assemblages of enunciation. Subjectification is simply one such assem-
|
||
blage and designates a formalization of expression or a regime of signs
|
||
rather than a condition internal to language. Neither is it a question of a
|
||
movement characteristic of ideology, as Althusser says: subjectification as
|
||
a regime of signs or a form of expression is tied to an assemblage, in other
|
||
words, an organization of power that is already fully functioning in the
|
||
economy, rather than superposing itself upon contents or relations
|
||
between contents determined as real in the last instance. Capital is a point
|
||
of subjectification par excellence.
|
||
The psychoanalytic cogito: the psychoanalyst presents him- or herself as
|
||
an ideal point of subjectification that brings the patient to abandon old,
|
||
so-called neurotic, points. The patient is partially a subject of enunciation
|
||
in all he or she says to the psychoanalyst, and under the artificial mental
|
||
conditions of the session: the patient is therefore called the "analysand."
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 131
|
||
|
||
But in everything else the patient says or does, he or she is a subject of the
|
||
statement, eternally psychoanalyzed, going from one linear proceeding to
|
||
another, perhaps even changing analysts, growing increasingly submissive
|
||
to the normalization of a dominant reality. In this sense, psychoanalysis,
|
||
with its mixed semiotic, fully participates in a line of subjectification. The
|
||
psychoanalyst does not even have to speak anymore, the analysand
|
||
assumes the burden of interpretation; as for the psychoanalyzed patient,
|
||
the more he or she thinks about "his" or "her" next session, or the preced-
|
||
ing one, in segments, the better a subject he or she is.
|
||
Just as the paranoid regime had two axes—one sign referring to another
|
||
(making the sign a signifier), and the signifier referring to the signified—so
|
||
too the passional regime, the line of subjectification, has two axes, one
|
||
syntagmatic and the other paradigmatic: as we have just seen, the first axis
|
||
is consciousness. Consciousness as passion is precisely that doubling of
|
||
subjects, of the subject of enunciation and the subject of the statement, and
|
||
the recoiling of one into the other. But the second form of subjectification
|
||
is love as passion, love-passion, another type of double, of doubling and
|
||
recoiling. Here again, a variable point of subjectification serves to distrib-
|
||
ute two subjects that as much conceal their faces as reveal them to each
|
||
other, that wed a line of flight, a line of deterritorialization forever drawing
|
||
them together and driving them apart. But everything changes: there is a
|
||
celibate side to this doubled consciousness, and there is a passional love
|
||
couple that no longer has any use for consciousness or reason. Yet it is the
|
||
same regime, even in betrayal and even if the betraying is done by a third
|
||
party. Adam and Eve, and Cain's wife (about whom the Bible should have
|
||
said more). Richard III, the traitor, is in the end given consciousness in a
|
||
dream, but only the strange face-off with Lady Anne, a meeting of two
|
||
countenances that conceal themselves knowing that they have promised
|
||
themselves to each other following the same line that will nonetheless sepa-
|
||
rate them. The most loyal and tender, or intense, love assigns subject of
|
||
enunciation and a subject of the statement that constantly switch places,
|
||
wrapped in the sweetness of being a naked statement in the other's mouth,
|
||
and of the other's being a naked enunciation in my own mouth. But there is
|
||
always a traitor in the making. What love is not betrayed? What cogito lacks
|
||
its evil genius, the traitor it will never be rid of? "Tristan . . . Isolde . . .
|
||
Isolde.. . Tristan": the cry of the two subjects climbs the scale of intensities
|
||
until it reaches the summit of a suffocating consciousness, whereas the ship
|
||
follows the line of the waters, the line of death and the unconscious,
|
||
betrayal, a continuous melody line. Passional love is a cogito built for two,
|
||
just as the cogito is a passion for the self alone. There is a potential couple in
|
||
the cogito, just as there is a doubling of a single virtual subject in love-
|
||
passion. Klossowski has created the strangest figures on the basis of this
|
||
132 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
complementarity between an over intense thought and an over feverish
|
||
couple. The line of subjectification is thus entirely occupied by the Double,
|
||
but it has two figures since there are two kinds of doubles: the syntagmatic
|
||
figure of consciousness, or the consciousness-related double, relating to
|
||
form (Self = Self [Moi = Moi\); and the paradigmatic figure of the couple,
|
||
or the passional double, relating to substance (Man = Woman; here, the
|
||
double is immediately the difference between the sexes).
|
||
We can follow the becoming of these doubles in mixed semiotics, which
|
||
are interminglings as well as degradations. On the one hand, the passional
|
||
love double, the couple in love-passion, falls into a conjugal relation or
|
||
even a "domestic squabble" situation: Which is the subject of enunciation?
|
||
Which is the subject of the statement? The battle of the sexes: You 're steal-
|
||
ing my thoughts. The domestic squabble has always been a cogito for two, a
|
||
war cogito. Strindberg took this fall of love-passion into despotic conju-
|
||
gality and hysterico-paranoid squabbling to its extreme ("she" says she
|
||
found it all by herself when in fact she owes it all to me, echo, thought theft,
|
||
O Strindberg!).28 On the other hand, the consciousness-related double of
|
||
pure thought, the couple of the legislating subject, falls into a bureaucratic
|
||
relation and a new form of persecution in which one double takes over the
|
||
role of subject of enunciation while the other is reduced to a subject of the
|
||
statement; the cogito itself becomes an "office squabble," a bureaucratic
|
||
love delusion. A new form of bureaucracy replaces or conjugates with the
|
||
old imperial bureaucracy, the bureaucrat says / think (Kafka goes the fur-
|
||
thest in this direction, as in the example of Sortini and Sordini in The Cas-
|
||
tle, or the many subjectifications of Klamm). 29 Conjugality is the
|
||
development of the couple, and bureaucracy the development of the
|
||
cogito. But one is contained in the other: amorous bureaucracy, bureau-
|
||
cratic couple. Too much has been written on the double, haphazardly,
|
||
metaphysically, finding it everywhere, in any old mirror, without noticing
|
||
the specific regime it possesses both in a mixed semiotic where it intro-
|
||
duces new phases, and in the pure semiotic of subjectification where it
|
||
inscribes itself on a line of flight and introduces very particular figures.
|
||
Once again: the two figures of thought-consciousness and love-passion in
|
||
the postsignifying regime; the two moments of bureaucratic consciousness
|
||
and conjugal relation in the mixed fall or combination. But even in a mixed
|
||
state, the original line is easily discovered by semiotic analysis.
|
||
There is a redundancy of consciousness and love that is not the same as
|
||
the signifying redundancy of the other regime. In the signifying regime,
|
||
redundancy is a phenomenon of objective frequency involving signs or ele-
|
||
ments of signs (the phonemes, letters, and groups of letters in a language):
|
||
there is both a maximum frequency of the signifier in relation to each sign,
|
||
and a comparative frequency of one sign in relation to another. In any case,
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 133
|
||
|
||
it could be said that this regime develops a kind of "wall" on which signs are
|
||
inscribed, in relation to one another and in relation to the signifier. In the
|
||
postsignifying regime, on the other hand, the redundancy is one of subjec-
|
||
tive resonance involving above all shifters, personal pronouns and proper
|
||
names. Here again, we may distinguish between the maximum resonance
|
||
of self-consciousness (Self = Self [Moi = Moi]) and a comparative reso-
|
||
nance of names (Tristan ... Isolde .. .)• This time, however, there is no
|
||
longer a wall upon which the frequency is tallied but instead a black hole
|
||
attracting consciousness and passion and in which they resonate. Tristan
|
||
calls Isolde, Isolde calls Tristan, both drawn toward the black hole of a self-
|
||
consciousness, carried by the tide toward death. When the linguists distin-
|
||
guish between two forms of redundancy, frequency and resonance, they
|
||
often ascribe the latter a merely derivative status.30 In fact, it is a question
|
||
of two semiotics that mix but retain their own distinct principles (similarly,
|
||
one could define other forms of redundancy, such as rhythmic, gestural, or
|
||
numerical, relating to the other regimes of signs). The most essential dis-
|
||
tinction between the signifying regime and the subjective regime and their
|
||
respective redundancies is the movement of deterritorialization they
|
||
effectuate. Since the signifying sign refers only to other signs, and the set of
|
||
all signs to the signifier itself, the corresponding semiotic enjoys a high
|
||
level of deterritorialization; but it is a deterritorialization that is still
|
||
relative, expressed as frequency. In this system, the line of flight remains
|
||
negative, it is assigned a negative sign. As we have seen, the subjective
|
||
regime proceeds entirely differently: precisely because the sign breaks its
|
||
relation of signifiance with other signs and sets off racing down a positive
|
||
line of flight, it attains an absolute deterritorialization expressed in the
|
||
black hole of consciousness and passion. The absolute deterritorialization
|
||
of the cogito. That is why subjective redundancy seems both to graft
|
||
itself onto signifying redundancy and to derive from it, as second-degree
|
||
redundancy.
|
||
Things are even more complicated than we have let on. Subjectification
|
||
assigns the line of flight a positive sign, it carries deterritorialization to the
|
||
absolute, intensity to the highest degree, redundancy to a reflexive form,
|
||
etc. But it has its own way of repudiating the positivity it frees, or of
|
||
relativizing the absoluteness it attains, without, however, falling back to
|
||
the preceding regime. In this redundancy of resonance, the absolute of con-
|
||
sciousness is the absolute of impotence and the intensity of passion, the
|
||
heat of the void. This is because Subjectification essentially constitutes
|
||
finite linear proceedings, one of which ends before the next begins: thus the
|
||
cogito is always recommenced, a passion or grievance is always recapitu-
|
||
lated. Every consciousness pursues its own death, every love-passion its
|
||
own end, attracted by a black hole, and all the black holes resonate together.
|
||
134 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
Thus subjectification imposes on the line of flight a segmentarity that is
|
||
forever repudiating that line, and upon absolute deterritorialization a
|
||
point of abolition that is forever blocking that deterritorialization or
|
||
diverting it. The reason for this is simple: forms of expression and regimes
|
||
of signs are still strata (even considered in themselves, after abstracting
|
||
forms of content); subjectification is no less a stratum than signifiance.
|
||
The principal strata binding human beings are the organism, signifiance
|
||
and interpretation, and subjectification and subjection. These strata to-
|
||
gether are what separates us from the plane of consistency and the abstract
|
||
machine, where there is no longer any regime of signs, where the line of
|
||
flight effectuates its own potential positivity and deterritorialization its
|
||
absolute power. The problem, from this standpoint, is to tip the most favor-
|
||
able assemblage from its side facing the strata to its side facing the plane of
|
||
consistency or the body without organs. Subjectification carries desire to
|
||
such a point of excess and unloosening that it must either annihilate itself
|
||
in a black hole or change planes. Destratify, open up to a new function, a
|
||
diagrammatic function. Let consciousness cease to be its own double, and
|
||
passion the double of one person for another. Make consciousness an
|
||
experimentation in life, and passion a field of continuous intensities, an
|
||
emission of particles-signs. Make the body without organs of conscious-
|
||
ness and love. Use love and consciousness to abolish subjectification: "To
|
||
become the great lover, the magnetizer and catalyzer . . . one has to first
|
||
experience the profound wisdom of being an utter fool."31 Use the / think
|
||
for a becoming-animal, and love for a becoming-woman of man. Desub-
|
||
jectify consciousness and passion. Are there not diagrammatic redundan-
|
||
cies distinct from both signifying redundancies and subjective redundan-
|
||
cies? Redundancies that would no longer be knots of arborescence but
|
||
resumptions and upsurges in a rhizome? Stammer language, be a foreigner
|
||
in one's own tongue:
|
||
do domi not passi do not dominate
|
||
do not dominate your passive passions not
|
||
|
||
do devouring not not dominate
|
||
your rats your rations your rats rations not not. . .32
|
||
It seems necessary to distinguish between three types of deterrito-
|
||
rialization: the first type is relative, proper to the strata, and culminates in
|
||
signifiance; the second is absolute, but still negative and stratic, and
|
||
appears in subjectification (Ratio et Passio)', finally, there is the possibility
|
||
of a positive absolute deterritorialization on the plane of consistency or the
|
||
body without organs.
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 135
|
||
|
||
We have not, of course, managed to eliminate forms of content (for
|
||
example, the role of the Temple, or the position of a dominant Reality,
|
||
etc.). What we have done is to isolate, under artificial conditions, a certain
|
||
number of semiotics displaying very diverse characteristics. Thepresigni-
|
||
fying semiotic, in which the "overcoding" marking the privileged status of
|
||
language operates diffusely: enunciation is collective, statements them-
|
||
selves are polyvocal, and substances of expression are multiple; relative
|
||
deterritorialization is determined by the confrontation between the terri-
|
||
torialities and segmentary lineages that ward off the State apparatus. The
|
||
signifying semiotic: overcoding is fully effectuated by the signifier, and by
|
||
the State apparatus that emits it; there is uniformity of enunciation, unifi-
|
||
cation of the substance of expression, and control over statements in a
|
||
regime of circularity; relative deterritorialization is taken as far as it can go
|
||
by a redundant and perpetual referral from sign to sign. The countersig-
|
||
nifying semiotic: here, overcoding is assured by the Number as form of
|
||
expression or enunciation, and by the War Machine upon which it
|
||
depends; deterritorialization follows a line of active destruction or aboli-
|
||
tion. The postsignifying semiotic, in which overcoding is assured by the
|
||
redundancy of consciousness; a subjectification of enunciation occurs on a
|
||
passional line that makes the organization of power (pouvoir)) immanent
|
||
and raises deterritorialization to the absolute, although in a way that is still
|
||
negative.
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
(1) The Center or the Signifier; the faciality of the god or despot. (2) The Temple or Pal-
|
||
ace, with priests and bureaucrats. (3) The organization in circles and the sign referring
|
||
to other signs on the same circle or on different circles. (4) The interpretive develop-
|
||
ment of signifier into signified, which then reimparts signifier. (5) The expiatory ani-
|
||
mal; the blocking of the line of flight. (6) The scapegoat, or the negative sign of the line
|
||
of night.
|
||
136 n 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
Yet we must consider two aspects: on the one hand, these semiotics are
|
||
still concrete even after forms of content have been abstracted, but only to
|
||
the extent that they are mixed, that they constitute mixed combinations.
|
||
Every semiotic is mixed and only functions as such; each one necessarily
|
||
captures fragments of one or more other semiotics (surplus value of code).
|
||
Even from this perspective, the signifying semiotic has no privileged status
|
||
to apply toward the formation of a general semiology: in particular, the way
|
||
in which it combines with the passional semiotic of subjectification ("the
|
||
signifier for the subject") implies nothing that would privilege it over other
|
||
combinations, for example, the combination of the passional semiotic and
|
||
the countersignifying semiotic, or of the countersignifying semiotic and
|
||
the signifying semiotic itself (when the Nomads turn imperial), etc. There
|
||
is no general semiology.
|
||
For example, without privileging one regime over another, it is possible
|
||
to construct schemas of the signifying and postsignifying semiotics that
|
||
clearly illustrate the possibilities for concrete mixture.
|
||
The second aspect, complementary but very different, consists in the
|
||
possibility of transforming one abstract or pure semiotic into another, by
|
||
virtue of the translatability ensuing from overcoding as the special charac-
|
||
teristic of language. This time, it is no longer a question of concrete mixed
|
||
semiotics but of transformations of one abstract semiotic into another
|
||
(even though that transformation is not itself abstract, in other words,
|
||
effectively takes place without being performed by a "translator" in the
|
||
role of pure knower). All transformations taking a given semiotic into the
|
||
presignifying regime may be called analogical transformations; those that
|
||
take it into the signifying regime are symbolic; into the countersignifying
|
||
regime, polemical or strategic; into the postsignifying regime, conscious-
|
||
ness-related or mimetic; finally, transformations that blow apart semiotics
|
||
systems or regimes of signs on the plane of consistency of a positive abso-
|
||
lute deterritorialization are called diagrammatic. A transformation is not
|
||
the same thing as a statement in a pure semiotic; nor even an ambiguous
|
||
statement requiring a whole pragmatic analysis to determine the semiotic
|
||
it belongs to; nor a statement belonging to a mixed semiotic (although the
|
||
transformation may have that effect). A transformational statement marks
|
||
the way in which a semiotic translates for its own purposes a statement
|
||
originating elsewhere, and in so doing diverts it, leaving untransformable
|
||
residues and actively resisting the inverse transformation. Furthermore,
|
||
transformations are not limited to the ones we just listed. It is always
|
||
through transformation that a new semiotic is created in its own right.
|
||
Translations can be creative. New pure regimes of signs are formed through
|
||
transformation and translation. Again, there is no general semiology but
|
||
rather a transsemiotic.
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 137
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
(1) The point of subjectification, replacing the center of signfiance. (2) The two faces
|
||
turned away from each other. (3) The subject of enunciation resulting from the point of
|
||
subjectification and the turning away. (4) The subject of the statement, into which the
|
||
subject of enunciation recoils. (5) The succession of finite linear proceedings accompa-
|
||
nied by a new form of priest and a new bureaucracy. (6) The line of flight, which is freed
|
||
but still segmented, remaining negative and blocked.
|
||
|
||
In analogical transformations, we often see sleep, drugs, and amorous
|
||
rapture form expressions that translate into presignifying regimes the sub-
|
||
jective or signifying regimes one wishes to impose upon the expressions,
|
||
but which they resist by themselves imposing upon these regimes an unex-
|
||
pected segmentarity and polyvocality. Christianity underwent strange cre-
|
||
ative translations in its transmission to "barbarian" or even "savage"
|
||
peoples. The introduction of monetary signs into certain commercial cir-
|
||
cuits in Africa caused those signs to undergo an analogical transformation
|
||
that was very difficult to control (except when the circuits underwent a
|
||
destructive transformation instead).33 The songs of black Americans,
|
||
including, especially, the words, would be a better example, since they
|
||
show how the slaves "translated" the English signifier and made presig-
|
||
nifying or even countersignifying use of the language, blending it with their
|
||
own African languages just as they blended old African work songs with
|
||
their new forced labor; these songs also show how, with Christianization
|
||
and the abolition of slavery, the slaves underwent a proceeding of
|
||
"subjectification" or even "individuation" that transformed their music,
|
||
while the music simultaneously transformed the proceeding by analogy;
|
||
and also how unique problems of "faciality" were posed when whites in
|
||
"blackface" appropriated the words and songs and blacks responded by
|
||
darkening their faces another hue, taking back their dances and songs, even
|
||
transforming or translating those of the whites.34 Of course, the crudest
|
||
and most visible transformations were in the other direction: the symbolic
|
||
translations occurring when the signifier takes power. The preceding exam-
|
||
ples concerning monetary signs and rhythmic regimes can be repeated in
|
||
the opposite direction. The passage from an African dance to a white dance
|
||
138 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
often exhibits a consciousness-related or mimetic translation, accompa-
|
||
nied by a power takeover by signifiance and subjectification. ("In Africa
|
||
the dance is impersonal, sacred and obscene. When the phallus becomes
|
||
erect and is handled like a banana it is not a 'personal hard-on' we see but a
|
||
tribal erection. . . . The hoochie-koochie dancer of the big city dances
|
||
alone—a fact of staggering significance. The law forbids response, forbids
|
||
participation. Nothing is left of the primitive rite but the 'suggestive'
|
||
movements of the body. What they suggest varies with the individual
|
||
observer.")^
|
||
It is not simply linguistic, lexical, or even syntactic transformations that
|
||
determine the importance of a true semiotic translation but the opposite.
|
||
Crazy talk is not enough. In each case we must judge whether what we see
|
||
is an adaptation of an old semiotic, a new variety of a particular mixed
|
||
semiotic, or the process of creation of an as yet unknown regime. For exam-
|
||
ple, it is relatively easy to stop saying "I," but that does not mean that you
|
||
have gotten away from the regime of subjectification; conversely, you can
|
||
keep on saying "I," just for kicks, and already be in another regime in which
|
||
personal pronouns function only as fictions. Signifiance and interpre-
|
||
tation are so thick-skinned, they form such a sticky mixture with sub-
|
||
jectification, that it is easy to believe that you are outside them when you
|
||
are in fact still secreting them. People sometimes denounce interpretation
|
||
yet show so signifying a face that they simultaneously impose interpreta-
|
||
tion upon the subject, which continues to nourish itself on it in order to sur-
|
||
vive. Who can really believe that psychoanalysis is capable of changing a
|
||
semiotic amassing every deception? The only change there has been is a
|
||
role switch. Instead of a patient who signifies and a psychoanalyst who
|
||
interprets, we now have a signifying analyst and it is the patient who does
|
||
all the interpreting. In the antipsychiatric experiment of Kingsley Hall,
|
||
Mary Barnes, a former nurse turned "schizophrenic," embraces the new
|
||
semiotic of the Voyage, only to arrogate to herself a veritable power in the
|
||
community and reintroduce as a collective delusion the worst kind of psy-
|
||
choanalytic regime of interpretation ("She interpreted everything that was
|
||
done for her, or for anyone else for that matter. . .").36 A highly stratified
|
||
semiotic is difficult to get away from. Even a presignifying, or counter-
|
||
signifying, semiotic, even an asignifying diagram, harbors knots of coinci-
|
||
dence just waiting to form virtual centers of signifiance and points of
|
||
subjectification. Of course, an operation of translation is not easy when it
|
||
is a question of destroying a dominant atmospheric semiotic. One of the
|
||
things of profound interest in Castaneda's books, under the influence of
|
||
drugs, or other things, and of a change of atmosphere, is precisely that they
|
||
show how the Indian manages to combat the mechanisms of interpretation
|
||
and instill in the disciple a presignifying semiotic, or even an asignifying
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 139
|
||
|
||
diagram: Stop! You're making me tired! Experiment, don't signify and
|
||
interpret! Find your own places, territorialities, deterritorializations,
|
||
regime, lines of flight! Semiotize yourself instead of rooting around in your
|
||
prefab childhood and Western semiology. "Don Juan stated that in order
|
||
to arrive at 'seeing' one first had to 'stop the world.' 'Stopping the world'
|
||
was indeed an appropriate rendition of certain states of awareness in which
|
||
the reality of everyday life is altered because the flow of interpretation,
|
||
which ordinarily runs uninterruptedly, has been stopped by a set of circum-
|
||
stances alien to the flow."37 In short, a true semiotic transformation
|
||
appeals to all kinds of variables, not only external ones, but also variables
|
||
implicit to language, internal to statements.
|
||
Pragmatics, then, already displays two components. The first could be
|
||
called generative since it shows how the various abstract regimes form con-
|
||
crete mixed semiotics, with what variants, how they combine, and which
|
||
one is predominant. The second is the transformational component, which
|
||
shows how these regimes of signs are translated into each other, especially
|
||
when there is a creation of a new regime. Generative pragmatics makes
|
||
tracings of mixed semiotics; transformational pragmatics makes maps of
|
||
transformations. Although a mixed semiotic does not necessarily imply
|
||
effective creativity, and may content itself with combinatory possibilities
|
||
without veritable transformation, it is still the transformational compo-
|
||
nent that accounts for the originality of a regime as well as for the novelty of
|
||
the mixes it enters at a given moment in a given domain. This second com-
|
||
ponent is therefore the more profound, and it is the only means of measur-
|
||
ing the elements of the first component.38 For example, we may ask when
|
||
statements of the Bolshevik type first appeared, and how Leninism, at the
|
||
time of the break with the social democrats, effected a veritable transfor-
|
||
mation that created an original semiotic, even if its fall into the mixed
|
||
semiotic of Stalinist organization was inevitable. In an exemplary study,
|
||
Jean-Pierre Faye did a detailed analysis of the transformations that pro-
|
||
duced Nazism, viewed as a system of new statements in a given social field.
|
||
At what moment is a regime of signs established, and in what domain?
|
||
Throughout an entire people? In a fraction of that people? In a more or less
|
||
localizable margin inside a psychiatric hospital? (For as we have seen we
|
||
can find a semiotic of subjectification in the ancient history of the Jews,
|
||
but also in psychiatric diagnosis in the nineteenth century, with, of course,
|
||
profound variations and even veritable transformations in the correspond-
|
||
ing semiotic.) All of these questions fall within the purview of pragmatics.
|
||
There is no question that the most profound transformations and transla-
|
||
tions of our time are not occurring in Europe. Pragmatics should reject the
|
||
idea of an invariant immune from transformation, even if it is the in-
|
||
variant of a dominant "grammaticality." For language is a political affair
|
||
140 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
before it is an affair for linguistics; even the evaluation of degrees of gram-
|
||
maticality is a political matter.
|
||
What is a semiotic, in other words, a regime of signs or a formalization
|
||
of expression? They are simultaneously more and less than language.
|
||
Language as a whole is defined by "superlinearity," its condition of possi-
|
||
bility; individual languages are defined by constants, elements, and rela-
|
||
tions of a phonological, syntactical, and semantic nature. Doubtless,
|
||
every regime of signs effectuates the condition of possibility of language
|
||
and utilizes language elements, but that is all. No regime can be identical
|
||
to that condition of possibility, and no regime has the property of con-
|
||
stants. As Foucault clearly shows, regimes of signs are only functions of
|
||
existence of language that sometimes span a number of languages and are
|
||
sometimes distributed within a single language; they coincide neither
|
||
with a structure nor with units of a given order, but rather intersect them
|
||
and cause them to appear in space and time. This is the sense in which
|
||
regimes of signs are assemblages of enunciation, which cannot be ade-
|
||
quately accounted for by any linguistic category: what makes a proposi-
|
||
tion or even a single word a "statement" pertains to implicit presupposi-
|
||
tions that cannot be made explicit, that mobilize pragmatic variables
|
||
proper to enunciation (incorporeal transformations). This precludes
|
||
explaining an assemblage in terms of the signifier or the subject, because
|
||
both pertain to variables of enunciation within the assemblage. It is
|
||
signifiance and subjectification that presuppose the assemblage, not the
|
||
reverse. The names we gave to the regimes of signs ("presignifying," "sig-
|
||
nifying," "countersignifying," "postsignifying") would remain evolution-
|
||
ist if heterogeneous functions or varieties of assemblages did not
|
||
effectively correspond to them (segmentarization, signifiance and inter-
|
||
pretation, numeration, subjectification). Regimes of signs are thus
|
||
defined by variables that are internal to enunciation but remain external
|
||
to the constants of language and irreducible to linguistic categories.
|
||
But at this point, everything turns around, and the reasons why a regime
|
||
of signs is less than language also become the reasons why it is more than
|
||
language. Only one side of the assemblage has to do with enunciation or
|
||
formalizes expression; on its other side, inseparable from the first, it for-
|
||
malizes contents, it is a machinic assemblage or an assemblage of bodies.
|
||
Now contents are not "signifieds" dependent upon a signifier in any way,
|
||
nor are they "objects" in any kind of relation of causality with the subject.
|
||
They have their own formalization and have no relation of symbolic corre-
|
||
spondence or linear causality with the form of expression: the two forms
|
||
are in reciprocal presupposition, and they can be abstracted from each
|
||
other only in a very relative way because they are two sides of a single
|
||
assemblage. We must therefore arrive at something in the assemblage itself
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 141
|
||
|
||
that is still more profound than these sides and can account for both of the
|
||
forms in presupposition, forms of expression or regimes of signs (semiotic
|
||
systems) and forms of content or regimes of bodies (physical systems). This
|
||
is what we call the abstract machine, which constitutes and conjugates all of
|
||
the assemblage's cutting edges of deterritorialization.39 We must say that
|
||
the abstract machine is necessarily "much more" than language. When lin-
|
||
guists (following Chomsky) rise to the idea of a purely language-based
|
||
abstract machine, our immediate objection is that their machine, far from
|
||
being too abstract, is not abstract enough because it is limited to the form of
|
||
expression and to alleged universals that presuppose language. Abstracting
|
||
content is an operation that appears all the more relative and inadequate
|
||
when seen from the viewpoint of abstraction itself. A true abstract machine
|
||
has no way of making a distinction within itself between a plane of expres-
|
||
sion and a plane of content because it draws a single plane of consistency,
|
||
which in turn formalizes contents and expressions according to strata and
|
||
reterritorializations. The abstract machine in itself is destratified, deter-
|
||
ritorialized; it has no form of its own (much less substance) and makes no
|
||
distinction within itself between content and expression, even though out-
|
||
side itself it presides over that distinction and distributes it in strata,
|
||
domains, and territories. An abstract machine in itself is not physical or
|
||
corporeal, any more than it is semiotic; it is diagrammatic (it knows noth-
|
||
ing of the distinction between the artificial and the natural either). It oper-
|
||
ates by matter, not by substance; by function, not by form. Substances and
|
||
forms are of expression "or" of content. But functions are not yet
|
||
"semiotically" formed, and matters are not yet "physically" formed. The
|
||
abstract machine is pure Matter-Function—a diagram independent of the
|
||
forms and substances, expressions and contents it will distribute.
|
||
We define the abstract machine as the aspect or moment at which noth-
|
||
ing but functions and matters remain. A diagram has neither substance nor
|
||
form, neither content nor expression.40 Substance is a formed matter, and
|
||
matter is a substance that is unformed either physically or semiotically.
|
||
Whereas expression and content have distinct forms, are really distinct
|
||
from each other, function has only "traits," of content and of expression,
|
||
between which it establishes a connection: it is no longer even possible to
|
||
tell whether it is a particle or a sign. A matter-content having only degrees
|
||
of intensity, resistance, conductivity, heating, stretching, speed, or tardi-
|
||
ness; and a function-expression having only "tensors," as in a system of
|
||
mathematical, or musical, writing. Writing now functions on the same
|
||
level as the real, and the real materially writes. The diagram retains the
|
||
most deterritorialized content and the most deterritorialized expression,
|
||
in order to conjugate them. Maximum deterritorialization sometimes
|
||
starts from a trait of content and sometimes from a trait of expression; that
|
||
142 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
trait is said to be "deterritorializing" in relation to the other precisely
|
||
because it diagrams it, carries it off, raises it to its own power. The most
|
||
deterritorialized element causes the other element to cross a threshold ena-
|
||
bling a conjunction of their respective deterritorializations, a shared accel-
|
||
eration. This is the abstract machine's absolute, positive deterritoria-
|
||
lization. That is why diagrams must be distinguished from indexes, which
|
||
are territorial signs, but also from icons, which pertain to reterrito-
|
||
rialization, and from symbols, which pertain to relative or negative deterri-
|
||
torialization.41 Defined diagrammatically in this way, an abstract machine
|
||
is neither an infrastructure that is determining in the last instance nor a
|
||
transcendental Idea that is determining in the supreme instance. Rather, it
|
||
plays a piloting role. The diagrammatic or abstract machine does not func-
|
||
tion to represent, even something real, but rather constructs a real that is
|
||
yet to come, a new type of reality. Thus when it constitutes points of cre-
|
||
ation or potentiality it does not stand outside history but is instead always
|
||
"prior to" history. Everything escapes, everything creates—never alone,
|
||
but through an abstract machine that produces continuums of intensity,
|
||
effects conjunctions of deterritorialization, and extracts expressions and
|
||
contents. This Real-Abstract is totally different from the fictitious abstrac-
|
||
tion of a supposedly pure machine of expression. It is an Absolute, but one
|
||
that is neither undifferentiated nor transcendent. Abstract machines thus
|
||
have proper names (as well as dates), which of course designate not persons
|
||
or subjects but matters and functions. The name of a musician or scientist
|
||
is used in the same way as a painter's name designates a color, nuance, tone,
|
||
or intensity: it is always a question of a conjunction of Matter and Func-
|
||
tion. The double deterritorialization of the voice and the instrument is
|
||
marked by a Wagner abstract machine, a Webern abstract machine, etc. In
|
||
physics and mathematics, we may speak of a Riemann abstract machine,
|
||
and in algebra of a Galois abstract machine (defined precisely by an arbi-
|
||
trary line, called the adjunctive line, which conjugates with a body taken as
|
||
a starting point), etc. There is a diagram whenever a singular abstract
|
||
machine functions directly in a matter.
|
||
Strictly speaking, therefore, there are no regimes of signs on the dia-
|
||
grammatic level, or on the plane of consistency, because form of expression
|
||
is no longer really distinct from form of content. The diagram knows only
|
||
traits and cutting edges that are still elements of content insofar as they are
|
||
material and of expression insofar as they are functional, but which draw
|
||
one another along, form relays, and meld in a shared deterritorialization:
|
||
particles-signs. There is nothing surprising in this, for the real distinction
|
||
between form of expression and form of content appears only with the
|
||
strata, and is different on each one. It is on the strata that the double articu-
|
||
lation appears that formalizes traits of expression and traits of content,
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 143
|
||
|
||
each in its own right, turning matters into physically or semiotically
|
||
formed substances and functions into forms of expression or content.
|
||
Expression then constitutes indexes, icons, or symbols that enter regimes
|
||
or semiotic systems. Content then constitutes bodies, things, or objects
|
||
that enter physical systems, organisms, and organizations. The deeper
|
||
movement for conjugating matter and function—absolute deterri-
|
||
torialization, identical to the earth itself—appears only in the form of
|
||
respective territorialities, negative or relative deterritorializations, and
|
||
complementary reterritorializations. All of this culminates in a language
|
||
stratum that installs an abstract machine on the level of expression and
|
||
takes the abstraction of content even further, tending to strip it of any form
|
||
of its own (the imperialism of language, the pretensions to a general
|
||
semiology). In short, the strata substantialize diagrammatic matters and
|
||
separate a formed plane of content from a formed plane of expression.
|
||
They hold expressions and contents, separately substantialized and forma-
|
||
lized, in the pincers of a double articulation assuring their independence
|
||
and real distinction and enthroning a dualism that endlessly reproduces
|
||
and redivides. They shatter the continuums of intensity, introducing
|
||
breaks between different strata and within each stratum. They prevent
|
||
conjunctions of flight from forming and crush the cutting edges of deterri-
|
||
torialization, either by effecting reterritorializations that make these
|
||
movements merely relative, or by assigning certain of the lines an entirely
|
||
negative value, or again by segmenting them, blocking them, plugging
|
||
them, or plunging them into a kind of black hole.
|
||
Above all, diagrammaticism should not be confused with an operation
|
||
of the axiomatic type. Far from drawing creative lines of flight and conju-
|
||
gating traits of positive deterritorialization, axiomatics blocks all lines,
|
||
subordinates them to a punctual system, and halts the geometric and alge-
|
||
braic writing systems that had begun to run off in all directions. This hap-
|
||
pened in relation to the question of indeterminism in physics: a "reorder-
|
||
ing" was undertaken to reconcile it with physical determinism. Mathemat-
|
||
ical writing systems were axiomatized, in other words, restratified,
|
||
resemiotized, and material flows were rephysicalized. It is as much a politi-
|
||
cal as a scientific affair: science must not go crazy. Hilbert and de Broglie
|
||
were as much politicians as scientists: they reestablished order. An
|
||
axiomatization, a semiotization, a physicalization, is not a diagram but in
|
||
fact the opposite of a diagram. The program of a stratum, against the dia-
|
||
gram of the plane of consistency. This does not, however, preclude the
|
||
diagram's heading back down the road to escape and scattering new, singu-
|
||
lar abstract machines (the mathematical creation of improbable functions
|
||
was carried out in opposition to axiomatization, and the material inven-
|
||
tion of unfindable particles in opposition to physicalization). Science as
|
||
144 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
such is like everything else; madness is as intrinsic to it as reorderings. The
|
||
same scientists may participate in both aspects, having their own madness,
|
||
police, signifiances, or subjectifications, as well as their own abstract
|
||
machines, all in their capacity as scientists. The phrase "the politics of sci-
|
||
ence" is a good designation for these currents, which are internal to science
|
||
and not simply circumstances and State factors that act upon it from the
|
||
outside, leading it to make as atomic bomb here and embark upon a space
|
||
program there. These political influences or determinations would not
|
||
exist if science itself did not have its own poles, oscillations, strata, and
|
||
destratifications, its own lines of flight and reorderings, in short, the more
|
||
or less potential events of its own politics, its own particular "polemics," its
|
||
own internal war machine (of which thwarted, persecuted, or hindered sci-
|
||
entists are historically a part). It is not enough to say that axiomatics does
|
||
not take invention and creation into account: it possesses a deliberate will
|
||
to halt or stabilize the diagram, to take its place by lodging itself on a level
|
||
of coagulated abstraction too large for the concrete but too small for the
|
||
real. We will see in what sense this is the "capitalist" level.
|
||
We cannot, however, content ourselves with a dualism between the
|
||
plane of consistency and its diagrams and abstract machines on the one
|
||
hand, and the strata and their programs and concrete assemblages on the
|
||
other. Abstract machines do not exist only on the plane of consistency,
|
||
upon which they develop diagrams; they are already present enveloped or
|
||
"encasted" in the strata in general, or even erected on particular strata
|
||
upon which they simultaneously organize a form of expression and a form
|
||
of content. What is illusory in the second case is the idea of an exclusively
|
||
expressive or language-based abstract machine, not the idea of an abstract
|
||
machine internal to the stratum and accounting for the relativity of those
|
||
two distinct forms. Thus there are two complementary movements, one by
|
||
which abstract machines work the strata and are constantly setting things
|
||
loose, another by which they are effectively stratified, effectively captured
|
||
by the strata. On the one hand, strata could never organize themselves if
|
||
they did not harness diagrammatic matters or functions and formalize
|
||
them from the standpoint of both expression and content; every regime of
|
||
signs, and even signifiance and subjectification, is still a diagrammatic
|
||
effect (although relativized and negativized). One the other hand, abstract
|
||
machines would never be present, even on the strata, if they did not have
|
||
the power or potentiality to extract and accelerate destratified particles-
|
||
signs (the passage to the absolute). Consistency is neither totalizing nor
|
||
structuring; rather, it is deterritorializing (a biological stratum, for exam-
|
||
ple, evolves not according to statistical phenomena but rather according to
|
||
cutting edges of deterritorialization). The security, tranquillity, and ho-
|
||
meostatic equilibrium of the strata are thus never completely guaranteed:
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 145
|
||
|
||
to regain a plane of consistency that inserts itself into the most diverse sys-
|
||
tems of stratification and jumps from one to the other, it suffices to prolong
|
||
the lines of flight working the strata, to connect the dots, to conjugate the
|
||
processes of deterritorialization. We have seen that signifiance and inter-
|
||
pretation, consciousness and passion, can prolong themselves following
|
||
these lines, and at the same time open out onto a properly diagrammatic
|
||
experience. All of these states or modes of the abstract machine coexist in
|
||
what we call the machinic assemblage. The assemblage has two poles or
|
||
vectors: one vector is oriented toward the strata, upon which it distributes
|
||
territorialities, relative deterritorializations, and reterritorializations; the
|
||
other is oriented toward the plane of consistency or destratification, upon
|
||
which it conjugates processes of deterritorialization, carrying them to the
|
||
absolute of the earth. It is along its stratic vector that the assemblage differ-
|
||
entiates a form of expression (from the standpoint of which it appears as a
|
||
collective assemblage of enunciation) from a form of content (from the
|
||
standpoint of which it appears as a machinic assemblage of bodies); it fits
|
||
one form to the other, one manifestation to the other, placing them in recip-
|
||
rocal presupposition. But along its diagrammatic or destratified vector, it
|
||
no longer has two sides; all it retains are traits of expression and content
|
||
from which it extracts degrees of deterritorialization that add together and
|
||
cutting edges that conjugate.
|
||
A regime of signs has more than just two components. It has, in fact, four
|
||
of them, which form the object of Pragmatics. The first was the generative
|
||
component, which shows how a form of expression located on the language
|
||
stratum always appeals to several combined regimes, in other words, how
|
||
every regime of signs or semiotic is concretely mixed. On the level of this
|
||
component, one can abstract forms of content, most successfully if empha-
|
||
sis is placed on the mixture of regimes in the form of expression: one should
|
||
not, however, conclude from this the predominance of a regime constitut-
|
||
ing a general semiology and unifying forms. The second, transformational,
|
||
component, shows how one abstract regime can be translated, transformed
|
||
into another, and especially how it can be created from other regimes. This
|
||
second component is obviously more profound, because all mixed regimes
|
||
presuppose these transformations from one regime to another, past, pres-
|
||
ent, or potential (as a function of the creation of new regimes). Once again,
|
||
one abstracts, or can abstract, content, since the analysis is limited to meta-
|
||
morphoses internal to the form of expression, even though the form of
|
||
expression is not adequate to account for them. The third component is
|
||
diagrammatic: it consists in taking regimes of signs or forms of expression
|
||
and extracting from them particles-signs that are no longer formalized but
|
||
instead constitute unformed traits capable of combining with one another.
|
||
This is the height of abstraction, but also the moment at which abstraction
|
||
146 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
becomes real; everything operates through abstract-real machines (which
|
||
have names and dates). One can abstract forms of content, but one must
|
||
simultaneously abstract forms of expression; for what is retained of each
|
||
are only unformed traits. That is why an abstract machine that would oper-
|
||
ate purely on the level of language is an absurdity. It is clear that this dia-
|
||
grammatic component is in turn more profound than the transformational
|
||
component: the creations-transformations of a regime of signs operate by
|
||
the emergence of ever-new abstract machines. Finally, the last, properly
|
||
machinic, component is meant to show how abstract machines are effectu-
|
||
ated in concrete assemblages; it is these assemblages that give distinct form
|
||
to traits of expression, but not without doing the same for traits of
|
||
content—the two forms being in reciprocal presupposition, or having a
|
||
necessary, unformed relation that once again prevents the form of expres-
|
||
sion from behaving as though it were self-sufficient (although it is indepen-
|
||
dent or distinct in a strictly formal way).
|
||
Thus pragmatics (or schizoanalysis) can be represented by four circular
|
||
components that bud and form rhizomes.
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
(1) The generative component: the study of concrete mixed semiotics; their mixtures
|
||
and variations. (2) The transformational component: the study of pure semiotics; their
|
||
transformations-translations and the creation of new semiotics. (3) The diagrammatic
|
||
component: the study of abstract machines, from the standpoint of semiotically
|
||
unformed matters in relation to physically unformed matters. (4) The machinic com-
|
||
ponent: the study of the assemblages that effectuate abstract machines, simultaneously
|
||
semiotizing matters of expression and physicalizing matters of content.
|
||
|
||
Pragmatics as a whole would consist in this: making a tracing of the
|
||
mixed semiotics, under the generative component; making the transfor-
|
||
mational map of the regimes, with their possibilities for translation and
|
||
creation, for budding along the lines of the tracings; making the diagram of
|
||
the abstract machines that are in play in each case, either as potentialities
|
||
or as effective emergences; outlining the program of the assemblages that
|
||
587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS D 147
|
||
|
||
distribute everything and bring a circulation of movement with alterna-
|
||
tives, jumps, and mutations.
|
||
For example, in considering a given "proposition," in other words, a ver-
|
||
bal aggregate defined syntactically, semantically, and logically as the
|
||
expression of an individual or group ("I love you" or "I am jealous"), one
|
||
would begin by asking to which "statement" this proposition corresponds
|
||
in the group or individual (for the same proposition can be tied to com-
|
||
pletely different statements). This question means: What regime of signs is
|
||
the proposition taken up by and without which its syntactical, semantic,
|
||
and logical elements would remain totally empty universal conditions?
|
||
What nonlinguistic element, or variable of enunciation, gives it consis-
|
||
tency? There is a presignifying "I love you" of the collective type in which,
|
||
as Miller says, a dance weds all the women of the tribe; there is a counter-
|
||
signifying "I love you" of the distributive and polemical type that has to do
|
||
with war and relations of force (the "I love you" of Penthesilea and Achil-
|
||
les); there is an "I love you" that is addressed to a center of signifiance and
|
||
uses interpretation to make a whole series of signifieds correspond to the
|
||
signifying chain; and there is a postsignifying or passional "I love you" that
|
||
constitutes a proceeding beginning from a point of subjectification, then
|
||
another, and yet another. Similarly, the proposition "I am jealous" is
|
||
clearly not the same statement in the passional regime of subjectification
|
||
as in the paranoid regime of signifiance: these are two distinct delusions.
|
||
Second, once it has been determined which statement the proposition cor-
|
||
responds to in a given group or individual at a given time, one would look
|
||
into the possibilities not only of mixture but also of translation and trans-
|
||
formation into another regime, or into statements belonging to other
|
||
regimes; one would look at what passes and does not pass in such a transfor-
|
||
mation, what remains irreducible and what flows. Third, one could try to
|
||
create new, as yet unknown statements for that proposition, even if the
|
||
result were a patois of sensual delight, physical and semiotic systems in
|
||
shreds, asubjective affects, signs without signifiance where syntax, seman-
|
||
tics, and logic are in collapse. This research should go from the worst to the
|
||
best since it would cover precious, metaphorical, or stultifying regimes as
|
||
well as cries-whispers, feverish improvisations, becomings-animal,
|
||
becomings-molecular, real transsexualities, continuums of intensity, con-
|
||
stitutions of bodies without organs . .. These two poles are inseparable;
|
||
they entertain perpetual relations of transformation, conversion, jumping,
|
||
falling, and rising. This final research simultaneously brings into play, on
|
||
the one hand, abstract machines, diagrams and diagrammatic functions,
|
||
and, on the other hand, machinic assemblages, the formal distinctions they
|
||
make between expression and content, and their investments of words and
|
||
organs according to a relation of reciprocal presupposition. For example,
|
||
148 D 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: ON SEVERAL REGIMES OF SIGNS
|
||
|
||
the "I love you" of courtly love: What is its diagram, what abstract machine
|
||
emerges, and what is the new assemblage? These questions apply as much
|
||
to destratification as to the organization of strata. In short, there are no
|
||
syntactically, semantically, or logically definable propositions that tran-
|
||
scend or loom above statements. All methods for the transcendentaliza-
|
||
tion of language, all methods for endowing language with universals, from
|
||
Russell's logic to Chomsky's grammar, have fallen into the worst kind of
|
||
abstraction, in the sense that they validate a level that is both too abstract
|
||
and not abstract enough. Regimes of signs are not based on language, and
|
||
language alone does not constitute an abstract machine, whether structural
|
||
or generative. The opposite is the case. It is language that is based on
|
||
regimes of signs, and regimes of signs on abstract machines, diagrammatic
|
||
functions, and machinic assemblages that go beyond any system of
|
||
semiology, linguistics, or logic. There is no universal prepositional logic,
|
||
nor is there grammaticality in itself, any more than there is signifier for
|
||
itself. "Behind" statements and semioticizations there are only machines,
|
||
assemblages, and movements of deterritorialization that cut across the
|
||
stratification of the various systems and elude both the coordinates of lan-
|
||
guage and of existence. That is why pragmatics is not a complement to
|
||
logic, syntax, or semantics; on the contrary, it is the fundamental element
|
||
upon which all the rest depend.
|
||
6. November 28, 1947: How Do You
|
||
Make Yourself
|
||
a Body without Organs?
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
The Dogon Egg and the Distribution of Intensities
|
||
|
||
At any rate, you have one (or several). It's not so much that it preexists or
|
||
comes ready-made, although in certain respects it is preexistent. At any
|
||
rate, you make one, you can't desire without making one. And it awaits you;
|
||
it is an inevitable exercise or experimentation, already accomplished the
|
||
moment you undertake it, unaccomplished as long as you don't. This is not
|
||
reassuring, because you can botch it. Or it can be terrifying, and lead you to
|
||
your death. It is nondesire as well as desire. It is not at all a notion or a
|
||
149
|
||
150 D HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS?
|
||
|
||
concept but a practice, a set of practices. You never reach the Body without
|
||
Organs, you can't reach it, you are forever attaining it, it is a limit. People
|
||
ask, So what is this BwO?—But you're already on it, scurrying like a ver-
|
||
min, groping like a blind person, or running like a lunatic: desert traveler
|
||
and nomad of the steppes. On it we sleep, live our waking lives, fight—fight
|
||
and are fought—seek our place, experience untold happiness and fabulous
|
||
defeats; on it we penetrate and are penetrated; on it we love. On November
|
||
28,1947, Artaud declares war on the organs: To be done with the judgment
|
||
of God, "for you can tie me up if you wish, but there is nothing more useless
|
||
than an organ."1 Experimentation: not only radiophonic but also biologi-
|
||
cal and political, incurring censorship and repression. Corpus and Socius,
|
||
politics and experimentation. They will not let you experiment in peace.
|
||
The BwO: it is already under way the moment the body has had enough
|
||
of organs and wants to slough them off, or loses them. A long procession.
|
||
The hypochondriac body: the organs are destroyed, the damage has already
|
||
been done, nothing happens anymore. "Miss X claims that she no longer
|
||
has a brain or nerves or chest or stomach or guts. All she has left is the skin
|
||
and bones of a disorganized body. These are her own words."2 The para-
|
||
noid body: the organs are continually under attack by outside forces, but
|
||
are also restored by outside energies. ("He lived for a long time without a
|
||
stomach, without intestines, almost without lungs, with a torn oesophagus,
|
||
without a bladder, and with shattered ribs, he used sometimes to swallow
|
||
part of his own larynx with his food, etc. But divine miracles ('rays') always
|
||
restored what had been destroyed.")3 The schizo body, waging its own
|
||
active internal struggle against the organs, at the price of catatonia. Then
|
||
the drugged body, the experimental schizo: "The human body is scandal-
|
||
ously inefficient. Instead of a mouth and an anus to get out of order why not
|
||
have one all-purpose hole to eat and eliminate? We could seal up nose and
|
||
mouth, fill in the stomach, make an air hole direct into the lungs where it
|
||
should have been in the first place."4 The masochist body: it is poorly
|
||
understood in terms of pain; it is fundamentally a question of the BwO. It
|
||
has its sadist or whore sew it up; the eyes, anus, urethra, breasts, and nose
|
||
are sewn shut. It has itself strung up to stop the organs from working;
|
||
flayed, as if the organs clung to the skin; sodomized, smothered, to make
|
||
sure everything is sealed tight.
|
||
Why such a dreary parade of sucked-dry, catatonicized, vitrified,
|
||
sewn-up bodies, when the BwO is also full of gaiety, ecstasy, and dance? So
|
||
why these examples, why must we start there? Emptied bodies instead of
|
||
full ones. What happened? Were you cautious enough? Not wisdom, cau-
|
||
tion. In doses. As a rule immanent to experimentation: injections of cau-
|
||
tion. Many have been defeated in this battle. Is it really so sad and
|
||
dangerous to be fed up with seeing with your eyes, breathing with your
|
||
HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS? D 151
|
||
|
||
lungs, swallowing with your mouth, talking with your tongue, thinking with
|
||
your brain, having an anus and larynx, head and legs? Why not walk on
|
||
your head, sing with your sinuses, see through your skin, breathe with your
|
||
belly: the simple Thing, the Entity, the full Body, the stationary Voyage,
|
||
Anorexia, cutaneous Vision, Yoga, Krishna, Love, Experimentation.
|
||
Where psychoanalysis says, "Stop, find your self again," we should say
|
||
instead, "Let's go further still, we haven't found our BwO yet, we haven't
|
||
sufficiently dismantled our self." Substitute forgetting for anamnesis,
|
||
experimentation for interpretation. Find your body without organs. Find
|
||
out how to make it. It's a question of life and death, youth and old age, sad-
|
||
ness and joy. It is where everything is played out.
|
||
"Mistress, 1) You may tie me down on the table, ropes drawn tight, for
|
||
ten to fifteen minutes, time enough to prepare the instruments; 2) One
|
||
hundred lashes at least, a pause of several minutes; 3) You begin sewing,
|
||
you sew up the hole in the glans; you sew the skin around the glans to the
|
||
glans itself, preventing the top from tearing; you sew the scrotum to the skin
|
||
of the thighs. You sew the breasts, securely attaching a button with four
|
||
holes to each nipple. You may connect them with an elastic band with
|
||
buttonholes—Now you go on to the second phase: 4) You can choose either
|
||
to turn me over on the table so I am tied lying on my stomach, but with my
|
||
legs together, or to bind me to the post with my wrists together, and my legs
|
||
also, my whole body tightly bound; 5) You whip my back buttocks thighs, a
|
||
hundred lashes at least; 6) You sew my buttocks together, all the way up and
|
||
down the crack of my ass. Tightly, with a doubled thread, each stitch knot-
|
||
ted. If I am on the table, now tie me to the post; 7) You give me fifty thrashes
|
||
on the buttocks; 8) If you wish to intensify the torture and carry out your
|
||
threat from last time, stick the pins all the way into my buttocks as far as
|
||
they go; 9) Then you may tie me to the chair; you give me thirty thrashes on
|
||
the breasts and stick in the smaller pins; if you wish, you may heat them
|
||
red-hot beforehand, all or sorne. I should be tightly bound to the chair,
|
||
hands behind my back so my chest sticks out. I haven't mentioned burns,
|
||
only because I have a medical exam coming up in awhile, and they take a
|
||
long time to heal." This is not a phantasy, it is a program: There is an essen-
|
||
tial difference between the psychoanalytic interpretation of the phantasy
|
||
and the antipsychiatric experimentation of the program. Between the
|
||
phantasy, an interpretation that must itself be interpreted, and the motor
|
||
program of experimentation.5 The BwO is what remains when you take
|
||
everything away. What you take away is precisely the phantasy, and
|
||
signifiances and subjectifications as a whole. Psychoanalysis does the
|
||
opposite: it translates everything into phantasies, it converts everything
|
||
into phantasy, it retains the phantasy. It royally botches the real, because it
|
||
botches the BwO.
|
||
152 D HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS?
|
||
|
||
Something will happen. Something is already happening. But what
|
||
comes to pass on the BwO is not exactly the same as how you make yourself
|
||
one. However, one is included in the other. Hence the two phases set forth
|
||
in the preceding letter. Why two clearly distinguished phases, when the
|
||
same thing is done in both cases—sewing and flogging? One phase is for the
|
||
fabrication of the BwO, the other to make something circulate on it or pass
|
||
across it; the same procedures are nevertheless used in both phases, but
|
||
they must be done over, done twice. What is certain is that the masochist
|
||
has made himself a BwO under such conditions that the BwO can no longer
|
||
be populated by anything but intensities of pain, pain waves. It is false to
|
||
say that the masochist is looking for pain but just as false to say that he is
|
||
looking for pleasure in a particularly suspensive or roundabout way. The
|
||
masochist is looking for a type of BwO that only pain can fill, or travel over,
|
||
due to the very conditions under which that BwO was constituted. Pains
|
||
are populations, packs, modes of king-masochist-in-the-desert that he
|
||
engenders and augments. The same goes for the drugged body and intensi-
|
||
ties of cold, refrigerator waves. For each type of BwO, we must ask: (1) What
|
||
type is it, how is it fabricated, by what procedures and means (predeter-
|
||
mining what will come to pass)? (2) What are its modes, what comes to
|
||
pass, and with what variants and what surprises, what is unexpected and
|
||
what expected? In short, there is a very special relation of synthesis and
|
||
analysis between a given type of BwO and what happens on it: an a priori
|
||
synthesis by which something will necessarily be produced in a given mode
|
||
(but what it will be is not known) and an infinite analysis by which what is
|
||
produced on the BwO is already part of that body's production, is already
|
||
included in the body, is already on it (but at the price of an infinity of pas-
|
||
sages, divisions, and secondary productions). It is a very delicate experi-
|
||
mentation since there must not be any stagnation of the modes or slippage
|
||
in type: the masochist and the drug user court these ever-present dangers
|
||
that empty their BwO's instead of filling them.
|
||
You can fail twice, but it is the same failure, the same danger. Once at the
|
||
level of the constitution of the BwO and again at the level of what passes or
|
||
does not pass across it. You think you have made yourself a good BwO, that
|
||
you chose the right Place, Power (Puissance), and Collectivity (there is
|
||
always a collectivity, even when you are alone), and then nothing passes,
|
||
nothing circulates, or something prevents things from moving. A paranoid
|
||
point, a point of blockage, an outburst of delirium: it comes across clearly
|
||
in Speed, by William Burroughs, Jr. Is it possible to locate this danger
|
||
point, should the block be expelled, or should one instead "love, honor, and
|
||
serve degeneracy wherever it surfaces"? To block, to be blocked, is that not
|
||
still an intensity? In each case, we must define what comes to pass and what
|
||
does not pass, what causes passage and prevents it. As in the meat circuit
|
||
HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS? D 153
|
||
|
||
according to Lewin, something flows through channels whose sections are
|
||
delimited by doors with gatekeepers, passers-on.6 Door openers and trap
|
||
closers, Malabars and Fierabras. The body is now nothing more than a set
|
||
of valves, locks, floodgates, bowls, or communicating vessels, each with a
|
||
proper name: a peopling of the BwO, a Metropolis that has to be managed
|
||
with a whip. What peoples it, what passes across it, what does the blocking?
|
||
A BwO is made in such a way that it can be occupied, populated only by
|
||
intensities. Only intensities pass and circulate. Still, the BwO is not a scene,
|
||
a place, or even a support upon which something comes to pass. It has noth-
|
||
ing to do with phantasy, there is nothing to interpret. The BwO causes
|
||
intensities to pass; it produces and distributes them in a spatium that is
|
||
itself intensive, lacking extension. It is not space, nor is it in space; it is mat-
|
||
ter that occupies space to a given degree—to the degree corresponding to
|
||
the intensities produced. It is nonstratified, unformed, intense matter, the
|
||
matrix of intensity, intensity = 0; but there is nothing negative about that
|
||
zero, there are no negative or opposite intensities. Matter equals energy.
|
||
Production of the real as an intensive magnitude starting at zero. That is
|
||
why we treat the BwO as the full egg before the extension of the organism
|
||
and the organization of the organs, before the formation of the strata; as the
|
||
intense egg defined by axes and vectors, gradients and thresholds, by
|
||
dynamic tendencies involving energy transformation and kinematic
|
||
movements involving group displacement, by migrations: all independent
|
||
of accessory forms because the organs appear and function here only as
|
||
pure intensities.7 The organ changes when it crosses a threshold, when it
|
||
changes gradient. "No organ is constant as regards either function or posi-
|
||
tion, . . . sex organs sprout anywhere,... rectums open, defecate and close,
|
||
. . . the entire organism changes color and consistency in split-second
|
||
adjustments."8 The tantric egg.
|
||
After all, is not Spinoza's Ethics the great book of the BwO? The attri-
|
||
butes are types or genuses of BwO's, substances, powers, zero intensities as
|
||
matrices of production. The modes are everything that comes to pass:
|
||
waves and vibrations, migrations, thresholds and gradients, intensities
|
||
produced in a given type of substance starting from a given matrix. The
|
||
masochist body as an attribute or genus of substance, with its production
|
||
of intensities and pain modes based on its degree 0 of being sewn up. The
|
||
drugged body as a different attribute, with its production of specific inten-
|
||
sities based on absolute Cold = 0. ("Junkies always beef about The Cold as
|
||
they call it, turning up their black coat collars and clutching their withered
|
||
necks . . . pure junk con. A junky does not want to be warm, he wants to be
|
||
cool-cooler-COLD. But he wants The Cold like he wants His Junk—NOT
|
||
OUTSIDE where it does him no good but INSIDE so he can sit around with a
|
||
spine like a frozen hydraulic jack... his metabolism approaching Absolute
|
||
154 D HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS?
|
||
|
||
Zero.")9 Etc. The problem of whether there is a substance of all substances,
|
||
a single substance for all attributes, becomes: Is there a totality of all
|
||
BwO'sl If the BwO is already a limit, what must we say of the totality of all
|
||
BwO's? It is a problem not of the One and the Multiple but of a fusional
|
||
multiplicity that effectively goes beyond any opposition between the one
|
||
and the multiple. A formal multiplicity of substantial attributes that, as
|
||
such, constitutes the ontological unity of substance. There is a continuum
|
||
of all of the attributes or genuses of intensity under a single substance, and
|
||
a continuum of the intensities of a certain genus under a single type or
|
||
attribute. A continuum of all substances in intensity and of all intensities
|
||
in substance. The uninterrupted continuum of the BwO. BwO, imma-
|
||
nence, immanent limit. Drug users, masochists, schizophrenics, lovers—
|
||
all BwO's pay homage to Spinoza. The BwO is the field of immanence of
|
||
desire, the plane of consistency specific to desire (with desire defined as a
|
||
process of production without reference to any exterior agency, whether it
|
||
be a lack that hollows it out or a pleasure that fills it).
|
||
Every time desire is betrayed, cursed, uprooted from its field of
|
||
immanence, a priest is behind it. The priest cast the triple curse on desire:
|
||
the negative law, the extrinsic rule, and the transcendent ideal. Facing
|
||
north, the priest said, Desire is lack (how could it not lack what it desires?).
|
||
The priest carried out the first sacrifice, named castration, and all the men
|
||
and women of the north lined up behind him, crying in cadence, "Lack,
|
||
lack, it's the common law." Then, facing south, the priest linked desire to
|
||
pleasure. For there are hedonistic, even orgiastic, priests. Desire will be
|
||
assuaged by pleasure; and not only will the pleasure obtained silence desire
|
||
for a moment but the process of obtaining it is already a way of interrupting
|
||
it, of instantly discharging it and unburdening oneself of it. Pleasure as dis-
|
||
charge: the priest carries out the second sacrifice, named masturbation.
|
||
Then, facing east, he exclaimed: Jouissance is impossible, but impossible
|
||
jouissance is inscribed in desire. For that, in its very impossibility, is the
|
||
Ideal, the "manque-a-jouir that is life."10 The priest carried out the third
|
||
sacrifice, phantasy or the thousand and one nights, the one hundred twenty
|
||
days, while the men of the East chanted: Yes, we will be your phantasy, your
|
||
ideal and impossibility, yours and also our own. The priest did not turn to
|
||
the west. He knew that in the west lay a plane of consistency, but he thought
|
||
that the way was blocked by the columns of Hercules, that it led nowhere
|
||
and was uninhabited by people. But that is where desire was lurking, west
|
||
was the shortest route east, as well as to the other directions, rediscovered
|
||
or deterritorialized.
|
||
The most recent figure of the priest is the psychoanalyst, with his or her
|
||
three principles: Pleasure, Death, and Reality. Doubtless, psychoanalysis
|
||
demonstrated that desire is not subordinated to procreation, or even to
|
||
HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS? D 155
|
||
|
||
genitality. That was its modernism. But it retained the essentials; it even
|
||
found new ways of inscribing in desire the negative law of lack, the external
|
||
rule of pleasure, and the transcendent ideal of phantasy. Take the interpre-
|
||
tation of masochism: when the ridiculous death instinct is not invoked, it is
|
||
claimed that the masochist, like everybody else, is after pleasure but can
|
||
only get it through pain and phantasied humiliations whose function is to
|
||
allay or ward off deep anxiety. This is inaccurate; the masochist's suffering
|
||
is the price he must pay, not to achieve pleasure, but to untie the
|
||
pseudobond between desire and pleasure as an extrinsic measure. Pleasure
|
||
is in no way something that can be attained only by a detour through suffer-
|
||
ing; it is something that must be delayed as long as possible because it inter-
|
||
rupts the continuous process of positive desire. There is, in fact, a joy that is
|
||
immanent to desire as though desire were filled by itself and its contempla-
|
||
tions, a joy that implies no lack or impossibility and is not measured by
|
||
pleasure since it is what distributes intensities of pleasure and prevents
|
||
them from being suffused by anxiety, shame, and guilt. In short, the mas-
|
||
ochist uses suffering as a way of constituting a body without organs and
|
||
bringing forth a plane of consistency of desire. That there are other ways,
|
||
other procedures than masochism, and certainly better ones, is beside the
|
||
point; it is enough that some find this procedure suitable for them.
|
||
Take a masochist who did not undergo psychoanalysis: "PROGRAM . . .
|
||
At night, put on the bridle and attach my hands more tightly, either to the
|
||
bit with the chain, or to the big belt right after returning from the bath. Put
|
||
on the entire harness right away also, the reins and thumbscrews, and
|
||
attach the thumbscrews to the harness. My penis should be in a metal
|
||
sheath. Ride the reins for two hours during the day, and in the evening as
|
||
the master wishes. Confinement for three or four days, hands still tied, the
|
||
reins alternately tightened and loosened. The master will never approach
|
||
her horse without the crop, and without using it. If the animal should dis-
|
||
play impatience or rebelliousness, the reins will be drawn tighter, the mas-
|
||
ter will grab them and give the beast a good thrashing."11 What is this
|
||
masochist doing? He seems to be imitating a horse, Equus eroticus, but
|
||
that's not it. Nor are the horse and the master-trainer or mistress images of
|
||
the mother or father. Something entirely different is going on: a becoming-
|
||
animal essential to masochism. It is a question of forces. The masochist
|
||
presents it this way: Training axiom—destroy the instinctive forces in order
|
||
to replace them with transmitted forces. In fact, it is less a destruction than
|
||
an exchange and circulation ("what happens to a horse can also happen to
|
||
me"). Horses are trained: humans impose upon the horse's instinctive
|
||
forces transmitted forces that regulate the former, select, dominate,
|
||
overcode them. The masochist effects an inversion of signs: the horse
|
||
transmits its transmitted forces to him, so that the masochist's innate
|
||
156 D HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS?
|
||
|
||
forces will in turn be tamed. There are two series, the horse's (innate force,
|
||
force transmitted by the human being), and the masochist's (force trans-
|
||
mitted by the horse, innate force of the human being). One series explodes
|
||
into the other, forms a circuit with it: an increase in power or a circuit of
|
||
intensities. The "master," or rather the mistress-rider, the equestrian,
|
||
ensures the conversion offerees and the inversion of signs. The masochist
|
||
constructs an entire assemblage that simultaneously draws and fills the
|
||
field of immanence of desire; he constitutes a body without organs or plane
|
||
of consistency using himself, the horse, and the mistress. "Results to be
|
||
obtained: that I am kept in continual expectancy of actions and orders, and
|
||
that little by little all opposition is replaced by a fusion of my person with
|
||
yours. . . . Thus at the mere thought of your boots, without even acknowl-
|
||
edging it, I must feel fear. In this way, it will no longer be women's legs that
|
||
have an effect on me, and if it pleases you to command me to receive your
|
||
caresses, when you have had them and if you make me feel them, you will
|
||
give me the imprint of your body as I have never had it before and never
|
||
would have had it otherwise."'2 Legs are still organs, but the boots now only
|
||
determine a zone of intensity as an imprint or zone on a BwO.
|
||
Similarly, or actually in a different way, it would be an error to interpret
|
||
courtly love in terms of a law of lack or an ideal of transcendence. The
|
||
renunciation of external pleasure, or its delay, its infinite regress, testifies
|
||
on the contrary to an achieved state in which desire no longer lacks any-
|
||
thing but fills itself and constructs its own field of immanence. Pleasure is
|
||
an affection of a person or a subject; it is the only way for persons to "find
|
||
themselves" in the process of desire that exceeds them; pleasures, even the
|
||
most artificial, are reterritorializations. But the question is precisely
|
||
whether it is necessary to find oneself. Courtly love does not love the self,
|
||
any more than it loves the whole universe in a celestial or religious way. It is
|
||
a question of making a body without organs upon which intensities pass,
|
||
self and other—not in the name of a higher level of generality or a broader
|
||
extension, but by virtue of singularities that can no longer be said to be per-
|
||
sonal, and intensities that can no longer be said to be extensive. The field of
|
||
immanence is not internal to the self, but neither does it come from an
|
||
external self or a nonself. Rather, it is like the absolute Outside that knows
|
||
no Selves because interior and exterior are equally a part of the immanence
|
||
in which they have fused. "Joy" in courtly love, the exchange of hearts, the
|
||
test or "assay": everything is allowed, as long as it is not external to desire or
|
||
transcendent to its plane, or else internal to persons. The slightest caress
|
||
may be as strong as an orgasm; orgasm is a mere fact, a rather deplorable
|
||
one, in relation to desire in pursuit of its principle. Everything is allowed:
|
||
all that counts is for pleasure to be the flow of desire itself, Immanence,
|
||
instead of a measure that interrupts it or delivers it to the three phantoms,
|
||
HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS? D 157
|
||
|
||
namely, internal lack, higher transcendence, and apparent exteriority.13 If
|
||
pleasure is not the norm of desire, it is not by virtue of a lack that is impossi-
|
||
ble to fill but, on the contrary, by virtue of its positivity, in other words, the
|
||
plane of consistency it draws in the course of its process.
|
||
A great Japanese compilation of Chinese Taoist treatises was made in
|
||
A.D. 982-984. We see in it the formation of a circuit of intensities between
|
||
female and male energy, with the woman playing the role of the innate or
|
||
instinctive force (Yin) stolen by or transmitted to the man in such a way
|
||
that the transmitted force of the man (Yang) in turn becomes innate, all the
|
||
more innate: an augmentation of powers.14 The condition for this circula-
|
||
tion and multiplication is that the man not ejaculate. It is not a question of
|
||
experiencing desire as an internal lack, nor of delaying pleasure in order to
|
||
produce a kind of externalizable surplus value, but instead of constituting
|
||
an intensive body without organs, Tao, a field of immanence in which
|
||
desire lacks nothing and therefore cannot be linked to any external or tran-
|
||
scendent criterion. It is true that the whole circuit can be channeled toward
|
||
procreative ends (ejaculation when the energies are right); that is how Con-
|
||
fucianism understood it. But this is true only for one side of the assemblage
|
||
of desire, the side facing the strata, organisms, State, family... It is not
|
||
true for the other side, the Tao side of destratification that draws a plane of
|
||
consistency proper to desire. Is the Tao masochistic? Is courtly love Taoist?
|
||
These questions are largely meaningless. The field of immanence or plane
|
||
of consistency must be constructed. This can take place in very different
|
||
social formations through very different assemblages (perverse, artistic,
|
||
scientific, mystical, political) with different types of bodies without
|
||
organs. It is constructed piece by piece, and the places, conditions, and
|
||
techniques are irreducible to one another. The question, rather, is whether
|
||
the pieces can fit together, and at what price. Inevitably, there will be mon-
|
||
strous crossbreeds. The plane of consistency would be the totality of all
|
||
BwO's, a pure multiplicity of immanence, one piece of which may be Chi-
|
||
nese, another American, another medieval, another petty perverse, but all
|
||
in a movement of generalized deterritorialization in which each person
|
||
takes and makes what she or he can, according to tastes she or he will have
|
||
succeeded in abstracting from a Self [Moi], according to a politics or strat-
|
||
egy successfully abstracted from a given formation, according to a given
|
||
procedure abstracted from its origin.
|
||
We distinguish between: (1) BwO's, which are different types, genuses,
|
||
or substantial attributes. For example, the Cold of the drugged BwO, the
|
||
Pain of the masochist BwO. Each has its degree 0 as its principle of produc-
|
||
tion (remissio). (2) What happens on each type of BwO, in other words, the
|
||
modes, the intensities that are produced, the waves that pass (latitude). (3)
|
||
The potential totality of all BwO's, the plane of consistency (Omnitudo,
|
||
158 D HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS?
|
||
|
||
sometimes called the BwO). There are a number of questions. Not only
|
||
how to make oneself a BwO, and how to produce the corresponding
|
||
intensities without which it would remain empty (not exactly the same
|
||
question). But also how to reach the plane of consistency. How to sew up,
|
||
cool down, and tie together all the BwO's. If this is possible to do, it is only
|
||
by conjugating the intensities produced on each BwO, by producing a con-
|
||
tinuum of all intensive continuities. Are not assemblages necessary to fab-
|
||
ricate each BwO, is not a great abstract Machine necessary to construct the
|
||
plane of consistency? Gregory Bateson uses the term plateau for continu-
|
||
ous regions of intensity constituted in such a way that they do not allow
|
||
themselves to be interrupted by any external termination, any more than
|
||
they allow themselves to build toward a climax; examples are certain sex-
|
||
ual, or aggressive, processes in Balinese culture.15 A plateau is a piece of
|
||
immanence. Every BwO is made up of plateaus. Every BwO is itself a pla-
|
||
teau in communication with other plateaus on the plane of consistency.
|
||
The BwO is a component of passage.
|
||
A rereading of Heliogabale and Les Tarahumaras. For Heliogabalus is
|
||
Spinoza, and Spinoza is Heliogabalus revived. And the Tarahumaras are
|
||
experimentation, peyote. Spinoza, Heliogabalus, and experimentation
|
||
have the same formula: anarchy and unity are one and the same thing, not
|
||
the unity of the One, but a much stranger unity that applies only to the mul-
|
||
tiple.16 These two books by Artaud express the multiplicity of fusion,
|
||
fusionability as infinite zero, the plane of consistency, Matter where no
|
||
gods go; principles as forces, essences, substances, elements, remissions,
|
||
productions; manners of being or modalities as produced intensities,
|
||
vibrations, breaths, Numbers. Finally, the difficulty of reaching this world
|
||
of crowned Anarchy if you go no farther than the organs ("the liver that
|
||
turns the skin yellow, the brain wracked by syphilis, the intestines that
|
||
expel filth") and if you stay locked into the organism, or into a stratum that
|
||
blocks the flows and anchors us in this, our world.
|
||
We come to the gradual realization that the BwO is not at all the opposite
|
||
of the organs. The organs are not its enemies. The enemy is the organism.
|
||
The BwO is opposed not to the organs but to that organization of the organs
|
||
called the organism. It is true that Artaud wages a struggle against the
|
||
organs, but at the same time what he is going after, what he has it in for, is
|
||
the organism: The body is the body. Alone it stands. And in no need of
|
||
organs. Organism it never is. Organisms are the enemies of the body.11 The
|
||
BwO is not opposed to the organs; rather, the BwO and its "true organs,"
|
||
which must be composed and positioned, are opposed to the organism, the
|
||
organic organization of the organs. The judgment of God, the system of the
|
||
judgment of God, the theological system, is precisely the operation of He
|
||
who makes an organism, an organization of organs called the organism,
|
||
HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS? D 159
|
||
|
||
because He cannot bear the BwO, because He pursues it and rips it apart so
|
||
He can be first, and have the organism be first. The organism is already
|
||
that, the judgment of God, from which medical doctors benefit and on
|
||
which they base their power. The organism is not at all the body, the BwO;
|
||
rather, it is a stratum on the BwO, in other words, a phenomenon of accu-
|
||
mulation, coagulation, and sedimentation that, in order to extract useful
|
||
labor from the BwO, imposes upon it forms, functions, bonds, dominant
|
||
and hierarchized organizations, organized transcendences. The strata are
|
||
bonds, pincers. "Tie me up if you wish." We are continually stratified. But
|
||
who is this we that is not me, for the subject no less than the organism
|
||
belongs to and depends on a stratum? Now we have the answer: the BwO is
|
||
that glacial reality where the alluvions, sedimentations, coagulations,
|
||
foldings, and recoilings that compose an organism—and also a significa-
|
||
tion and a subject—occur. For the judgment of God weighs upon and is
|
||
exercised against the BwO; it is the BwO that undergoes it. It is in the BwO
|
||
that the organs enter into the relations of composition called the organism.
|
||
The BwO howls: "They've made me an organism! They've wrongfully
|
||
folded me! They've stolen my body!" The judgment of God uproots it from
|
||
its immanence and makes it an organism, a signification, a subject. It is the
|
||
BwO that is stratified. It swings between two poles, the surfaces of stratifi-
|
||
cation into which it is recoiled, on which it submits to the judgment, and
|
||
the plane of consistency in which it unfurls and opens to experimentation.
|
||
If the BwO is a limit, if one is forever attaining it, it is because behind each
|
||
stratum, encasted in it, there is always another stratum. For many a stra-
|
||
tum, and not only an organism, is necessary to make the judgment of God.
|
||
A perpetual and violent combat between the plane of consistency, which
|
||
frees the BwO, cutting across and dismantling all of the strata, and the sur-
|
||
faces of stratification that block it or make it recoil.
|
||
Let us consider the three great strata concerning us, in other words, the
|
||
ones that most directly bind us: the organism, signifiance, and subjectifi-
|
||
cation. The surface of the organism, the angle of signifiance and interpreta-
|
||
tion, and the point of subjectification or subjection. You will be organized,
|
||
you will be an organism, you will articulate your body—otherwise you're
|
||
just depraved. You will be signifier and signified, interpreter and
|
||
interpreted—otherwise you're just a deviant. You will be a subject, nailed
|
||
down as one, a subject of the enunciation recoiled into a subject of the
|
||
statement—otherwise you're just a tramp. To the strata as a whole, the
|
||
BwO opposes disarticulation (or n articulations) as the property of the
|
||
plane of consistency, experimentation as the operation on that plane (no
|
||
signifier, never interpret!), and nomadism as the movement (keep moving,
|
||
even in place, never stop moving, motionless voyage, desubjectification).
|
||
What does it mean to disarticulate, to cease to be an organism? How can we
|
||
160 D HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS?
|
||
|
||
convey how easy it is, and the extent to which we do it every day? And how
|
||
necessary caution is, the art of dosages, since overdose is a danger. You
|
||
don't do it with a sledgehammer, you use a very fine file. You invent self-
|
||
destructions that have nothing to do with the death drive. Dismantling the
|
||
organism has never meant killing yourself, but rather opening the body to
|
||
connections that presuppose an entire assemblage, circuits, conjunctions,
|
||
levels and thresholds, passages and distributions of intensity, and territor-
|
||
ies and deterritorializations measured with the craft of a surveyor. Actu-
|
||
ally, dismantling the organism is no more difficult than dismantling the
|
||
other two strata, signifiance and subjectification. Signifiance clings to the
|
||
soul just as the organism clings to the body, and it is not easy to get rid of
|
||
either. And how can we unhook ourselves from the points of subjectifi-
|
||
cation that secure us, nail us down to a dominant reality? Tearing the con-
|
||
scious away from the subject in order to make it a means of exploration,
|
||
tearing the unconscious away from signifiance and interpretation in order
|
||
to make it a veritable production: this is assuredly no more or less difficult
|
||
than tearing the body away from the organism. Caution is the art common
|
||
to all three; if in dismantling the organism there are times one courts death,
|
||
in slipping away from signifiance and subjection one courts falsehood, illu-
|
||
sion and hallucination and psychic death. Artaud weighs and measures
|
||
every word: the conscious "knows what is good for it and what is of no value
|
||
to it: it knows which thoughts and feelings it can receive without danger
|
||
and with profit, and which are harmful to the exercise of its freedom.
|
||
Above all, it knows just how far its own being goes, and just how far it has
|
||
not yet gone or does not have the right to go without sinking into the unreal,
|
||
the illusory, the unmade, the unprepared . . . a Plane which normal con-
|
||
sciousness does not reach but which Ciguri allows us to reach, and which is
|
||
the very mystery of all poetry. But there is in human existence another
|
||
plane, obscure and formless, where consciousness has not entered, and
|
||
which surrounds it like an unilluminated extension or a menace, as the case
|
||
may be. And which itself gives off adventurous sensations, perceptions.
|
||
These are those shameless fantasies which affect an unhealthy con-
|
||
scious. . . . I too have had false sensations and perceptions and I have
|
||
believed in them."18
|
||
You have to keep enough of the organism for it to reform each dawn; and
|
||
you have to keep small supplies of signifiance and subjectification, if only
|
||
to turn them against their own systems when the circumstances demand it,
|
||
when things, persons, even situations, force you to; and you have to keep
|
||
small rations of subjectivity in sufficient quantity to enable you to respond
|
||
to the dominant reality. Mimic the strata. You don't reach the BwO, and its
|
||
plane of consistency, by wildly destratifying. That is why we encountered
|
||
the paradox of those emptied and dreary bodies at the very beginning: they
|
||
HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS? D 161
|
||
|
||
had emptied themselves of their organs instead of looking for the point at
|
||
which they could patiently and momentarily dismantle the organization of
|
||
the organs we call the organism. There are, in fact, several ways of botching
|
||
the BwO: either one fails to produce it, or one produces it more or less, but
|
||
nothing is produced on it, intensities do not pass or are blocked. This is
|
||
because the BwO is always swinging between the surfaces that stratify it
|
||
and the plane that sets it free. If you free it with too violent an action, if you
|
||
blow apart the strata without taking precautions, then instead of drawing
|
||
the plane you will be killed, plunged into a black hole, or even dragged
|
||
toward catastrophe. Staying stratified—organized, signified, subjected—
|
||
is not the worst that can happen; the worst that can happen is if you throw
|
||
the strata into demented or suicidal collapse, which brings them back down
|
||
on us heavier than ever. This is how it should be done: Lodge yourself on a
|
||
stratum, experiment with the opportunities it offers, find an advantageous
|
||
place on it, find potential movements of deterritorialization, possible lines
|
||
of flight, experience them, produce flow conjunctions here and there, try
|
||
out continuums of intensities segment by segment, have a small plot of new
|
||
land at all times. It is through a meticulous relation with the strata that one
|
||
succeeds in freeing lines of flight, causing conjugated flows to pass and
|
||
escape and bringing forth continuous intensities for a BwO. Connect, con-
|
||
jugate, continue: a whole "diagram," as opposed to still signifying and sub-
|
||
jective programs. We are in a social formation; first see how it is stratified
|
||
for us and in us and at the place where we are; then descend from the strata
|
||
to the deeper assemblage within which we are held; gently tip the assem-
|
||
blage, making it pass over to the side of the plane of consistency. It is only
|
||
there that the BwO reveals itself for what it is: connection of desires, con-
|
||
junction of flows, continuum of intensities. You have constructed your
|
||
own little machine, ready when needed to be plugged into other collective
|
||
machines. Castaneda describes a long process of experimentation (it
|
||
makes little difference whether it is with peyote or other things): let us
|
||
recall for the moment how the Indian forces him first to find a "place,"
|
||
already a difficult operation, then to find "allies," and then gradually to
|
||
give up interpretation, to construct flow by flow and segment by segment
|
||
lines of experimentation, becoming-animal, becoming-molecular, etc. For
|
||
the BwO is all of that: necessarily a Place, necessarily a Plane, necessarily a
|
||
Collectivity (assembling elements, things, plants, animals, tools, people,
|
||
powers, and fragments of all of these; for it is not "my" body without
|
||
organs, instead the "me" (moi) is on it, or what remains of me, unalterable
|
||
and changing in form, crossing thresholds).
|
||
In the course of Castaneda's books, the reader may begin to doubt the
|
||
existence of the Indian Don Juan, and many other things besides. But that
|
||
has no importance. So much the better if the books are a syncretism rather
|
||
162 D HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS?
|
||
|
||
than an ethnographical study, and the protocol of an experiment rather
|
||
than an account of an initiation. The fourth book, Tales of Power, is about
|
||
the living distinction between the "Tonal" and the "Nagual." The tonal
|
||
seems to cover many disparate things: It is the organism, and also all that is
|
||
organized and organizing; but it is also signifiance, and all that is signifying
|
||
or signified, all that is susceptible to interpretation, explanation, all that is
|
||
memorizable in the form of something recalling something else; finally, it
|
||
is the Self (Moi), the subject, the historical, social, or individual person,
|
||
and the corresponding feelings. In short, the tonal is everything, including
|
||
God, the judgment of God, since it "makes up the rules by which it appre-
|
||
hends the world. So, in a manner of speaking, it creates the world."19 Yet
|
||
the tonal is only an island. For the nagual is also everything. And it is the
|
||
same everything, but under such conditions that the body without organs
|
||
has replaced the organism and experimentation has replaced all interpreta-
|
||
tion, for which it no longer has any use. Flows of intensity, their fluids, their
|
||
fibers, their continuums and conjunctions of affects, the wind, fine
|
||
segmentation, microperceptions, have replaced the world of the subject.
|
||
Becomings, becomings-animal, becomings-molecular, have replaced his-
|
||
tory, individual or general. In fact, the tonal is not as disparate as it seems:
|
||
it includes all of the strata and everything that can be ascribed to the strata,
|
||
the organization of the organism, the interpretations and explanations of
|
||
the signifiable, the movements of subjectification. The nagual, on the con-
|
||
trary, dismantles the strata. It is no longer an organism that functions but a
|
||
BwO that is constructed. No longer are there acts to explain, dreams or
|
||
phantasies to interpret, childhood memories to recall, words to make sig-
|
||
nify; instead, there are colors and sounds, becomings and intensities (and
|
||
when you become-dog, don't ask if the dog you are playing with is a dream
|
||
or a reality, if it is "your goddam mother" or something else entirely). There
|
||
is no longer a Self [Moi] that feels, acts, and recalls; there is "a glowing fog, a
|
||
dark yellow mist" that has affects and experiences movements, speeds.20
|
||
The important thing is not to dismantle the tonal by destroying it all of a
|
||
sudden. You have to diminish it, shrink it, clean it, and that only at certain
|
||
moments. You have to keep it in order to survive, to ward off the assault of
|
||
the nagual. For a nagual that erupts, that destroys the tonal, a body without
|
||
organs that shatters all the strata, turns immediately into a body of noth-
|
||
ingness, pure self-destruction whose only outcome is death: "The tonal
|
||
must be protected at any cost."21
|
||
We still have not answered the question of why there are so many dan-
|
||
gers, and so many necessary precautions. It is not enough to set up an
|
||
abstract opposition between the strata and the BwO. For the BwO already
|
||
exists in the strata as well as on the destratified plane of consistency, but in
|
||
a totally different manner. Take the organism as a stratum: there is indeed a
|
||
HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS? D 163
|
||
|
||
BwO that opposes the organization of the organs we call the organism, but
|
||
there is also a BwO of the organism that belongs to that stratum. Cancerous
|
||
tissue: each instant, each second, a cell becomes cancerous, mad, prolife-
|
||
rates and loses its configuration, takes over everything; the organism must
|
||
resubmit it to its rule or restratify it, not only for its own survival, but also
|
||
to make possible an escape from the organism, the fabrication of the
|
||
"other" BwO on the plane of consistency. Take the stratum of signifiance:
|
||
once again, there is a cancerous tissue, this time of signifiance, a burgeon-
|
||
ing body of the despot that blocks any circulation of signs, as well as
|
||
preventing the birth of the asignifying sign on the "other" BwO. Or take
|
||
a stifling body of subjectification, which makes a freeing all the more
|
||
unlikely by forbidding any remaining distinction between subjects. Even if
|
||
we consider given social formations, or a given stratic apparatus within a
|
||
formation, we must say that every one of them has a BwO ready to gnaw,
|
||
proliferate, cover, and invade the entire social field, entering into relations
|
||
of violence and rivalry as well as alliance and complicity. A BwO of money
|
||
(inflation), but also a BwO of the State, army, factory, city, Party, etc. If the
|
||
strata are an affair of coagulation and sedimentation, all a stratum needs is
|
||
a high sedimentation rate for it to lose its configuration and articulations,
|
||
and to form its own specific kind of tumor, within itself or in a given forma-
|
||
tion or apparatus. The strata spawn their own BwO's, totalitarian and fas-
|
||
cist BwO's, terrifying caricatures of the plane of consistency. It is not
|
||
enough to make a distinction between full BwO's on the plane of consis-
|
||
tency and empty BwO's on the debris of strata destroyed by a too-violent
|
||
destratification. We must also take into account cancerous BwO's in a stra-
|
||
tum that has begun to proliferate. The three-body problem. Artaud said that
|
||
outside the "plane" is another plane surrounding us with "an unillu-
|
||
minated extension or a menace, as the case may be." It is a struggle and as
|
||
such is never sufficiently clear. How can we fabricate a BwO for ourselves
|
||
without its being the cancerous BwO of a fascist inside us, or the empty
|
||
BwO of a drug addict, paranoiac, or hypochondriac? How can we tell the
|
||
three Bodies apart? Artaud was constantly grappling with this problem.
|
||
The extraordinary composition of To Be Done with the Judgment of God:
|
||
he begins by cursing the cancerous body of America, the body of war and
|
||
money; he denounces the strata, which he calls "caca"; to the strata he
|
||
opposes the true Plane, even if it is only peyote, the little trickle of the
|
||
Tarahumaras; but he also knows about the dangers of a too-sudden, care-
|
||
less destratification. Artaud was constantly grappling with all of that, and
|
||
flowed with it. Letter to Hitler. "Dear Sir, In 1932 in the Ider Cafe in Berlin,
|
||
on one of the evenings when I made your acquaintance and shortly before
|
||
you took power, I showed you roadblocks on a map that was not just a map
|
||
of geography, roadblocks against me, an act of force aimed in a certain
|
||
164 D HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS?
|
||
|
||
number of directions you indicated to me. Today Hitler I lift the road-
|
||
blocks I set down! The Parisians need gas. Yours, A.A.—P.S. Be it under-
|
||
stood, dear sir, that this is hardly an invitation, it is above all a warning."22
|
||
That map that is not only a map of geography is something like a BwO
|
||
intensity map, where the roadblocks designate thresholds and the gas,
|
||
waves or flows. Even if Artaud did not succeed for himself, it is certain that
|
||
through him something has succeeded for us all.
|
||
The BwO is the egg. But the egg is not regressive; on the contrary, it is
|
||
perfectly contemporary, you always carry it with you as your own milieu of
|
||
experimentation, your associated milieu. The egg is the milieu of pure
|
||
intensity, spatium not extension, Zero intensity as principle of production.
|
||
There is a fundamental convergence between science and myth, embryol-
|
||
ogy and mythology, the biological egg and the psychic or cosmic egg: the egg
|
||
always designates this intensive reality, which is not undifferentiated, but
|
||
is where things and organs are distinguished solely by gradients, migra-
|
||
tions, zones of proximity. The egg is the BwO. The BwO is not "before" the
|
||
organism; it is adjacent to it and is continually in the process of construct-
|
||
ing itself. If it is tied to childhood, it is not in the sense that the adult
|
||
regresses to the child and the child to the Mother, but in the sense that the
|
||
child, like the Dogon twin who takes a piece of the placenta with him, tears
|
||
from the organic form of the Mother an intense and destratified matter
|
||
that on the contrary constitutes his or her perpetual break with the past, his
|
||
or her present experience, experimentation. The BwO is a childhood block,
|
||
a becoming, the opposite of a childhood memory. It is not the child
|
||
"before" the adult, or the mother "before" the child: it is the strict contem-
|
||
poraneousness of the adult, of the adult and the child, their map of compar-
|
||
ative densities and intensities, and all of the variations on that map. The
|
||
BwO is precisely this intense germen where there are not and cannot be
|
||
either parents or children (organic representation). This is what Freud
|
||
failed to understand about Weissmann: the child as the germinal contem-
|
||
porary of its parents. Thus the BwO is never yours or mine. It is always a
|
||
body. It is no more projective than it is regressive. It is an involution, but
|
||
always a contemporary, creative involution. The organs distribute them-
|
||
selves on the BwO, but they distribute themselves independently of the
|
||
form of the organism; forms become contingent, organs are no longer any-
|
||
thing more than intensities that are produced, flows, thresholds, and gradi-
|
||
ents. "A" stomach, "an" eye, "a" mouth: the indefinite article does not lack
|
||
anything; it is not indeterminate or undifferentiated, but expresses the
|
||
pure determination of intensity, intensive difference. The indefinite arti-
|
||
cle is the conductor of desire. It is not at all a question of a fragmented,
|
||
splintered body, of organs without the body (OwB). The BwO is exactly the
|
||
opposite. There are not organs in the sense of fragments in relation to a lost
|
||
HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS? D 165
|
||
|
||
unity, nor is there a return to the undifferentiated in relation to a differen-
|
||
tiable totality. There is a distribution of intensive principles of organs, with
|
||
their positive indefinite articles, within a collectivity or multiplicity, inside
|
||
an assemblage, and according to machinic connections operating on a
|
||
BwO. Logos spermaticos. The error of psychoanalysis was to understand
|
||
BwO phenomena as regressions, projections, phantasies, in terms of an
|
||
image of the body. As a result, it only grasps the flipside of the BwO and
|
||
immediately substitutes family photos, childhood memories, and part-
|
||
objects for a worldwide intensity map. It understands nothing about the
|
||
egg nor about indefinite articles nor about the contemporaneousness of a
|
||
continually self-constructing milieu.
|
||
The BwO is desire; it is that which one desires and by which one de-
|
||
sires. And not only because it is the plane of consistency or the field of
|
||
immanence of desire. Even when it falls into the void of too-sudden destra-
|
||
tification, or into the proliferation of a cancerous stratum, it is still desire.
|
||
Desire stretches that far: desiring one's own annihilation, or desiring the
|
||
power to annihilate. Money, army, police, and State desire, fascist desire,
|
||
even fascism is desire. There is desire whenever there is the constitution of
|
||
a BwO under one relation or another. It is a problem not of ideology but of
|
||
pure matter, a phenomenon of physical, biological, psychic, social, or cos-
|
||
mic matter. That is why the material problem confronting schizoanalysis is
|
||
knowing whether we have it within our means to make the selection, to dis-
|
||
tinguish the BwO from its doubles: empty vitreous bodies, cancerous bod-
|
||
ies, totalitarian and fascist. The test of desire: not denouncing false desires,
|
||
but distinguishing within desire between that which pertains to stratic pro-
|
||
liferation, or else too-violent destratification, and that which pertains to
|
||
the construction of the plane of consistency (keep an eye out for all that is
|
||
fascist, even inside us, and also for the suicidal and the demented). The
|
||
plane of consistency is not simply that which is constituted by the sum of all
|
||
BwO's. There are things it rejects; the BwO chooses, as a function of the
|
||
abstract machine that draws it. Even within a BwO (the masochist body,
|
||
the drugged body, etc.), we must distinguish what can be composed on the
|
||
plane and what cannot. There is a fascist use of drugs, or a suicidal use, but
|
||
is there also a possible use that would be in conformity with the plane of
|
||
consistency? Even paranoia: Is there a possibility of using it that way in
|
||
part? When we asked the question of the totality of all BwO's, considered as
|
||
substantial attributes of a single substance, it should have been under-
|
||
stood, strictly speaking, to apply only to the plane. The plane is the totality
|
||
of the full BwO's that have been selected (there is no positive totality
|
||
including the cancerous or empty bodies). What is the nature of this total-
|
||
ity? Is it solely logical? Or must we say that each BwO, from a basis in its
|
||
own genus, produces effects identical or analogous to the effects other
|
||
166 D HOW DO YOU MAKE YOURSELF A BODY WITHOUT ORGANS?
|
||
|
||
BwO's produce from a basis in their genera? Could what the drug user or
|
||
masochist obtains also be obtained in a different fashion in the conditions
|
||
of the plane, so it would even be possible to use drugs without using drugs,
|
||
to get soused on pure water, as in Henry Miller's experimentations? Or is it
|
||
a question of a real passage of substances, an intensive continuum of all the
|
||
BwO's? Doubtless, anything is possible. All we are saying is that the iden-
|
||
tity of effects, the continuity of genera, the totality of all BwO's, can be
|
||
obtained on the plane of consistency only by means of an abstract machine
|
||
capable of covering and even creating it, by assemblages capable of plug-
|
||
ging into desire, of effectively taking charge of desires, of assuring their
|
||
continuous connections and transversal tie-ins. Otherwise, the BwO's of
|
||
the plane will remain separated by genus, marginalized, reduced to means
|
||
of bordering, while on the "other plane" the emptied or cancerous doubles
|
||
will triumph.
|
||
7. Year Zero: Faciality
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Earlier, we encountered two axes, signifiance and subjectification. We saw
|
||
that they were two very different semiotic systems, or even two strata.
|
||
Signifiance is never without a white wall upon which it inscribes its signs
|
||
and redundancies. Subjectification is never without a black hole in which
|
||
it lodges its consciousness, passion, and redundancies. Since all semiotics
|
||
are mixed and strata come at least in twos, it should come as no surprise
|
||
that a very special mechanism is situated at their intersection. Oddly
|
||
enough, it is a face: the white wall/black hole system. A broad face with
|
||
white cheeks, a chalk face with eyes cut in for a black hole. Clown head,
|
||
white clown, moon-white mime, angel of death, Holy Shroud. The face is
|
||
not an envelope exterior to the person who speaks, thinks, or feels. The
|
||
form of the signifier in language, even its units, would remain indetermi-
|
||
nate if the potential listener did not use the face of the speaker to guide his
|
||
or her choices ("Hey, he seems angry . . ."; "He couldn't say it..."; "You
|
||
see my face when I'm talking to you ..."; "look at me carefully..."). A
|
||
167
|
||
168 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
child, woman, mother, man, father, boss, teacher, police officer, does not
|
||
speak a general language but one whose signifying traits are indexed to spe-
|
||
cific faciality traits. Faces are not basically individual; they define zones of
|
||
frequency or probability, delimit a field that neutralizes in advance any
|
||
expressions or connections unamenable to the appropriate significations.
|
||
Similarly, the form of subjectivity, whether consciousness or passion,
|
||
would remain absolutely empty if faces did not form loci of resonance that
|
||
select the sensed or mental reality and make it conform in advance to a
|
||
dominant reality. The face itself is redundancy. It is itself in redundancy
|
||
with the redundancies of signifiance or frequency, and those of resonance
|
||
or subjectivity. The face constructs the wall that the signifier needs in order
|
||
to bounce off of; it constitutes the wall of the signifier, the frame or screen.
|
||
The face digs the hole that subjectification needs in order to break through;
|
||
it constitutes the black hole of subjectivity as consciousness or passion, the
|
||
camera, the third eye.
|
||
Or should we say things differently? It is not exactly the face that consti-
|
||
tutes the wall of the signifier or the hole of subjectivity. The face, at least the
|
||
concrete face, vaguely begins to take shape on the white wall. It vaguely
|
||
begins to appear in the black hole. In film, the close-up of the face can be
|
||
said to have two poles: make the face reflect light or, on the contrary,
|
||
emphasize its shadows to the point of engulfing it "in pitiless darkness."1 A
|
||
psychologist once said that the face is a visual percept that crystallizes out
|
||
of "different varieties of vague luminosity without form or dimension." A
|
||
suggestive whiteness, a hole that captures, a face. According to this
|
||
account, the dimensionless black hole and formless white wall are already
|
||
there to begin with. And there are already a number of possible combina-
|
||
tions in the system: either black holes distribute themselves on the white
|
||
wall, or the white wall unravels and moves toward a black hole combining
|
||
all black holes, hurtling them together or making them "crest." Sometimes
|
||
faces appear on the wall, with their holes; sometimes they appear in the
|
||
hole, with their linearized, rolled-up wall. A horror story, the face is a hor-
|
||
ror story. It is certain that the signifier does not construct the wall that it
|
||
needs all by itself; it is certain that subjectivity does not dig its hole all
|
||
alone. Concrete faces cannot be assumed to come ready-made. They are
|
||
engendered by an abstract machine of faciality (visageite), which produces
|
||
them at the same time as it gives the signifier its white wall and subjectivity
|
||
its black hole. Thus the black hole/white wall system is, to begin with, not a
|
||
face but the abstract machine that produces faces according to the change-
|
||
able combinations of its cogwheels. Do not expect the abstract machine to
|
||
resemble what it produces, or will produce.
|
||
The abstract machine crops up when you least expect it, at a chance
|
||
juncture when you are just falling asleep, or into a twilight state or halluci-
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 169
|
||
|
||
nating, or doing an amusing physics experiment . . . Kafka's novella,
|
||
"Blumfeld":2 the bachelor returns home in the evening to find two little
|
||
ping-pong balls jumping around by themselves on the "wall" constituted
|
||
by the floor. They bounce everywhere and even try to hit him in the face.
|
||
They apparently contain other, still smaller, electric balls. Blumfeld finally
|
||
manages to lock them up in the black hole of a wardrobe. The scene contin-
|
||
ues the next day when Blumfeld tries to give the balls to a small, feeble-
|
||
minded boy and two grimacing little girls, and then at the office, where he
|
||
encounters his two grimacing and feebleminded assistants, who want to
|
||
make off with a broom. In a wonderful ballet by Debussy and Nijinsky, a
|
||
little tennis ball comes bouncing onto the stage at dusk, and at the end
|
||
another ball appears in a similar fashion. This time, between the two balls,
|
||
two girls and a boy who watches them develop passional dance and facial
|
||
traits in vague luminosities (curiosity, spite, irony, ecstasy. . .).3 There is
|
||
nothing to explain, nothing to interpret. It is the pure abstract machine of a
|
||
twilight state. White wall/black hole? But depending on the combinations,
|
||
the wall could just as well be black, and the hole white. The balls can bounce
|
||
off of a wall or spin into a black hole. Even upon impact they can have the
|
||
relative role of a hole in relation to the wall, just as when they are rolling
|
||
straight ahead they can have the relative role of a wall in relation to the hole
|
||
they are heading for. They circulate in the white wall/black hole system.
|
||
Nothing in all of this resembles a face, yet throughout the system faces are
|
||
distributed and faciality traits organized. Nevertheless, the abstract
|
||
machine can be effectuated in other things besides faces, but not in any
|
||
order, and not without the necessary foundation (raisons).
|
||
The face has been a major concern of American psychology, in particu-
|
||
lar the relation between the mother and the child through eye-to-eye con-
|
||
tact. Four-eye machine? Let us recall certain stages in the research: (1)
|
||
Isakower's studies on falling asleep, in which so-called proprioceptive sen-
|
||
sations of a manual, buccal, cutaneous, or even vaguely visual nature recall
|
||
the infantile mouth-breast relation. (2) Lewin's discovery of a white screen
|
||
of the dream, which is ordinarily covered by visual contents but remains
|
||
white when the only dream contents are proprioceptive sensations (this
|
||
screen or white wall, once again, is the breast as it approaches, getting
|
||
larger and then pressing flat). (3) Spitz's interpretation according to which
|
||
the white screen, rather than being a representation of the breast itself as an
|
||
object of tactile sensation or contact, is a visual percept implying a mini-
|
||
mum of distance and upon which the mother's face appears for the child to
|
||
use as a guide in finding the breast. Thus there is a combination of two very
|
||
different kinds of elements: manual, buccal, or cutaneous proprioceptive
|
||
sensations; and the visual perception of the face seen from the front against
|
||
the white screen, with the shape of the eyes drawn in for black holes. This
|
||
170 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
visual perception very quickly assumes decisive importance for the act of
|
||
eating, in relation to the breast as a volume and the mouth as a cavity, both
|
||
experienced through touch.4
|
||
We can now propose the following distinction: the face is part of a
|
||
surface-holes, holey surface, system. This system should under no cir-
|
||
cumstances be confused with the volume-cavity system proper to the
|
||
(proprioceptive) body. The head is included in the body, but the face is not.
|
||
The face is a surface: facial traits, lines, wrinkles; long face, square face, tri-
|
||
angular face; the face is a map, even when it is applied to and wraps a vol-
|
||
ume, even when it surrounds and borders cavities that are now no more
|
||
than holes. The head, even the human head, is not necessarily a face. The
|
||
face is produced only when the head ceases to be a part of the body, when it
|
||
ceases to be coded by the body, when it ceases to have a multidimensional,
|
||
polyvocal corporeal code—when the body, head included, has been
|
||
decoded and has to be overcodedby something we shall call the Face. This
|
||
amounts to saying that the head, all the volume-cavity elements of the
|
||
head, have to be facialized. What accomplishes this is the screen with holes,
|
||
the white wall/black hole, the abstract machine producing faciality. But the
|
||
operation does not end there: if the head and its elements are facialized, the
|
||
entire body also can be facialized, comes to be facialized as part of an inevi-
|
||
table process. When the mouth and nose, but first the eyes, become a holey
|
||
surface, all the other volumes and cavities of the body follow. An operation
|
||
worthy of Doctor Moreau: horrible and magnificent. Hand, breast, stom-
|
||
ach, penis and vagina, thigh, leg and foot, all come to be facialized. Fetish-
|
||
ism, erotomania, etc., are inseparable from these processes of facializa-
|
||
tion. It is not at all a question of taking a part of the body and making it
|
||
resemble a face, or making a dream-face dance in a cloud. No anthropo-
|
||
morphism here. Facialization operates not by resemblance but by an order
|
||
of reasons. It is a much more unconscious and machinic operation that
|
||
draws the entire body across the holey surface, and in which the role of the
|
||
face is not as a model or image, but as an overcoding of all of the decoded
|
||
parts. Everything remains sexual; there is no sublimation, but there are
|
||
new coordinates. It is precisely because the face depends on an abstract
|
||
machine that it is not content to cover the head, but touches all other parts of
|
||
the body, and even, if necessary, other objects without resemblance. The
|
||
question then becomes what circumstances trigger the machine that pro-
|
||
duces the face and facialization. Although the head, even the human head,
|
||
is not necessarily a face, the face is produced in humanity. But it is pro-
|
||
duced by a necessity that does not apply to human beings "in general." The
|
||
face is not animal, but neither is it human in general; there is even some-
|
||
thing absolutely inhuman about the face. It would be an error to proceed as
|
||
though the face became inhuman only beyond a certain threshold: close-
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 171
|
||
|
||
up, extreme magnification, recondite expression, etc. The inhuman in
|
||
human beings: that is what the face is from the start. It is by nature a close-
|
||
up, with its inanimate white surfaces, its shining black holes, its emptiness
|
||
and boredom. Bunker-face. To the point that if human beings have a des-
|
||
tiny, it is rather to escape the face, to dismantle the face and facializations,
|
||
to become imperceptible, to become clandestine, not by returning to
|
||
animality, nor even by returning to the head, but by quite spiritual and spe-
|
||
cial becomings-animal, by strange true becomings that get past the wall and
|
||
get out of the black holes, that makefaciality traits themselves finally elude
|
||
the organization of the face—freckles dashing toward the horizon, hair car-
|
||
ried off by the wind, eyes you traverse instead of seeing yourself in or gazing
|
||
into in those glum face-to-face encounters between signifying subjectivi-
|
||
ties. "I no longer look into the eyes of the woman I hold in my arms but I
|
||
swim through, head and arms and legs, and I see that behind the sockets of
|
||
the eyes there is a region unexplored, the world of futurity, and here there is
|
||
no logic whatsoever. . . . I have broken the wall. . .. My eyes are useless, for
|
||
they render back only the image of the known. My whole body must be-
|
||
come a constant beam of light, moving with an ever greater rapidity, never
|
||
arrested, never looking back, never dwindling.... Therefore I close my
|
||
ears, my eyes, my mouth.'''5 BwO. Yes, the face has a great future, but only if
|
||
it is destroyed, dismantled. On the road to the asignifying and asubjective.
|
||
But so far we have explained nothing of what we sense.
|
||
The move from the body-head system to the face system has nothing to
|
||
do with an evolution or genetic stages. Nor with phenomenological posi-
|
||
tions. Nor with integrations of part-objects, or structural or structuring sys-
|
||
tems. Nor can there be any appeal to a preexisting subject, or one brought
|
||
into existence, except by this machine specific to faciality. In the literature
|
||
of the face, Sartre's text on the look and Lacan's on the mirror make the
|
||
error of appealing to a form of subjectivity or humanity reflected in a
|
||
phenomenological field or split in a structural field. The gaze is but secon-
|
||
dary in relation to thegazeless eyes, to the black hole of faciality. The mirror
|
||
is but secondary in relation to the white wall of faciality. Neither will we
|
||
speak of a genetic axis, or the integration of part-objects. Any approach
|
||
based on stages in ontogenesis is arbitrary: it is thought that what is fastest
|
||
is primary, or even serves as a foundation or springboard for what comes
|
||
next. An approach based on part-objects is even worse; it is the approach of
|
||
a demented experimenter who flays, slices, and anatomizes everything in
|
||
sight, and then proceeds to sew things randomly back together again. You
|
||
can make any list of part-objects you want: hand, breast, mouth, e y e s . . .
|
||
It's still Frankenstein. What we need to consider is not fundamentally
|
||
organs without bodies, or the fragmented body; it is the body without
|
||
organs, animated by various intensive movements that determine the
|
||
172 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
nature and emplacement of the organs in question and make that body an
|
||
organism, or even a system of strata of which the organism is only a part. It
|
||
becomes apparent that the slowest of movements, or the last to occur or
|
||
arrive, is not the least intense. And the fastest may already have converged
|
||
with it, connected with it, in the disequilibrium of a nonsynchronic devel-
|
||
opment of strata that have different speeds and lack a sequence of stages
|
||
but are nevertheless simultaneous. The question of the body is not one of
|
||
part-objects but of differential speeds.
|
||
These movements are movements of deterritorialization. They are what
|
||
"make" the body an animal or human organism. For example, the prehen-
|
||
sile hand implies a relative deterritorialization not only of the front paw but
|
||
also of the locomotor hand. It has a correlate, the use-object or tool: the
|
||
club is a deterritorialized branch. The breast of the woman, with her up-
|
||
right posture, indicates a deterritorialization of the animal's mammary
|
||
gland; the mouth of the child, adorned with lips by an outfolding of the
|
||
mucous membranes, marks a deterritorialization of the snout and mouth
|
||
of the animal. Lips-breast: each serves as a correlate of the other.6 The
|
||
human head implies a deterritorialization in relation to the animal and has
|
||
as its correlate the organization of a world, in other words, a milieu that has
|
||
itself been deterritorialized (the steppe is the first "world," in contrast to
|
||
the forest milieu). But the face represents a far more intense, if slower,
|
||
deterritorialization. We could say that it is an absolute deterritorialization:
|
||
it is no longer relative because it removes the head from the stratum of the
|
||
organism, human or animal, and connects it to other strata, such as signi-
|
||
fiance and subjectification. Now the face has a correlate of great impor-
|
||
tance: the landscape, which is not just a milieu but a deterritorialized
|
||
world. There are a number of face-landscape correlations, on this "higher"
|
||
level. Christian education exerts spiritual control over both faciality and
|
||
landscapity (paysageite): Compose them both, color them in, complete
|
||
them, arrange them according to a complementarity linking landscapes to
|
||
faces.7 Face and landscape manuals formed a pedagogy, a strict discipline,
|
||
and were an inspiration to the arts as much as the arts were an inspiration
|
||
to them. Architecture positions its ensembles—houses, towns or cities,
|
||
monuments or factories—to function like faces in the landscape they
|
||
transform. Painting takes up the same movement but also reverses it, posi-
|
||
tioning a landscape as a face, treating one like the other: "treatise on the
|
||
face and the landscape." The close-up in film treats the face primarily as a
|
||
landscape; that is the definition of film, black hole and white wall, screen
|
||
and camera. But the same goes for the earlier arts, architecture, painting,
|
||
even the novel: close-ups animate and invent all of their correlations. So, is
|
||
your mother a landscape or a face? A face or a factory? (Godard.) All faces
|
||
envelop an unknown, unexplored landscape; all landscapes are populated
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 173
|
||
|
||
by a loved or dreamed-of face, develop a face to come or already past. What
|
||
face has not called upon the landscapes it amalgamated, sea and hill; what
|
||
landscape has not evoked the face that would have completed it, providing
|
||
an unexpected complement for its lines and traits? Even when painting
|
||
becomes abstract, all it does is rediscover the black hole and white wall, the
|
||
great composition of the white canvas and black slash. Tearing, but also
|
||
stretching of the canvas along an axis of escape (fuite), at a vanishing point
|
||
(point defuite), along a diagonal, by a knife slice, slash, or hole: the machine
|
||
is already in place that always functions to produce faces and landscapes,
|
||
however abstract. Titian began his paintings in black and white, not to
|
||
make outlines to fill in, but as the matrix for each of the colors to come.
|
||
The novel—A flock of geese flew which the snow had dazzled. [Perceval]
|
||
saw them and heard them, for they were going away noisily because of a fal-
|
||
con which came drawing after them at a great rate until hefound abandoned
|
||
one separated from the flock, and he struck it so and bruised it that he
|
||
knocked it down to earth.... When Perceval saw the trampled snow on which
|
||
the goose had lain, and the blood which appeared around, he leaned upon his
|
||
lance and looked at that image, for the blood and the snow together seemed
|
||
to him like the fresh color which was on the face of his friend, and he thinks
|
||
until heforgets himself; for the vermilion seated on white was on herface just
|
||
the same as these three drops of blood on the white snow.... We have seen a
|
||
knight who is dozing on his charger. Everything is there: the redundancy
|
||
specific to the face and landscape, the snowy white wall of the landscape-
|
||
face, the black hole of the falcon and the three drops distributed on the wall;
|
||
and, simultaneously, the silvery line of the landscape-face spinning toward
|
||
the black hole of the knight deep in catatonia. Cannot the knight, at certain
|
||
times and under certain conditions, push the movement further still, cross-
|
||
ing the black hole, breaking through the white wall, dismantling the face—
|
||
even if the attempt may backfire?8 All of this is in no way characteristic of
|
||
the genre of the novel only at the end of its history; it is there from the
|
||
beginning, it is an essential part of the genre. It is false to see Don Quixote
|
||
as the end of the chivalric novel, invoking the hero's hallucinations, hare-
|
||
brained ideas, and hypnotic or cataleptic states. It is false to see novels such
|
||
as Beckett's as the end of the novel in general, invoking the black holes, the
|
||
characters' line of deterritorialization, the schizophrenic promenades of
|
||
Molloy or the Unnameable, their loss of their names, memory, or purpose.
|
||
The novel does have an evolution, but that is surely not it. The novel has
|
||
always been defined by the adventure of lost characters who no longer
|
||
know their name, what they are looking for, or what they are doing, amnesi-
|
||
acs, ataxies, catatonics. They differentiate the genre of the novel from the
|
||
genres of epic or drama (when the dramatic or epic hero is stricken with
|
||
folly or forgetting, etc., it is in an entirely different way). La princesse de
|
||
174 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
Cleves is a novel precisely by virtue of what seemed paradoxical to the peo-
|
||
ple of the time: the states of absence or "rest," the sleep that overtakes the
|
||
characters. There is always a Christian education in the novel. Molloy is the
|
||
beginning of the genre of the novel. When the novel began, with Chretien
|
||
de Troyes, for example, the essential character that would accompany it
|
||
over the entire course of its history was already there: The knight of the
|
||
novel of courtly love spends his time forgetting his name, what he is doing,
|
||
what people say to him, he doesn't know where he is going or to whom he is
|
||
speaking, he is continually drawing a line of absolute deterritorialization,
|
||
but also losing his way, stopping, and falling into black holes. "He awaits
|
||
chivalry and adventure." Open Chretien de Troyes to any page and you will
|
||
find a catatonic knight seated on his steed, leaning on his lance, waiting,
|
||
seeing the face of his loved one in the landscape; you have to hit him to
|
||
make him respond. Lancelot, in the presence of the queen's white face,
|
||
doesn't notice his horse plunge into the river; or he gets into a passing cart
|
||
and it turns out to be the cart of disgrace. There is a face-landscape aggre-
|
||
gate proper to the novel, in which black holes sometimes distribute them-
|
||
selves on a white wall, and the white line of the horizon sometimes spins
|
||
toward a black hole, or both simultaneously.
|
||
|
||
Theorems of Deterritorialization, or
|
||
Machinic Propositions9
|
||
First theorem: One never deterritorializes alone; there are always at least
|
||
two terms, hand-use object, mouth-breast, face-landscape. And each of the
|
||
two terms reterritorializes on the other. Reterritorialization must not be
|
||
confused with a return to a primitive or older territoriality: it necessarily
|
||
implies a set of artifices by which one element, itself deterritorialized,
|
||
serves as a new territoriality for another, which has lost its territoriality as
|
||
well. Thus there is an entire system of horizontal and complementary reter-
|
||
ritorializations, between hand and tool, mouth and breast, face and land-
|
||
scape. Second theorem: The fastest of two elements or movements of
|
||
deterritorialization is not necessarily the most intense or most deterri-
|
||
torialized. Intensity of deterritorialization must not be confused with
|
||
speed of movement or development. The fastest can even connect its inten-
|
||
sity to the slowest, which, as an intensity, does not come after the fastest but
|
||
is simultaneously at work on a different stratum or plane (for example, the
|
||
way the breast-mouth relation is guided from the start by a plane of
|
||
faciality). Third theorem: It can even be concluded from this that the least
|
||
deterritorialized reterritorializes on the most deterritorialized. This is
|
||
where the second system of reterritorializations conies in, the vertical
|
||
system running from bottom to top. This is the sense in which not only
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 175
|
||
|
||
the mouth but also the breast, hand, the entire body, even the tool, are
|
||
"facialized." As a general rule, relative deterritorializations (transcoding)
|
||
reterritorialize on a deterritorialization that is in certain respects absolute
|
||
(overcoding). We have seen that the deterritorialization of the head into a
|
||
face is absolute but remains negative in that it passes from one stratum to
|
||
another, from the stratum of the organism to those of signifiance and
|
||
subjectification. The hand and breast reterritorialize on the face and in the
|
||
landscape: they are facialized at the same time as they are landscapified.
|
||
Even a use-object may come to be facialized: you might say that a house,
|
||
utensil, or object, an article of clothing, etc., is watching me, not because it
|
||
resembles a face, but because it is taken up in the white wall/black hole
|
||
process, because it connects to the abstract machine of facialization. The
|
||
close-up in film pertains as much to a knife, cup, clock, or kettle as to a face
|
||
or facial element, for example, Griffith's "the kettle is watching me." Is it
|
||
not fair to say, then, that there are close-ups in novels, as when Dickens
|
||
writes the opening line of The Cricket on the Hearth: "The kettle began
|
||
it. . .",10 and in painting, when a utensil becomes a face-landscape from
|
||
within, or when a cup on a tablecloth or a teapot is facialized, in Bonnard,
|
||
Vuillard? Fourth theorem: The abstract machine is therefore effectuated
|
||
not only in the faces that produce it but also to varying degrees in body
|
||
parts, clothes, and objects that it facializes following an order of reasons
|
||
(rather than an organization of resemblances).
|
||
Yet the question remains: When does the abstract machine of faciality
|
||
enter into play? When is it triggered? Take some simple examples: the
|
||
maternal power operating through the face during nursing; the passional
|
||
power operating through the face of the loved one, even in caresses; the
|
||
political power operating through the face of the leader (streamers, icons,
|
||
and photographs), even in mass actions; the power of film operating
|
||
through the face of the star and the close-up; the power of television. It is
|
||
not the individuality of the face that counts but the efficacy of the cipher-
|
||
ing it makes possible, and in what cases it makes it possible. This is an affair
|
||
not of ideology but of economy and the organization of power (pouvoir).
|
||
We are certainly not saying that the face, the power of the face (la puissance
|
||
du visage), engenders and explains social power (pouvoir). Certain assem-
|
||
blages of power (pouvoir) require the production of a face, others do not. If
|
||
we consider primitive societies, we see that there is very little that operates
|
||
through the face: their semiotic is nonsignifying, nonsubjective, essentially
|
||
collective, polyvocal, and corporeal, playing on very diverse forms and
|
||
substances. This polyvocality operates through bodies, their volumes,
|
||
their internal cavities, their variable exterior connections and coordinates
|
||
(territorialities). A fragment from a manual semiotic, a manual sequence,
|
||
may be coordinated, without subordination or unification, with an oral
|
||
176 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
sequence, or a cutaneous one, or a rhythmic one, etc. Lizot, for example,
|
||
shows how "the dissociation of duty, ritual and daily life is almost total...
|
||
it is strange, inconceivable to us": during mourning behavior, certain
|
||
people make obscene jokes while others cry; or an Indian abruptly stops
|
||
crying and begins to repair his flute; or everybody goes to sleep.'' The same
|
||
goes for incest. There is no incest prohibition; instead, there are sequences
|
||
of incest that connect with sequences of prohibition following specific
|
||
coordinates. Paintings, tattoos, or marks on the skin embrace the multidi-
|
||
mensionality of bodies. Even masks ensure the head's belonging to the
|
||
body, rather than making it a face. Doubtless, there are profound move-
|
||
ments of deterritorialization that shake up the coordinates of the body and
|
||
outline particular assemblages of power; however, they connect the body
|
||
not to faciality but to becomings-animal, in particular with the help of
|
||
drugs. Of course, there is no less spirituality for that, for these becomings-
|
||
animal involve an animal Spirit—a jaguar-spirit, bird-spirit, ocelot-spirit,
|
||
toucan-spirit—that takes possession of the body's interior, enters its
|
||
cavities, and fills its volumes instead of making a face for it. Possession
|
||
expresses a direct relation between Voices and the body rather than a rela-
|
||
tion to the face. Shaman, warrior, and hunter organizations of power, frag-
|
||
ile and precarious, are all the more spiritual by virtue of the fact that they
|
||
operate through corporeality, animality, and vegetality. When we said ear-
|
||
lier that the human head still belongs to the stratum of the organism, we
|
||
obviously were not denying the existence of culture and society among
|
||
these peoples; we were merely saying that these cultures' and societies'
|
||
codes pertain to bodies, to the belonging of heads to bodies, to the ability of
|
||
the body-head system to become and receive souls, and to receive them as
|
||
friends while repulsing enemy souls. "Primitives" may have the most
|
||
human of heads, the most beautiful and most spiritual, but they have no
|
||
face and need none.
|
||
The reason is simple. The face is not a universal. It is not even that of the
|
||
white man; it is White Man himself, with his broad white cheeks and the
|
||
black hole of his eyes. The face is Christ. The face is the typical European,
|
||
what Ezra Pound called the average sensual man, in short, the ordinary
|
||
everyday Erotomaniac (nineteenth-century psychiatrists were right to say
|
||
that erotomania, unlike nymphomania, often remains pure and chaste;
|
||
this is because it operates through the face and facialization). Not a univer-
|
||
sal, but fades totius universi. Jesus Christ superstar: he invented the
|
||
facialization of the entire body and spread it everywhere (the Passion of
|
||
Joan of Arc, in close-up). Thus the face is by nature an entirely specific
|
||
idea, which did not preclude its acquiring and exercising the most general
|
||
of functions: the function of biuni vocalization, or binarization. It has two
|
||
aspects: the abstract machine of faciality, insofar as it is composed by a
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 177
|
||
|
||
black hole/white wall system, functions in two ways, one of which concerns
|
||
the units or elements, the other the choices. Under the first aspect, the
|
||
black hole acts as a central computer, Christ, the third eye that moves
|
||
across the wall or the white screen serving as general surface of reference.
|
||
Regardless of the content one gives it, the machine constitutes a facial unit,
|
||
an elementary face in biunivocal relation with another: it is a man or a
|
||
woman, a rich person or a poor one, an adult or a child, a leader or a subject,
|
||
"an x or a y." The movement of the black hole across the screen, the trajec-
|
||
tory of the third eye over the surface of reference, constitutes so many
|
||
dichotomies or arborescences, like four-eye machines made of elementary
|
||
faces linked together two by two. The face of a teacher and a student, father
|
||
and son, worker and boss, cop and citizen, accused and judge ("the judge
|
||
had a stern expression, his eyes were horizonless..."): concrete individu-
|
||
alized faces are produced and transformed on the basis of these units, these
|
||
combinations of units—like the face of a rich child in which a military call-
|
||
ing is already discernible, that West Point chin. You don't so much have a
|
||
face as slide into one.
|
||
Under the second aspect, the abstract machine of faciality assumes a
|
||
role of selective response, or choice: given a concrete face, the machine
|
||
judges whether it passes or not, whether it goes or not, on the basis of the
|
||
elementary facial units. This time, the binary relation is of the "yes-no"
|
||
type. The empty eye or black hole absorbs or rejects, like a half-doddering
|
||
despot who can still give a signal of acquiescence or refusal. The face of a
|
||
given teacher is contorted by tics and bathed in an anxiety that makes it "no
|
||
go." A defendant, a subject, displays an overaffected submission that turns
|
||
into insolence. Or someone is too polite to be honest. A given face is neither
|
||
a man's nor a woman's. Or it is neither a poor person's nor a rich person's.
|
||
Is it someone who lost his fortune? At every moment, the machine rejects
|
||
faces that do not conform, or seem suspicious. But only at a given level of
|
||
choice. For it is necessary to produce successive divergence-types of devi-
|
||
ance for everything that eludes biunivocal relationships, and to establish
|
||
binary relations between what is accepted on first choice and what is only
|
||
tolerated on second, third choice, etc. The white wall is always expanding,
|
||
and the black hole functions repeatedly. The teacher has gone mad, but
|
||
madness is a face conforming to the nth choice (not the last, however, since
|
||
there are mad faces that do not conform to what one assumes madness
|
||
should be). A ha! It's not a man and it's not a woman, so it must be a trans-
|
||
vestite: The binary relation is between the "no" of the first category and the
|
||
"yes" of the following category, which under certain conditions may just as
|
||
easily mark a tolerance as indicate an enemy to be mowed down at all costs.
|
||
At any rate, you've been recognized, the abstract machine has you
|
||
inscribed in its overall grid. It is clear that in its new role as deviance
|
||
178 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
detector, the faciality machine does not restrict itself to individual cases
|
||
but operates in just as general a fashion as it did in its first role, the compu-
|
||
tation of normalities. If the face is in fact Christ, in other words, your aver-
|
||
age ordinary White Man, then the first deviances, the first divergence-
|
||
types, are racial: yellow man, black man, men in the second or third
|
||
category. They are also inscribed on the wall, distributed by the hole. They
|
||
must be Christianized, in other words, facialized. European racism as the
|
||
white man's claim has never operated by exclusion, or by the designation
|
||
of someone as Other: it is instead in primitive societies that the stranger is
|
||
grasped as an "other."12 Racism operates by the determination of degrees
|
||
of deviance in relation to the White-Man face, which endeavors to inte-
|
||
grate nonconforming traits into increasingly eccentric and backward
|
||
waves, sometimes tolerating them at given places under given conditions,
|
||
in a given ghetto, sometimes erasing them from the wall, which never
|
||
abides alterity (it's a Jew, it's an Arab, it's a Negro, it's a lunatic . . .). From
|
||
the viewpoint of racism, there is no exterior, there are no people on the out-
|
||
side. There are only people who should be like us and whose crime it is not
|
||
to be. The dividing line is not between inside and outside but rather is
|
||
internal to simultaneous signifying chains and successive subjective
|
||
choices. Racism never detects the particles of the other; it propagates
|
||
waves of sameness until those who resist identification have been wiped
|
||
out (or those who only allow themselves to be identified at a given degree of
|
||
divergence). Its cruelty is equaled only by its incompetence and naivete.
|
||
On the brighter side, painting has exploited all the resources of the
|
||
Christ-face. Painting has taken the abstract white wall/black hole machine
|
||
of faciality in all directions, using the face of Christ to produce every kind
|
||
of facial unit and every degree of deviance. In this respect, there is an
|
||
exultation in the painting of the Middle Ages to the Renaissance, like an
|
||
unbridled freedom. Not only did Christ preside over the facialization of
|
||
the entire body (his own) and the landscapification of all milieus (his own),
|
||
but he composed all of the elementary faces and had every divergence at his
|
||
disposal: Christ-athlete at the fair, Christ-Mannerist queer, Christ-Negro,
|
||
or at least a Black Virgin at the edge of the wall. The most prodigious
|
||
strokes of madness appear on canvas under the auspices of the Catholic
|
||
code. A single example chosen from many [Giotto, The Life of St. Francis,
|
||
scene XII, The Transfiguration—Trans.]: against the white background of
|
||
the landscape and the black-blue hole of the sky, the crucified Christ-
|
||
turned-kite-machine sends stigmata to Saint Francis by rays; the stigmata
|
||
effect the facialization of the body of the saint, in the image of the body of
|
||
Christ; but the rays carrying the stigmata to the saint are also the strings
|
||
Francis uses to pull the divine kite. It was under the sign of the cross
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 179
|
||
|
||
that people learned to steer the face and processes of facialization in all
|
||
directions.
|
||
Information theory takes as its point of departure a homogeneous set of
|
||
ready-made signifying messages that are already functioning as elements
|
||
in biunivocal relationships, or the elements of which are biunivocally
|
||
organized between messages. Second, the picking of a combination
|
||
depends on a certain number of subjective binary choices that increase pro-
|
||
portionally to the number of elements. But the problem is that all of this
|
||
biunivocalization and binarization (which is not just the result of an
|
||
increase in calculating skills, as some say) assumes the deployment of a wall
|
||
or screen, the installation of a central computing hole without which no
|
||
message would be discernible and no choice could be implemented. The
|
||
black hole/white wall system must already have gridded all of space and
|
||
outlined its arborescences or dichotomies for those of signifier and
|
||
subjectification even to be conceivable. The mixed semiotic of signifiance
|
||
and subjectification has an exceptional need to be protected from any
|
||
intrusion from the outside. In fact, there must not be any exterior: no
|
||
nomad machine, no primitive poly vocality must spring up, with their com-
|
||
binations of heterogeneous substances of expression. Translatability of
|
||
any kind requires a single substance of expression. One can constitute sig-
|
||
nifying chains operating with deterritorialized, digitalized, discrete ele-
|
||
ments only if there is a semiological screen available, a wall to protect
|
||
them. One can make subjective choices between two chains or at each point
|
||
in a chain only if no outside tempest sweeps away the chains and subjects.
|
||
One can form a web of subjectivities only if one possesses a central eye, a
|
||
black hole capturing everything that would exceed or transform either the
|
||
assigned affects or the dominant significations. Moreover, it is absurd to
|
||
believe that language as such can convey a message. A language is always
|
||
embedded in the faces that announce its statements and ballast them in
|
||
relation to the signifiers in progress and subjects concerned. Choices are
|
||
guided by faces, elements are organized around faces: a common grammar
|
||
is never separable from a facial education. The face is a veritable mega-
|
||
phone. Thus not only must the abstract machine of faciality provide a pro-
|
||
tective screen and a computing black hole; in addition, the faces it
|
||
produces draw all kinds of arborescences and dichotomies without which
|
||
the signifying and the subjective would not be able to make the arbor-
|
||
escences and dichotomies function that fall within their purview in lan-
|
||
guage. Doubtless, the binarities and biunivocalities of the face are not the
|
||
same as those of language, of its elements and subjects. There is no resem-
|
||
blance between them. But the former subtend the latter. When the faciality
|
||
machine translates formed contents of whatever kind into a single sub-
|
||
stance of expression, it already subjugates them to the exclusive form of
|
||
180 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
signifying and subjective expression. It carries out the prior gridding that
|
||
makes it possible for the signifying elements to become discernible, and for
|
||
the subjective choices to be implemented. The faciality machine is not an
|
||
annex to the signifier and the subject; rather, it is subjacent (connexe) to
|
||
them and is their condition of possibility. Facial biunivocalities and bina-
|
||
rities double the others; facial redundancies are in redundancy with signi-
|
||
fying and subjective redundancies. It is precisely because the face depends
|
||
on an abstract machine that it does not assume a preexistent subject or
|
||
signifier; but it is subjacent to them and provides the substance necessary
|
||
to them. What chooses the faces is not a subject, as in the Szondi test; it is
|
||
faces that choose their subjects. What interprets the black blotch/white
|
||
hole figure, or the white page/black hole, is not a signifier, as in the Ror-
|
||
schach test; it is that figure which programs the signifiers.
|
||
We have made some progress toward answering the question of what
|
||
triggers the abstract machine of faciality, for it is not in operation all the
|
||
time or in just any social formation. Certain social formations need face,
|
||
and also landscape.13 There is a whole history behind it. At very different
|
||
dates, there occurred a generalized collapse of all of the heterogeneous,
|
||
polyvocal, primitive semiotics in favor of a semiotic of signifiance and
|
||
subjectification. Whatever the differences between signifiance and subjec-
|
||
tification, whichever prevails over the other in this case or that, whatever
|
||
the varying figures assumed by their de facto mixtures—they have it in
|
||
common to crush all polyvocality, set up language as a form of exclusive
|
||
expression, and operate by signifying biunivocalization and subjective
|
||
binarization. The superlinearity proper to language is no longer coordi-
|
||
nated with multidimensional figures: it now flattens out all volumes and
|
||
subordinates all lines. Is it by chance that linguistics always, and very
|
||
quickly, encounters the problem of homonymy, or ambiguous statements
|
||
that it then subjects to a set of binary reductions? More generally, linguis-
|
||
tics can tolerate no poly vocality or rhizome traits: a child who runs around,
|
||
plays, dances, and draws cannot concentrate attention on language and
|
||
writing, and will never be a good subject. In short, the new semiotic needs
|
||
systematically to destroy the whole range of primitive semiotic systems,
|
||
even if it retains some of their debris in well-defined enclosures.
|
||
However, there is more to the picture than semiotic systems waging war
|
||
on one another armed only with their own weapons. Very specific assem-
|
||
blages of power impose signifiance and subjectification as their determinate
|
||
form of expression, in reciprocal presupposition with new contents: there
|
||
is no signifiance without a despotic assemblage, no subjectification with-
|
||
out an authoritarian assemblage, and no mixture between the two without
|
||
assemblages of power that act through signifiers and act upon souls and
|
||
subjects. It is these assemblages, these despotic or authoritarian forma-
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 181
|
||
|
||
tions, that give the new semiotic system the means of its imperialism, in
|
||
other words, the means both to crush the other semiotics and protect itself
|
||
against any threat from outside. A concerted effort is made to do away with
|
||
the body and corporeal coordinates through which the multidimensional
|
||
or polyvocal semiotics operated. Bodies are disciplined, corporeality dis-
|
||
mantled, becomings-animal hounded out, deterritorialization pushed to a
|
||
new threshold—a jump is made from the organic strata to the strata of
|
||
signifiance and subjectification. A single substance of expression is pro-
|
||
duced. The white wall/black hole system is constructed, or rather the
|
||
abstract machine is triggered that must allow and ensure the almightiness
|
||
of the signifier as well as the autonomy of the subject. You will be pinned to
|
||
the white wall and stuffed in the black hole. This machine is called the
|
||
faciality machine because it is the social production efface, because it per-
|
||
forms the facialization of the entire body and all its surroundings and
|
||
objects, and the landscapification of all worlds and milieus. The deter-
|
||
ritorialization of the body implies a reterritorialization on the face; the
|
||
decoding of the body implies an overcoding by the face; the collapse of cor-
|
||
poreal coordinates or milieus implies the constitution of a landscape. The
|
||
semiotic of the signifier and the subjective never operates through bodies.
|
||
It is absurd to claim to relate the signifier to the body. At any rate it can be
|
||
related only to a body that has already been entirely facialized. The differ-
|
||
ence between our uniforms and clothes and primitive paintings and garb is
|
||
that the former effect a facialization of the body, with buttons for black
|
||
holes against the white wall of the material. Even the mask assumes a new
|
||
function here, the exact opposite of its old one. For there is no unitary func-
|
||
tion of the mask, except a negative one (in no case does the mask serve to
|
||
dissimulate, to hide, even while showing or revealing). Either the mask
|
||
assures the head's belonging to the body, its becoming-animal, as was the
|
||
case in primitive societies. Or, as is the case now, the mask assures the erec-
|
||
tion, the construction of the face, the facialization of the head and the
|
||
body: the mask is now the face itself, the abstraction or operation of the
|
||
face. The inhumanity of the face. Never does the face assume a prior
|
||
signifier or subject. The order is totally different: despotic and authoritar-
|
||
ian concrete assemblage of power —*. triggering of the abstract machine of
|
||
faciality, white wall/black hole —> installation of the new semiotic of
|
||
signifiance and subjectification on that holey surface. That is why we have
|
||
been addressing just two problems exclusively: the relation of the face to
|
||
the abstract machine that produces it, and the relation of the face to the
|
||
assemblages of power that require that social production. The face is a
|
||
politics.
|
||
Of course, we have already seen that signifiance and subjectification are
|
||
semiotic systems that are entirely distinct in their principles and have
|
||
182 O YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
different regimes (circular irradiation versus segmentary linearity) and
|
||
different apparatuses of power (despotic generalized slavery versus author-
|
||
itarian contract-proceeding). Neither begins with Christ, or the White
|
||
Man as Christian universal: there are Indian, African, and Asiatic despotic
|
||
formations of signifiance; the authoritarian process of subjectification
|
||
appears most purely in the destiny of the Jewish people. But however dif-
|
||
ferent these semiotics are, they still form a de facto mix, and it is at the level
|
||
of this mixture that they assert their imperialism, in other words, their
|
||
common endeavor to crush all other semiotics. There is no signifiance that
|
||
does not harbor the seeds of subjectivity; there is no subjectification that
|
||
does not drag with it remnants of signifier. If the signifier bounces above all
|
||
off a wall, if subjectivity spins above all toward a hole, then we must say that
|
||
the wall of the signifier already includes holes and the black hole of subjec-
|
||
tivity already carries scraps of wall. The mix, therefore, has a solid founda-
|
||
tion in the indissociable white wall/black hole machine, and the two
|
||
semiotics intermingle through intersection, splicing, and the plugging of
|
||
one into the other, as with the "Hebrew and the Pharaoh." But there is more
|
||
because the nature of the mixtures may vary greatly. If it is possible to
|
||
assign the faciality machine a date—the year zero of Christ and the histori-
|
||
cal development of the White Man—it is because that is when the mixture
|
||
ceased to be a splicing or an intertwining, becoming a total interpene-
|
||
tration in which each element suffuses the other like drops of red-black
|
||
wine in white water. Our semiotic of modern White Men, the semiotic of
|
||
capitalism, has attained this state of mixture in which signifiance and
|
||
subjectification effectively interpenetrate. Thus it is in this semiotic that
|
||
faciality, or the white wall/black hole system, assumes its full scope. We
|
||
must, however, assess the states of mixture and the varying proportions of
|
||
the elements. Whether in the Christian or pre-Christian state, one element
|
||
may dominate another, one may be more or less powerful than the other.
|
||
We are thus led to define limit-faces, which are different from both the
|
||
facial units and the degrees of facial divergence previously defined.
|
||
1. The black hole is on the white wall. It is not a unit, since the black hole
|
||
is in constant movement on the wall and operates by binarization. Two
|
||
black holes, four black holes, n black holes distribute themselves like eyes.
|
||
Faciality is always a multiplicity. The landscape will be populated with eyes
|
||
or black holes, as in an Ernst painting, or a drawing by Aloi'se or Wolfli. Cir-
|
||
cles are drawn around a hole on the white wall; an eye can be placed in each
|
||
of the circles. We can even propose the following law: the more circles there
|
||
are around a hole, the more the bordering effect acts to increase the surface
|
||
over which the hole slides and to give that surface a force of capture. Per-
|
||
haps the purest case is to be found in popular Ethiopian scrolls represent-
|
||
ing demons: on the white surface of the parchment, two black holes are
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 183
|
||
|
||
drawn, or an outline of round or rectangular faces; but the black holes
|
||
spread and reproduce, they enter into redundancy, and each time a secon-
|
||
dary circle is drawn, a new black hole is constituted, an eye is put in it.'4 An
|
||
effect of capturing a surface that becomes more enclosed the more it
|
||
expands. This is the signifying despotic face and the multiplication proper
|
||
to it, its proliferation, its redundancy of frequency. A multiplication of
|
||
eyes. The despot or his representatives are everywhere. This is the face as
|
||
seen from the front, by a subject who does not so much see as get snapped
|
||
up by black holes. This is a figure of destiny, terrestrial destiny, objective
|
||
signifying destiny. The close-up in film knows this figure well: the Griffith
|
||
close-up of a face, an element of a face or a facialized object, which then
|
||
assumes an anticipatory temporal value (the hands of the clock fore-
|
||
shadow something).
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Simple machine
|
||
With multiple Four-Eye Machine
|
||
bordering effects
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Proliferation of Eyes By Multiplication of Border
|
||
|
||
Terrestrial Signifying Despotic Face
|
||
|
||
2. Now, on the contrary, the white wall has unraveled, becoming a silver
|
||
thread moving toward the black hole. One black hole "crests" all the other
|
||
black holes, all of the eyes and faces, while the landscape becomes a thread
|
||
184 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
whose far end coils around the hole. It is still a multiplicity but constitutes a
|
||
different figure of destiny: reflexive, passional, subjective destiny. It is the
|
||
maritime face or landscape: it follows the line separating the sky from the
|
||
waters, or the land from the waters. This authoritarian face is in profile and
|
||
spins toward the black hole. Or else there are two faces facing each other,
|
||
but in profile to the observer, and their union is already marked by a limit-
|
||
less separation. Or else the faces turn away from each other, swept away by
|
||
betrayal. Tristan, Isolde, Isolde, Tristan, in the boat carrying them to the
|
||
black hole of betrayal and death. A faciality of consciousness and passion, a
|
||
redundancy of resonance and coupling. This time, the effect of the close-up
|
||
is no longer to expand a surface while simultaneously closing it off; its only
|
||
function is to have an anticipatory temporal value. It marks the origin of a
|
||
scale of intensity, or is part of that scale; the closer the faces get to the black
|
||
hole as termination point, the more the close-up heats the line they follow.
|
||
Eisenstein's close-ups versus Griffith's (the intensive heightening of
|
||
shame, or anger, in the close-ups in Potemkiri).1^ Here again, it is clear that
|
||
any combination is possible between the two limit-figures of the face. In
|
||
Pabst's Lulu, the despotic face of the fallen Lulu is associated with the
|
||
image of a bread knife, which has the anticipatory value of foreshadowing
|
||
the murder; but the authoritarian face of Jack the Ripper also ascends a
|
||
whole scale of intensities leading to the knife and Lulu's murder.
|
||
More generally, we may note characteristics common to the two limit-
|
||
figures. First, although the white wall, the broad cheeks, is the substantial
|
||
element of the signifier, and the black hole the reflexive element of subjec-
|
||
tivity, they always go together. But in one of two modes: either the black
|
||
holes distribute themselves and multiply on the white wall, or the wall,
|
||
reduced to its crest or horizon thread, hurtles toward a black hole that
|
||
crests them all. There is no wall without black holes, and no black hole
|
||
without a wall. Second, in both cases the black hole is necessarily sur-
|
||
rounded by a border, or even bordered more than once: the effect of this
|
||
border is either to expand the surface of the wall or to intensify the line. The
|
||
black hole is never in the eyes (pupil); it is always inside the border, and the
|
||
eyes are always inside the hole: dead eyes, which see all the better for being
|
||
in a black hole.16 These common characteristics do not preclude the exis-
|
||
tence of a limit-difference between the two figures of the face, and propor-
|
||
tions according to which first one then the other dominates in the mixed
|
||
semiotic. The terrestrial signifying despotic face, the maritime subjective
|
||
passional authoritarian face (the desert can also be a sea of land). Two fig-
|
||
ures of destiny, two states of the faciality machine. Jean Paris has clearly
|
||
shown how these poles operate in painting, the pole of the despotic Christ
|
||
and that of the passional Christ: on the one hand, the face of Christ seen
|
||
from the front, as in a Byzantine mosaic, with the black hole of the eyes
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 185
|
||
|
||
against a gold background, all depth projected forward; and on the other
|
||
hand, faces that cross glances and turned away from each other, seen half-
|
||
turned or in profile, as in a quattrocento painting, their sidelong glances
|
||
drawing multiple lines, integrating depth into the painting itself (arbitrary
|
||
examples of transition and mixture can be cited, such a Duccio's Calling
|
||
of Saint Peter and Saint Andrew, against the background of an aquatic land-
|
||
scape; the second formula has already overtaken Christ and the first fisher-
|
||
man, while the second fisherman remains within the Byzantine code).17
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Celebatory Machine
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Coupled Machine
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Complex Machine
|
||
1. Musicality Line
|
||
2. Picturality Line
|
||
3. Landscapity Line
|
||
4. Faciality Line
|
||
5. Consciousness Line
|
||
6. Passion Line
|
||
Etc.
|
||
|
||
|
||
Maritime Subjective Authoritarian Face (after Tristan and Isolde)
|
||
|
||
Swann's Love: Proust was able to make the face, landscape, painting,
|
||
music, etc., resonate together. Three moments in the story of Swann and
|
||
Odette. First, a whole signifying mechanism is set up. The face of Odette
|
||
with her broad white or yellow cheeks, and her eyes as black hoes. But this
|
||
face continually refers back to other things, also arrayed on the wall. That is
|
||
Swann's aetheticism, his amateurism: a thing must always recall some-
|
||
thing else, in a network of interpretations under the sign of the signifier.
|
||
A face refers back to a landscape. A face must "recall" a painting, or a
|
||
186 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
fragment of a painting. A piece of music must let fall a little phrase that
|
||
connects with Odette's face, to the point that the little phrase becomes only
|
||
a signal. The white wall becomes populous, the black holes are arrayed.
|
||
This entire mechanism of signifiance, with its referral of interpretations,
|
||
prepares the way for the second, passional subjective, moment, during
|
||
which Swann's jealousy, querulous delusion, and erotomania develop.
|
||
Now Odette's face races down a line hurtling toward a single black hole,
|
||
that of Swann's Passion. The other lines, of landscapity, picturality, and
|
||
musicality, also rush toward this catatonic hole and coil around it, border-
|
||
ing it several times.
|
||
But in the third moment, at the end of his long passion, Swann attends a
|
||
reception where he sees the faces of the servants and guests disaggregate
|
||
into autonomous aesthetic traits, as if the line of picturality regained its
|
||
independence, both beyond the wall and outside the black hole. Then
|
||
Vinteuil's little phrase regains its transcendence and renews its connection
|
||
with a still more intense, asignifying, and asubjective line of pure musi-
|
||
cality. And Swann knows that he no longer loves Odette and, above all, that
|
||
Odette will never again love him.
|
||
Was this salvation through art necessary? For neither Swann nor Proust
|
||
was saved. Was it necessary to break through the wall and out of the hole in
|
||
this way, by renouncing love? Was not that love rotten from the start, made
|
||
of signifiance and jealousy? Was it possible to do anything else, considering
|
||
Odette's mediocrity and Swann's aestheticism? In a way, the madeleine is
|
||
the same story. The narrator munches his madeleine: redundancy, the
|
||
black hole of involuntary memory. How can he get out of that? And it is,
|
||
above all, something one has to get out of, escape from. Proust knows that
|
||
quite well, even if his commentators do not. But the way he gets out is
|
||
through art, uniquely through art.
|
||
How do you get out of the black hole? How do you break through the
|
||
wall? How do you dismantle the face? Whatever genius there may be in the
|
||
French novel, that is not its affair. It is too concerned with measuring the
|
||
wall, or even with building it, with plumbing the depths of black holes and
|
||
composing faces. The French novel is profoundly pessimistic and idealis-
|
||
tic, "critical of life rather than creative of life." It stuffs its characters down
|
||
the hole and bounces them off the wall. It can only conceive of organized
|
||
voyages, and of salvation only through art, a still Catholic salvation, in
|
||
other words, salvation through eternity. It spends its time plotting points
|
||
instead of drawing lines, active lines of flight or of positive deterritori-
|
||
alization. The Anglo-American novel is totally different. "To get away. To
|
||
get away, out!... To cross a horizon .. ."18 From Hardy to Lawrence, from
|
||
Melville to Miller, the same cry rings out: Go across, get out, breakthrough,
|
||
make a beeline, don't get stuck on a point. Find the line of separation, fol-
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 187
|
||
|
||
low it or create it, to the point of treachery. That is why their relationship to
|
||
other civilizations, to the Orient or South America, and also to drugs and
|
||
voyages in place, is entirely different from that of the French. They know
|
||
how difficult it is to get out of the black hole of subjectivity, of conscious-
|
||
ness and memory, of the couple and conjugality. How tempting it is to let
|
||
yourself get caught, to lull yourself into it, to latch back onto aface. "[Being]
|
||
locked away in the black hole. . . gave her a molten copperish glow, the
|
||
words coming out of her mouth like lava, her flesh clutching ravenously for
|
||
a hold, a perch on something solid and substantial, something in which to
|
||
reintegrate and repose for a few moments. . . . At first I mistook it for pas-
|
||
sion, for ecstasy. . . . I thought I had found a living volcano, a female
|
||
Vesuvius. I never thought I had found a human ship going down in an
|
||
ocean of despair, in a Sargasso of impotence. Now I think of that black star
|
||
gleaming through the hole in the ceiling, that fixed star which hung above
|
||
our conjugal cell, more fixed, more remote than the Absolute, and I know it
|
||
was her, emptied of all that was properly herself: a dead black sun without
|
||
aspect."19 A copperish glow like the face at the bottom of a black hole. The
|
||
point is to get out of it, not in art, in other words, in spirit, but in life, in real
|
||
life. Don't take away my power to love. These English and American authors
|
||
also know how hard it is to break through the wall of the signifier. Many
|
||
people have tried since Christ, beginning with Christ. But Christ himself
|
||
botched the crossing, the jump, he bounced off the wall. "As if by a great
|
||
recoil, this negative backwash rolled up and stayed his death. The whole
|
||
negative impulse of humanity seemed to coil up into a monstrous inert
|
||
mass to create the human integer, the figure one, one and indivisible"—the
|
||
Face.20 Cross the wall, the Chinese perhaps, but at what price? At the price
|
||
of a becoming-animal, a becoming-flower or rock, and beyond that a strange
|
||
becoming-imperceptible, a becoming-hard now one with loving.21 It is a
|
||
question of speed, even if the movement is in place. Is this also to dismantle
|
||
the face, or as Miller says, no longer to look at or into the eyes but to swim
|
||
through them, to close your own eyes and make your body a beam of light
|
||
moving at ever-increasing speed? Of course, this requires all the resources
|
||
of art, and art of the highest kind. It requires a whole line of writing,
|
||
picturality, musicality... For it is through writing that you become animal,
|
||
it is through color that you become imperceptible, it is through music that
|
||
you become hard and memoryless, simultaneously animal and impercepti-
|
||
ble: in love. But art is never an end in itself; it is only a tool for blazing life
|
||
lines, in other words, all of those real becomings that are not produced only
|
||
in art, and all of those active escapes that do not consist in fleeing into art,
|
||
taking refuge in art, and all of those positive deterritorializations that
|
||
never reterritorialize on art, but instead sweep it away with them toward
|
||
the realms of the asignifying, asubjective, and faceless.
|
||
188 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
Dismantling the face is no mean affair. Madness is a definite danger: Is it
|
||
by chance that schizos lose their sense of the face, their own and others',
|
||
their sense of the landscape, and the sense of language and its dominant sig-
|
||
nifications all at the same time? The organization of the face is a strong
|
||
one. We could say that the face holds within its rectangle or circle a whole
|
||
set of traits, faciality traits, which it subsumes and places at the service of
|
||
signifiance and subjectification. What is a tic? It is precisely the continu-
|
||
ally refought battle between a faciality trait that tries to escape the sover-
|
||
eign organization of the face and the face itself, which clamps back down
|
||
on the trait, takes hold of it again, blocks its line of flight, and reimposes its
|
||
organization upon it. (There is a medical distinction between the clonic or
|
||
convulsive tic and the tonic or spasmodic tic; perhaps we can say that in the
|
||
first case the faciality trait that is trying to escape has the upper hand,
|
||
whereas in the second case the facial organization that is trying to clamp
|
||
back down or immobilize itself has the upper hand.) But if dismantling the
|
||
face is a major affair, it is because it is not simply a question of tics, or an
|
||
amateur's or aesthete's adventure. If the face is a politics, dismantling the
|
||
face is also a politics involving real becomings, an entire becoming-
|
||
clandestine. Dismantling the face is the same as breaking through the wall
|
||
of the signifier and getting out of the black hole of subjectivity. Here, the
|
||
program, the slogan, of schizoanalysis is: Find your black holes and white
|
||
walls, know them, know your faces; it is the only way you will be able to dis-
|
||
mantle them and draw your lines of flight.22
|
||
It is time once again to multiply practical warnings. First, it is never a
|
||
question of a return to ... It is not a question of "returning" to the
|
||
presignifying and presubjective semiotics of primitive peoples. We will
|
||
always be failures at playing African or Indian, even Chinese, and no voy-
|
||
age to the South Seas, however arduous, will allow us to cross the wall, get
|
||
out of the hole, or lose our face. We will never succeed in making ourselves a
|
||
new primitive head and body, human, spiritual, and faceless. It would only
|
||
be taking more photos and bouncing off the wall again. We will always find
|
||
ourselves reterritorialized again. O my little desert island, on you I am in
|
||
the Closerie des Lilas again, O my deep ocean, you reflect the lake in the
|
||
Bois de Boulogne, O little phrase of Vinteuil, you recall a sweet moment.
|
||
These are Eastern physical and spiritual exercises, but for a couple, like a
|
||
conjugal bed tucked with a Chinese sheet: you did do your exercises today,
|
||
didn't you? Lawrence has only one grudge against Melville: he knew better
|
||
than anyone how to get across the face, the eyes and horizon, the wall and
|
||
hole, but he mistook that crossing, that creative line, for an "impossible
|
||
return," a return to the savages in Typee, for a way of staying an artist and
|
||
hating life, of maintaining a nostalgia for the Home Country. ("He ever
|
||
pined for Home and Mother, the two things he had run away from as far as
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 189
|
||
|
||
ships would carry h i m . . . . Melville came home to face out the rest of his
|
||
life.... He refused life. But he stuck to his ideal of perfect relationship, pos-
|
||
sible perfect love A truly perfect relationship is one in which each party
|
||
leaves great tracts unknown in the other party.. . . Melville was, at the core,
|
||
a mystic and an idealist.... And he stuck to his ideal guns. I abandon mine.
|
||
I say, let the old guns rot. Get new ones, and shoot straight.")2*
|
||
We can't turn back. Only neurotics, or, as Lawrence says, "renegades,"
|
||
deceivers, attempt a regression. The white wall of the signifier, the black
|
||
hole of subjectivity, and the facial machine are impasses, the measure of
|
||
our submissions and subjections; but we are born into them, and it is there
|
||
we must stand battle. Not in the sense of a necessary stage, but in the sense
|
||
of a tool for which a new use must be invented. Only across the wall of the
|
||
signifier can you run lines of asignifiance that void all memory, all return,
|
||
all possible signification and interpretation. Only in the black hole of
|
||
subjective consciousness and passion do you discover the transformed,
|
||
heated, captured particles you must relaunch for a nonsubjective, living
|
||
love in which each party connects with unknown tracts in the other without
|
||
entering or conquering them, in which the lines composed are broken lines.
|
||
Only on your face and at the bottom of your black hole and upon your white
|
||
wall will you be able to set faciality traits free like birds, not in order to
|
||
return to a primitive head, but to invent the combinations by which those
|
||
traits connect with landscapity traits that have themselves been freed from
|
||
the landscape and with traits of picturality and musicality that have also
|
||
been freed from their respective codes. With what joy the painters used the
|
||
face of Christ himself, taking it in every sense and direction; and it was not
|
||
simply the joy of a desire to paint, but the joy of all desires. Is it possible to
|
||
tell, when the knight of the courtly novel is in his catatonic state, whether
|
||
he is deep in his black hole or already astride the particles that will carry
|
||
him out of it to begin a new journey? Lawrence, who has been compared to
|
||
Lancelot, writes: "To be alone, mindless and memoryless beside the sea...
|
||
As alone and as absent and as present as an aboriginal dark on the sand in
|
||
the sun ... Far off, far off, as if he had landed on another planet, as a man
|
||
might after death. . . The landscape?—he cared not a thing about the land-
|
||
scape. . . . Humanity?—there was none. Thought?—fallen like a stone into
|
||
the sea. The great, the glamorous past?—worn thin, frail, like a frail trans-
|
||
lucent film of shell thrown up on the shore."24 The uncertain moment at
|
||
which the white wall/black hole, black point/white shore system, as on a
|
||
Japanese print, itself becomes one with the act of leaving it, breaking away
|
||
from and crossing through it.
|
||
We have seen that the abstract machine has two very different states:
|
||
sometimes it is taken up in strata where it brings about deterritorial-
|
||
izations that are merely relative, or deterritorializations that are absolute
|
||
190 D YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY
|
||
|
||
but remain negative; sometimes it is developed on a plane of consistency
|
||
giving it a "diagrammatic" function, a positive value of deterritorial-
|
||
ization, the ability to form new abstract machines. Sometimes the abstract
|
||
machine, as the faciality machine, forces flows into signifiances and
|
||
subjectifications, into knots of aborescence and holes of abolition; some-
|
||
times, to the extent that it performs a veritable "defacialization," it frees
|
||
something like probe-heads (tetes chercheuses, guidance devices) that dis-
|
||
mantle the strata in their wake, break through the walls of signifiance, pour
|
||
out of the holes of subjectivity, fell trees in favor of veritable rhizomes, and
|
||
steer the flows down lines of positive deterritorializaton or creative flight.
|
||
There are no more concentrically organized strata, no more black holes
|
||
around which lines coil to form borders, no more walls to which dichoto-
|
||
mies, binarities, and bipolar values cling. There is no more face to be in
|
||
redundancy with a landscape, painting, or little phrase of music, each per-
|
||
petually bringing the other to mind, on the unified surface of the wall or the
|
||
central swirl of the black hole. Each freed faciality trait forms a rhizome
|
||
with a freed trait of landscapity, picturality, or musicality. This is not a col-
|
||
lection of part-objects but a living block, a connecting of stems by which
|
||
the traits of a face enter a real multiplicity or diagram with a trait of an
|
||
unknown landscape, a trait of painting or music that is thereby effectively
|
||
produced, created, according to quanta of absolute, positive deterritori-
|
||
alization—not evoked or recalled according to systems of reterritorializa-
|
||
tion. A wasp trait and an orchid trait. Quanta marking so many mutations
|
||
of abstract machines, each of which operates as a function of the other.
|
||
Thus opens a rhizomatic realm of possibility effecting the potentialization
|
||
of the possible, as opposed to arborescent possibility, which marks a clo-
|
||
sure, an impotence.
|
||
The face, what a horror. It is naturally a lunar landscape, with its pores,
|
||
planes, matts, bright colors, whiteness, and holes: there is no need for a
|
||
close-up to make it inhuman; it is naturally a close-up, and naturally
|
||
inhuman, a monstrous hood. Necessarily so because it is produced by a
|
||
machine and in order to meet the requirements of the special apparatus of
|
||
power that triggers the machine and takes deterritorialization to the abso-
|
||
lute while keeping it negative. Earlier, when we contrasted the primitive,
|
||
spiritual, human head with the inhuman face, we were falling victim to a
|
||
nostalgia for a return or regression. In truth, there are only inhumanities,
|
||
humans are made exclusively of inhumanities, but very different ones, of
|
||
very different natures and speeds. Primitive inhumanity, prefacial inhu-
|
||
manity, has all the polyvocality of a semiotic in which the head is a part of
|
||
the body, a body that is already deterritorialized relatively and plugged
|
||
into becomings-spiritual/animal. Beyond the face lies an altogether differ-
|
||
ent inhumanity: no longer that of the primitive head, but of "probe-heads";
|
||
YEAR ZERO: FACIALITY D 191
|
||
|
||
here, cutting edges of deterritorialization become operative and lines of
|
||
deterritorialization positive and absolute, forming strange new becom-
|
||
ings, new polyvocalities. Become clandestine, make rhizome everywhere,
|
||
for the wonder of a nonhuman life to be created. Face, my love, you have
|
||
finally become a probe-head... Year zen, year omega, year c o . . . Must we
|
||
leave it at that, three states, and no more: primitive heads, Christ-face, and
|
||
probe-heads?
|
||
8. 1874: Three Novellas, or
|
||
"What Happened?"
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
It is not very difficult to determine the essence of the "novella" as a literary
|
||
genre: Everything is organized around the question, "What happened?
|
||
Whatever could have happened?" The tale is the opposite of the novella,
|
||
because it is an altogether different question that the reader asks with bated
|
||
breath: What is going to happen? Something is always going to happen,
|
||
come to pass. Something always happens in the novel also, but the novel
|
||
integrates elements of the novella and the tale into the variation of its
|
||
perpetual living present (duration). The detective novel is a particularly
|
||
hybrid genre in this respect, since most often the something = X that has
|
||
happened is on the order of a murder or theft, but exactly what it is that has
|
||
happened remains to be discovered, and in the present determined by the
|
||
model detective. Yet it would be an error to reduce these different aspects
|
||
to the three dimensions of time. Something happened, something is going
|
||
to happen, can designate a past so immediate, a future so near, that they are
|
||
one (as Husserl would say) with retentions and protentions of the present
|
||
192
|
||
1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?" D 193
|
||
|
||
itself. Nevertheless, the distinction is legitimate, in view of the different
|
||
movements that animate the present, are contemporaneous with it: One
|
||
moves with it, another already casts it into the past from the moment it is
|
||
present (novella), while another simultaneously draws it into the future
|
||
(tale). We are lucky to have treatments of the same subject by a tale writer
|
||
and a novella writer: two lovers, one of whom dies suddenly in the other's
|
||
room. In Maupassant's tale, "Une ruse" (An artifice), everything revolves
|
||
around these questions: What is going to happen? How will the survivor
|
||
extricate himself from the situation? What will the third party-savior, in
|
||
this case a doctor, think of? In Barbey d'Aurevilly's novella, "Le rideau
|
||
cramoisi" (The crimson curtain), everything revolves around: Something
|
||
happened, but what? That is the question, not only because it is really not
|
||
known what the cold young woman just died from, but also because it will
|
||
never be known why she gave herself to the petty officer, or how the third
|
||
party-savior, here the colonel of the regiment, was able to arrange things.' It
|
||
should not be thought that it is easier to leave things open-ended: for there
|
||
to be something that has happened that we will never know about, or even
|
||
several things in a row, requires no less minute attention and precision than
|
||
the contrary case, when the author must invent the details of what will need
|
||
to be known. You will never know what just happened, or you will always
|
||
know what is going to happen: these are the reasons for the reader's two
|
||
bated breaths, in the novella and the tale, respectively, and they are two
|
||
ways in which the living present is divided at every instant. In the novella,
|
||
we do not wait for something to happen, we expect something to have just
|
||
happened. The novella is a last novella, whereas the tale is a first tale. The
|
||
"presence" of the tale writer is completely different from that of the novella
|
||
writer (and both are different from that of the novelist). Let us not dwell too
|
||
much on the dimensions of time: the novella has little to do with a memory
|
||
of the past or an act of reflection; quite to the contrary, it plays upon a fun-
|
||
damental forgetting. It evolves in the element of "what happened" because
|
||
it places us in a relation with something unknowable and imperceptible
|
||
(and not the other way around: it is not because it speaks of a past about
|
||
which it can no longer provide us knowledge). It may even be that nothing
|
||
has happened, but it is precisely that nothing that makes us say, Whatever
|
||
could have happened to make me forget where I put my keys, or whether I
|
||
mailed that letter, etc.? What little blood vessel in my brain could have rup-
|
||
tured? What is this nothing that makes something happen? The novella has
|
||
a fundamental relation to secrecy (not with a secret matter or object to be
|
||
discovered, but with the form of the secret, which remains impenetrable),
|
||
whereas the tale has a relation to discovery (the form of discovery, indepen-
|
||
dent of what can be discovered). The novella also enacts postures of the
|
||
body and mind that are like folds or envelopments, whereas the tale puts
|
||
194 D 1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?"
|
||
|
||
into play attitudes or positions that are like unfoldings and developments,
|
||
however unexpected. Barbey has an evident fondness for body posture, in
|
||
other words, states of the body when it is surprised by something that just
|
||
happened. In the preface to the Diaboliques, Barbey even suggests that
|
||
there is a diabolism of body postures, a sexuality, pornography, and scatol-
|
||
ogy of postures quite different from those that also, and simultaneously,
|
||
mark body attitudes or positions. Posture is like inverse suspense. Thus it
|
||
is not a question of saying that the novella relates to the past and the tale to
|
||
the future; what we should say instead is that the novella relates, in the pres-
|
||
ent itself, to the formal dimension of something that has happened, even if
|
||
that something is nothing or remains unknowable. Similarly, one should
|
||
not try to make the distinction between the novella and the tale coincide
|
||
with categories such as the fantastic, the fabulous, etc.; that is another
|
||
problem, there is no reason why it should overlap. The links of the novella
|
||
are: What happened? (the modality or expression), Secrecy (the form),
|
||
Body Posture (the content).
|
||
Take Fitzgerald. He is a tale and novella writer of genius. He is a novella
|
||
writer when he asks himself, Whatever could have happened for things to
|
||
have come to this? He is the only one who has been able to carry this ques-
|
||
tion to such a point of intensity. It is not a question of memory, reflection,
|
||
old age, or fatigue, whereas the tale would deal with childhood, action, or
|
||
impulse. Yet it is true that Fitzgerald only asks himself the question of the
|
||
novella writer when he is personally worn-out, fatigued, sick, or even worse
|
||
off. But once again, there is not necessarily a connection: it can also be a
|
||
question of vigor, or love. It still is, even in desperate conditions. It is better
|
||
to think of it as an affair of perception: you enter a room and perceive
|
||
something as already there, as just having happened, even though it has not
|
||
yet been done. Or you know that what is in the process of happening is hap-
|
||
pening for the last time, it's already over with. You hear an "I love you" you
|
||
know is the last one. Perceptual semiotics. God, whatever could have hap-
|
||
pened, even though everything is and remains imperceptible, and in order
|
||
for everything to be and remain imperceptible forever?
|
||
Not only is there a specificity of the novella, but there is also a specific
|
||
way in which the novella treats a universal matter. For we are made of lines.
|
||
We are not only referring to lines of writing. Lines of writing conjugate with
|
||
other lines, life lines, lines of luck or misfortune, lines productive of the
|
||
variation of the line of writing itself, lines that are between the lines of writ-
|
||
ing. Perhaps the novella has its own way of giving rise to and combining
|
||
these lines, which nonetheless belong to everyone and every genre.
|
||
Vladimir Propp has said, with great solemnity, that the folktale must be
|
||
defined in terms of external and internal movements that it qualifies, for-
|
||
malizes, and combines in its own specific way.2 We would like to demon-
|
||
1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?" D 195
|
||
|
||
strate that the novella is defined by living lines, flesh lines, about which it
|
||
brings a special revelation. Marcel Arland is correct to say that the novella
|
||
"is nothing but pure lines right down to the nuances, and nothing but the
|
||
pure and conscious power of the word."3
|
||
|
||
First Novella: "In the Cage," Henry James
|
||
The heroine, a young telegrapher, leads a very clear-cut, calculated life pro-
|
||
ceeding by delimited segments: the telegrams she takes one after the other,
|
||
day after day; the people to whom she sends the telegrams; their social class
|
||
and the different ways they use telegraphy; the words to be counted. More-
|
||
over, her telegraphist's cage is like a contiguous segment to the grocery
|
||
store next door, where her fiance works. Contiguity of territories. And the
|
||
fiance is constantly plotting out their future, work, vacations, house. Here,
|
||
as for all of us, there is a line of rigid segmentarity on which everything
|
||
seems calculable and foreseen, the beginning and end of a segment, the pas-
|
||
sage from one segment to another. Our lives are made like that: Not only
|
||
are the great molar aggregates segmented (States, institutions, classes), but
|
||
so are people as elements of an aggregate, as are feelings as relations
|
||
between people; they are segmented, not in such a way as to disturb or dis-
|
||
perse, but on the contrary to ensure and control the identity of each agency,
|
||
including personal identity. The fiance can say to the young woman, Even
|
||
though there are differences between our segments, we have the same tastes
|
||
and we are alike. I am a man, you are a woman; you are a telegraphist, I am a
|
||
grocer; you count words, I weigh things; our segments fit together, conju-
|
||
gate. Conjugality. A whole interplay of well-determined, well-planned ter-
|
||
ritories. They have a future but no becoming. This is the first life line, the
|
||
molar or rigid line of segmentarity; in no sense is it dead, for it occupies and
|
||
pervades our life, and always seems to prevail in the end. It even includes
|
||
much tenderness and love. It would be too easy to say, "This is a bad line,"
|
||
for you find it everywhere, and in all the other lines.
|
||
A rich couple comes into the post office and reveals to the young woman,
|
||
or at least confirms, the existence of another life: coded, multiple tele-
|
||
grams, signed with pseudonyms. It is hard to tell who is who anymore, or
|
||
what anything means. Instead of a rigid line composed of well-determined
|
||
segments, telegraphy now forms a supple flow marked by quanta that are
|
||
like so many little segmentations-in-progress grasped at the moment of
|
||
their birth, as on a moonbeam, or on an intensive scale. Thanks to her "pro-
|
||
digious talent for interpretation," the young woman grasps that the man
|
||
has a secret that has placed him in danger, deeper and deeper in danger, in a
|
||
dangerous posture. It does not just have to do with his love relations with
|
||
the woman. James has reached the stage in his work when it is no longer the
|
||
196 D 1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?"
|
||
|
||
matter of the secret that interests him, even if he has succeeded in render-
|
||
ing it entirely banal and unimportant. Now what counts is the form of the
|
||
secret; the matter no longer even has to be discovered (we never find out,
|
||
there are several possibilities, there is an objective indetermination, a kind
|
||
of molecularization of the secret). In relation to this man, directly with
|
||
him, the young telegraphist develops a strange passional complicity, a
|
||
whole intense molecular life that does not even enter into rivalry with the
|
||
life she leads with her fiance. What has happened, whatever could have
|
||
happened? This life, however, is not in her head, it is not imaginary. Rather,
|
||
we should say that there are two politics involved, as the young woman sug-
|
||
gests in a remarkable conversation with her fiance: a macropolitics and a
|
||
micropolitics that do not envision classes, sexes, people, or feelings in at all
|
||
the same way. Or again, there are two very different types of relations:
|
||
intrinsic relations of couples involving well-determined aggregates or ele-
|
||
ments (social classes, men and women, this or that particular person), and
|
||
less localizable relations that are always external to themselves and instead
|
||
concern flows and particles eluding those classes, sexes, and persons. Why
|
||
are the latter relations of doubles rather than of couples? "She was literally
|
||
afraid of the alternate self who might be waiting outside. He might be wait-
|
||
ing; it was he who was her alternate self, and of him she was afraid."4 In any
|
||
case, this line is very different from the previous one; it is a line of molecu-
|
||
lar or supple segmentation the segments of which are like quanta of
|
||
deterritorialization. It is on this line that a present is defined whose very
|
||
form is the form of something that has already happened, however close
|
||
you might be to it, since the ungraspable matter of that something is
|
||
entirely molecularized, traveling at speeds beyond the ordinary thresholds
|
||
of perception. Yet we will not say that it is necessarily better.
|
||
There is no question that the two lines are constantly interfering, react-
|
||
ing upon each other, introducing into each other either a current of supple-
|
||
ness or a point of rigidity. Nathalie Sarraute, in her essay on the novel,
|
||
praises English novelists, not only for discovering (as did Proust and
|
||
Dostoyevsky) the great movements, territories, and points of the uncon-
|
||
scious that allow us to regain time or revive the past, but also for
|
||
inopportunely following these molecular lines, simultaneously present and
|
||
imperceptible. She shows that dialogue or conversation does indeed com-
|
||
ply with the breaks of a fixed segmentarity, with vast movements of regu-
|
||
lated distribution corresponding to the attitudes and positions of each of
|
||
us; but also that they are run through and swept up by micromovements,
|
||
fine segmentations distributed in an entirely different way, unfindable par-
|
||
ticles of an anonymous matter, tiny cracks and postures operating by dif-
|
||
ferent agencies even in the unconscious, secret lines of disorientation or
|
||
1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?" D 197
|
||
|
||
deterritorialization: as she puts it, a whole subconversation within conver-
|
||
sation, in other words, a micropolitics of conversation.5
|
||
Then James's heroine reaches a sort of maximum quantum in her sup-
|
||
ple segmentarity or line of flow beyond which she cannot go (even if she
|
||
wanted to, there is no going further). There is a danger that these vibrations
|
||
traversing us may be aggravated beyond our endurance. What happened?
|
||
The molecular relation between the telegraphist and the telegraph sender
|
||
dissolved in the form of the secret—because nothing happened. Each of
|
||
them is propelled toward a rigid segmentarity: he will marry the now-
|
||
widowed lady, she will marry her fiance. And yet everything has changed.
|
||
She has reached something like a new line, a third type, a kind of line of
|
||
flight that is just as real as the others even if it occurs in place: this line no
|
||
longer tolerates segments; rather, it is like an exploding of the two
|
||
segmentary series. She has broken through the wall, she has gotten out of
|
||
the black holes. She has attained a kind of absolute deterritorialization.
|
||
"She ended up knowing so much that she could no longer interpret any-
|
||
thing. There were no longer shadows to help her see more clearly, only
|
||
glare."6 You cannot go further in life than this sentence by James. The
|
||
nature of the secret has changed once again. Undoubtedly, the secret
|
||
always has to do with love, and sexuality. But previously it was either only a
|
||
hidden matter given in the past (the better hidden the more ordinary it
|
||
was), and we did not exactly know what form to give it: See, I am bending
|
||
under the burden of my secret, see what mystery resides within me. It was a
|
||
way of seeming interesting, what D. H. Lawrence called "the dirty little
|
||
secret," my Oedipus, in a way. Or else the secret became the form of some-
|
||
thing whose matter was molecularized, imperceptible, unassignable: not a
|
||
given of the past but the ungivable "What happened?" But on this third line
|
||
there is no longer even any form—nothing but a pure abstract line. It is
|
||
because we no longer have anything to hide that we can no longer be appre-
|
||
hended. To become imperceptible oneself, to have dismantled love in
|
||
order to become capable of loving. To have dismantled one's self in order
|
||
finally to be alone and meet the true double at the other end of the line. A
|
||
clandestine passenger on a motionless voyage. To become like everybody
|
||
else; but this, precisely, is a becoming only for one who knows how to be
|
||
nobody, to no longer be anybody. To paint oneself gray on gray. As
|
||
Kierkegaard says, nothing distinguishes the knight of the faith from a bour-
|
||
geois German going home or to the post office: he sends off no special tele-
|
||
graphic sign; he constantly produces or reproduces finite segments, yet he
|
||
is already moving on a line no one even suspects.7 In any case, the tele-
|
||
graphic line is not a symbol, and it is not simple. There are at least three of
|
||
them: a line of rigid and clear-cut segmentarity; a line of molecular
|
||
segmentarity; and an abstract line, a line of flight no less deadly and no less
|
||
198 D 1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?"
|
||
|
||
alive than the others. On the first line, there are many words and conversa-
|
||
tions, questions and answers, interminable explanations, precisions; the
|
||
second is made of silences, allusions, and hasty innuendos inviting
|
||
interpretation. But if the third line flashes, if the line of flight is like a train
|
||
in motion, it is because one jumps linearly on it, one can finally speak
|
||
"literally" of anything at all, a blade of grass, a catastrophe or sensation,
|
||
calmly accepting that which occurs when it is no longer possible for any-
|
||
thing to stand for anything else. The three lines, however, continually
|
||
intermingle.
|
||
|
||
Second Novella:
|
||
"The Crack-up," F. Scott Fitzgerald
|
||
What happened? This is the question Fitzgerald keeps coming back to
|
||
toward the end, having remarked that "of course all life is a process of
|
||
breaking down."8 How should we understand this "of course"? We can say,
|
||
first of all, that life is always drawn into an increasingly rigid and desic-
|
||
cated segmentarity. For the writer Fitzgerald, voyages, with their clear-cut
|
||
segments, had lost their usefulness. There was also, from segment to seg-
|
||
ment, the depression, loss of wealth, fatigue and growing old, alcoholism,
|
||
the failure of conjugality, the rise of the cinema, the advent of fascism and
|
||
Stalinism, and the loss of success and talent—at the very moment
|
||
Fitzgerald would find his genius. " The big sudden blows that come, or seem
|
||
to come, from outside" (p. 69), and proceed by oversignificant breaks, mov-
|
||
ing us from one term to the other according to successive binary "choices":
|
||
rich/poor... Even when change runs in the other direction, there is noth-
|
||
ing to compensate for the rigidification, the aging that overcodes every-
|
||
thing that occurs. This is a line of rigid segmentarity bringing masses into
|
||
play, even if it was supple to begin with.
|
||
But Fitzgerald says that there is another type of cracking, with an en-
|
||
tirely different segmentarity. Instead of great breaks, these are micro-
|
||
cracks, as in a dish; they are much more subtle and supple, and occur when
|
||
things are going well on the other side. If there is aging on this line, it is not of
|
||
the same kind: when you age on this line you don't feel it on the other line,
|
||
you don't notice it on the other line until after "it" has already happened on
|
||
this line. At such a moment, which does not correspond to any of the ages of
|
||
the other line, you reach a degree, a quantum, an intensity beyond which
|
||
you cannot go. (It's a very delicate business, these intensities: the finest
|
||
intensity becomes harmful if it overtaxes your strength at a given moment;
|
||
you have to be able to take it, you have to be in shape.) But what exactly hap-
|
||
pened? In truth, nothing assignable or perceptible: molecular changes,
|
||
redistributions of desire such that when something occurs, the self that
|
||
1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?" D 199
|
||
|
||
awaited it is already dead, or the one that would await it has not yet arrived.
|
||
This time, there are outbursts and crackings in the immanence of a rhi-
|
||
zome, rather than great movements and breaks determined by the tran-
|
||
scendence of a tree. The crack-up "happens almost without your knowing it
|
||
but is realized suddenly indeed" (p. 69). This molecular line, more supple
|
||
but no less disquieting, in fact, much more disquieting, is not simply inter-
|
||
nal or personal: it also brings everything into play, but on a different scale
|
||
and in different forms, with segmentations of a different nature,
|
||
rhizomatic instead of arborescent. A micropolitics.
|
||
There is, in addition, a third line, which is like a line of rupture or a
|
||
"clean break" and marks the exploding of the other two, their shake-up...
|
||
in favor of something else? "This led me to the idea that the ones who had
|
||
survived had made some sort of clean break. This is a big word and is no
|
||
parallel to a jailbreak when one is probably headed for a new jail or will be
|
||
forced back to the old one" (p. 81). Here, Fitzgerald contrasts rupture with
|
||
structural pseudobreaks in so-called signifying chains. But he also distin-
|
||
guishes it from more supple, more subterranean links or stems of the "voy-
|
||
age" type, or even from molecular conveyances. "The famous 'Escape' or
|
||
'run away from it all' is an excursion in a trap even if the trap includes the
|
||
South Seas, which are only for those who want to paint them or sail them. A
|
||
clean break is something you cannot come back from; that is irretrievable
|
||
because it makes the past cease to exist" (p. 81). Can it be that voyages are
|
||
always a return to rigid segmentarity? Is it always your daddy and mommy
|
||
that you meet when you travel, even as far away as the South Seas, like
|
||
Melville? Hardened muscles? Must we say that supple segmentarity itself
|
||
reconstructs the great figures it claimed to escape, but under the micro-
|
||
scope, in miniature? Beckett's unforgettable line is an indictment of all
|
||
voyages: " We don't travel for the fun of it, as far as I know; we're foolish, but
|
||
not that foolish.'"
|
||
In rupture, not only has the matter of the past volitized; the form of what
|
||
happened, of an imperceptible something that happened in a volatile mat-
|
||
ter, no longer even exists. One has become imperceptible and clandestine
|
||
in motionless voyage. Nothing can happen, or can have happened, any
|
||
longer. Nobody can do anything for or against me any longer. My territories
|
||
are out of grasp, not because they are imaginary, but the opposite: because I
|
||
am in the process of drawing them. Wars, big and little, are behind me. Voy-
|
||
ages, always in tow to something else, are behind me. I no longer have any
|
||
secrets, having lost my face, form, and matter. I am now no more than a
|
||
line. I have become capable of loving, not with an abstract, universal love,
|
||
but a love I shall choose, and that shall choose me, blindly, my double, just
|
||
as selfless as I. One has been saved by and for love, by abandoning love and
|
||
self. Now one is no more than an abstract line, like an arrow crossing the
|
||
200 D 1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?"
|
||
|
||
void. Absolute deterritorialization. One has become like everybody/the
|
||
whole world (tout le monde), but in a way that can become like everybody/
|
||
the whole world. One has painted the world on oneself, not oneself on the
|
||
world. It should not be said that the genius is an extraordinary person, nor
|
||
that everybody has genius. The genius is someone who knows how to make
|
||
everybody/the whole world a becoming (Ulysses, perhaps: Joyce's failed
|
||
ambition, Pound's near-success). One has entered becomings-animal,
|
||
becomings-molecular, and finally becomings-imperceptible. "I was off the
|
||
dispensing end of the relief roll forever. The heady villainous feeling con-
|
||
tinued. . . . I will try to be a correct animal though, and if you throw me a
|
||
bone with enough meat on it I may even lick your hand."9 Why such a
|
||
despairing tone? Does not the line of rupture or true flight have its own
|
||
danger, one worse than the others? Time to die. In any case, Fitzgerald pro-
|
||
poses a distinction between the three lines traversing us and composing "a
|
||
life" (after Maupassant). Break line, crack line, rupture line. The line of
|
||
rigid segmentarity with molar breaks; the line of supple segmentation with
|
||
molecular cracks; the line of flight or rupture, abstract, deadly and alive,
|
||
nonsegmentary.
|
||
|
||
Third Novella:
|
||
"The Story of the Abyss and the Spyglass," Pierrette Fleutiaux10
|
||
Some segments are more or less near, and others more or less distant. The
|
||
segments seem to encircle an abyss, a kind of huge black hole. On each seg-
|
||
ment there are two kinds of lookouts, near-seers and far-seers. What they
|
||
watch for are the movements, outbursts, infractions, disturbances, and
|
||
rebellions occurring in the abyss. But there is a major difference between
|
||
the two types of lookouts. The near-seers have a simple spyglass. In the
|
||
abyss, they see the outline of gigantic cells, great binary divisions, dichoto-
|
||
mies, well-defined segments of the type "classroom, barracks, low-income
|
||
housing project, or even countryside seen from an airplane." They see
|
||
branches, chains, rows, columns, dominoes, striae. Once in a while along
|
||
the edges they discover a misshapen figure or a shaky contour. Then they
|
||
bring out the terrible Ray Telescope. It is used not to see with but to cut
|
||
with, to cut out shapes. This geometrical instrument, which emits a laser
|
||
beam, assures the dominion of the great signifying break everywhere and
|
||
restores the momentarily threatened molar order. The cutting telescope
|
||
overcodes everything; it acts on flesh and blood, but itself is nothing but
|
||
pure geometry, as a State affair, and the near-seers' physics in the service of
|
||
that machine. What is geometry, what is the State, and what are the near-
|
||
seers? These are meaningless questions ("I am speaking literally") because
|
||
it is not so much a question of defining something as effectively drawing a
|
||
1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?" D 201
|
||
|
||
line; not a line of writing but a line of rigid segmentarity along which every-
|
||
one will be judged and rectified according to his or her contours, individual
|
||
or collective.
|
||
Very different is the situation of those with long-distance vision, the far-
|
||
seers, with all their ambiguities. There are very few of them, at most one per
|
||
segment. Their telescopes are complex and refined. But they are in no way
|
||
leaders. And what they see is entirely different from what the others see.
|
||
They see a whole microsegmentarity, details of details, "a roller coaster of
|
||
possibilities," tiny movements that have not reached the edge, lines or
|
||
vibrations that start to form long before there are outlined shapes, "seg-
|
||
ments that move by jerks." A whole rhizome, a molecular segmentarity
|
||
that does not permit itself to be overcoded by a signifier like the cutting
|
||
machine, or even to be attributed to a given figure, a given aggregate or ele-
|
||
ment. This second line is inseparable from the anonymous segmentation
|
||
that produces it and challenges everything all the time, without goal or rea-
|
||
son: "What happened?" The far-seers can divine the future, but always in
|
||
the form of a becoming of something that has already happened in a molec-
|
||
ular matter; unfindable particles. The situation is the same in biology: the
|
||
great cellular divisions and dichotomies, with their contours, are accompa-
|
||
nied by migrations, invaginations, displacements, and morphogenetic
|
||
impulses whose segments are marked not by localizable points but by
|
||
thresholds of intensity passing underneath, mitoses that scramble every-
|
||
thing, and molecular lines that intersect each other within the large-scale
|
||
cells and between their breaks. The situation is the same in a society: rigid
|
||
segments and overcutting segments are crosscut underneath by segmenta-
|
||
tions of another nature. But this is neither one nor the other, neither biol-
|
||
ogy nor a society; nor is it a resemblance between the two: "I am speaking
|
||
literally," I am drawing lines, lines of writing, and life passes between the
|
||
lines. A line of supple segmentarity formed and became entangled with the
|
||
other, but it was a very different kind of line, shakily drawn by the micro-
|
||
politics of the far-seers. It is a political affair, as worldwide in scope as the
|
||
other, but on a scale and in a form that is incommensurable, nonsuperpos-
|
||
able. It is also a perceptual affair, for perception always goes hand in hand
|
||
with semiotics, practice, politics, theory. One sees, speaks and thinks on a
|
||
given scale, and according to a given line that may or may not conjugate
|
||
with the other's line, even if the other is still oneself. If it does not, then you
|
||
should not insist, you should not argue; you should flee, flee, even saying as
|
||
you go, "Okay, okay, you win." It's no use talking; you first have to change
|
||
telescopes, mouths, and teeth, all of the segments. Not only does one speak
|
||
literally, one also lives literally, in other words, following lines, whether
|
||
connectable or not, even heterogeneous ones. Sometimes it doesn't work
|
||
when they are homogeneous."
|
||
202 D 1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?"
|
||
|
||
The ambiguity of the far-seers' situation is that they are able to detect the
|
||
slightest microinfraction in the abyss, things the others do not see; they also
|
||
observe, beneath its apparent geometrical justice, the dreadful damage
|
||
caused by the Cutting Telescope. They feel as though they foresee things
|
||
and are ahead of the others because they see the smallest thing as already
|
||
having happened; but they know that their warnings are to no avail because
|
||
the cutting telescope will set everything straight without being warned,
|
||
without the need for or possibility of prediction. At times they feel that
|
||
they do indeed see something the others do not, but at other times that
|
||
what they see differs only in degree and serves no purpose. Although they
|
||
are collaborators with the most rigid and cruelest project of control, how
|
||
could they not feel a vague sympathy for the subterranean activity revealed
|
||
to them? An ambiguity in the molecular line, as if it vacillated between two
|
||
sides. One day (what will have happened?), a far-seer will abandon his or
|
||
her segment and start walking across a narrow overpass above the dark
|
||
abyss, will break his or her telescope and depart on a line of flight to meet a
|
||
blind Double approaching from the other side.
|
||
|
||
Individual or group, we are traversed by lines, meridians, geodesies,
|
||
tropics, and zones marching to different beats and differing in nature. We
|
||
said that we are composed of lines, three kinds of lines. Or rather, of bun-
|
||
dles of lines, for each kind is multiple. We may be more interested in a cer-
|
||
tain line than in the others, and perhaps there is indeed one that is, not
|
||
determining, but of greater importance . . . if it is there. For some of these
|
||
lines are imposed on us from outside, at least in part. Others sprout up
|
||
somewhat by chance, from a trifle, why we will never know. Others can be
|
||
invented, drawn, without a model and without chance: we must invent our
|
||
lines of flight, if we are able, and the only way we can invent them is by
|
||
effectively drawing them, in our lives. Aren't lines of flight the most diffi-
|
||
cult of all? Certain groups or people have none and never will. Certain
|
||
groups or people lack a given kind of line, or have lost it. The painter Flor-
|
||
ence Julien has a special interest in lines of flight: she invented a procedure
|
||
by which she extracts from photographs lines that are nearly abstract and
|
||
formless. But once again, there is a bundle of very diverse lines: the line of
|
||
flight of children leaving school at a run is different from that of demon-
|
||
strators chased by the police, or of a prisoner breaking out. There are differ-
|
||
ent animal lines of flight: each species, each individual, has its own.
|
||
Fernand Deligny transcribes the lines and paths of autistic children by
|
||
means of maps: he carefully distinguishes "lines of drift" and "customary
|
||
lines." This does not only apply to walking; he also makes maps of percep-
|
||
tions and maps of gestures (cooking or collecting wood) showing custom-
|
||
ary gestures and gestures of drift. The same goes for language, if it is
|
||
1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?" D 203
|
||
|
||
present. Deligny opened his lines of writing to life lines. The lines are con-
|
||
stantly crossing, intersecting for a moment, following one another. A line of
|
||
drift intersects a customary line, and at that point the child does something
|
||
not quite belonging to either one: he or she finds something he or she lost—
|
||
what happened?—or jumps and claps his or her hands, a slight and rapid
|
||
movement—and that gesture in turn emits several lines.'2 In short, there is
|
||
a line of flight, which is already complex since it has singularities; and there
|
||
a customary or molar line with segments; and between the two (?), there is a
|
||
molecular line with quanta that cause it to tip to one side or the other.
|
||
As Deligny says, it should be borne in mind that these lines mean noth-
|
||
ing. It is an affair of cartography. They compose us, as they compose our
|
||
map. They transform themselves and may even cross over into one
|
||
another. Rhizome. It is certain that they have nothing to do with language;
|
||
it is, on the contrary, language that must follow them, it is writing that must
|
||
take sustenance from them, between its own lines. It is certain that they
|
||
have nothing to do with a signifier, the determination of a subject by the
|
||
signifier; instead, the signifier arises at the most rigidified level of one of
|
||
the lines, and the subject is spawned at the lowest level. It is certain that
|
||
they have nothing to do with a structure, which is never occupied by any-
|
||
thing more than points and positions, by arborescences, and which always
|
||
forms a closed system, precisely in order to prevent escape. Deligny
|
||
invokes a common Body upon which these lines are inscribed as so many
|
||
segments, thresholds, or quanta, territorialities, deterritorializations, or
|
||
reterritorializations. The lines are inscribed on a Body without Organs,
|
||
upon which everything is drawn and flees, which is itself an abstract line
|
||
with neither imaginary figures nor symbolic functions: the real of the BwO.
|
||
This body is the only practical object of schizoanalysis: What is your body
|
||
without organs? What are your lines? What map are you in the process of
|
||
making or rearranging? What abstract line will you draw, and at what price,
|
||
for yourself and for others? What is your line of flight? What is your BwO,
|
||
merged with that line? Are you cracking up? Are you going to crack up? Are
|
||
you deterritorializing? Which lines are you severing, and which are you
|
||
extending or resuming? Schizoanalysis does not pertain to elements or
|
||
aggregates, nor to subjects, relations, or structures. It pertains only to linea-
|
||
ments running through groups as well as individuals. Schizoanalysis, as the
|
||
analysis of desire, is immediately practical and political, whether it is a
|
||
question of an individual, group, or society. For politics precedes being.
|
||
Practice does not come after the emplacement of the terms and their rela-
|
||
tions, but actively participates in the drawing of the lines; it confronts the
|
||
same dangers and the same variations as the emplacement does.
|
||
Schizoanalysis is like the art of the new. Or rather, there is no problem of
|
||
application: the lines it brings out could equally be the lines of a life, a work
|
||
204 D 1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?"
|
||
|
||
of literature or art, or a society, depending on which system of coordinates
|
||
is chosen.
|
||
Line of molar or rigid segmentarity, line of molecular or supple seg-
|
||
mentation, line of flight—many problems arise. The first concerns the
|
||
particular character of each line. It might be thought that rigid segments
|
||
are socially determined, predetermined, overcoded by the State; there
|
||
may be a tendency to construe supple segmentarity as an interior activity,
|
||
something imaginary or phantasmic. As for the line of flight, would it not
|
||
be entirely personal, the way in which an individual escapes on his or her
|
||
own account, escapes "responsibilities," escapes the world, takes refuge
|
||
in the desert, or else in a r t . . . ? False impression. Supple segmentarity
|
||
has nothing to do with the imaginary, and micropolitics is no less exten-
|
||
sive or real than macropolitics. Politics on the grand scale can never
|
||
administer its molar segments without also dealing with the micro-
|
||
injections or infiltrations that work in its favor or present an obstacle to it;
|
||
indeed, the larger the molar aggregates, the greater the molecularization
|
||
of the agencies they put into play. Lines of flight, for their part, never con-
|
||
sist in running away from the world but rather in causing runoffs, as when
|
||
you drill a hole in a pipe; there is no social system that does not leak from
|
||
all directions, even if it makes its segments increasingly rigid in order to
|
||
seal the lines of flight. There is nothing imaginary, nothing symbolic,
|
||
about a line of flight. There is nothing more active than a line of flight,
|
||
among animals or humans.13 Even History is forced to take that route
|
||
rather than proceeding by "signifying breaks." What is escaping in a soci-
|
||
ety at a given moment? It is on lines of flight that new weapons are
|
||
invented, to be turned against the heavy arms of the State. "I may be run-
|
||
ning, but I'm looking for a gun as I go" (George Jackson). It was along lines
|
||
of flight that the nomads swept away everything in their path and found
|
||
new weapons, leaving the Pharaoh thunderstruck. It is possible for a sin-
|
||
gle group, or a single individual even, to exhibit all the lines we have been
|
||
discussing simultaneously. But it is most frequently the case that a single
|
||
group or individual functions as a line of flight; that group or individual
|
||
creates the line rather than following it, is itself the living weapon it forges
|
||
rather than stealing one. Lines of flight are realities; they are very danger-
|
||
ous for societies, although they can get by without them, and sometimes
|
||
manage to keep them to a minimum.
|
||
The second problem concerns the respective importance of the lines.
|
||
You can begin with the rigid segmentarity, it's the easiest, it's pregiven;
|
||
and then you can look at how and to what extent it is crosscut by a supple
|
||
segmentarity, a kind of rhizome surrounding its roots. Then you can look
|
||
at how the line of flight enters in. And alliances and battles. But it is also
|
||
possible to begin with the line of flight: perhaps this is the primary line,
|
||
1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?" D 205
|
||
|
||
with its absolute deterritorialization. It is clear that the line of flight does
|
||
not come afterward; it is there from the beginning, even if it awaits its
|
||
hour, and waits for the others to explode. Supple segmentarity, then, is
|
||
only a kind of compromise operating by relative deterritorializations and
|
||
permitting reterritorializations that cause blockages and reversions to
|
||
the rigid line. It is odd how supple segmentarity is caught between the two
|
||
other lines, ready to tip to one side or the other; such is its ambiguity. It is
|
||
also necessary to look at the various combinations: it is quite possible that
|
||
one group or individual's line of flight may not work to benefit that of
|
||
another group or individual; it may on the contrary block it, plug it, throw
|
||
it even deeper into rigid segmentarity. It can happen in love that one per-
|
||
son's creative line is the other's imprisonment. The composition of the
|
||
lines, of one line with another, is a problem, even of two lines of the same
|
||
type. There is no assurance that two lines of flight will prove compatible,
|
||
compossible. There is no assurance that the body without organs will be
|
||
easy to compose. There is no assurance that a love, or a political ap-
|
||
proach, will withstand it.
|
||
Third problem: there is a mutual immanence of the lines. And it is not
|
||
easy to sort them out. No one of them is transcendent, each is at work
|
||
within the others. Immanence everywhere. Lines of flight are immanent to
|
||
the social field. Supple segmentarity continually dismantles the concre-
|
||
tions of rigid segmentarity, but everything that it dismantles it reassembles
|
||
on its own level: micro-Oedipuses, microformations of power,
|
||
microfascisms. The line of flight blasts the two segmentary series apart; but
|
||
it is capable of the worst, of bouncing off the wall, falling into a black hole,
|
||
taking the path of greatest regression, and in its vagaries reconstructing the
|
||
most rigid of segments. Have you sown your wild oats? That is worse than
|
||
not escaping at all: See Lawrence's reproach to Melville.14 Between the
|
||
matter of a dirty little secret in rigid segmentarity, the empty form of
|
||
"What happened?" in supple segmentarity, and clandestinity of what can
|
||
no longer happen on the line of flight, how can we fail to see the upheavals
|
||
caused by a monster force, the Secret, threatening to bring everything tum-
|
||
bling down? Between the Couple of the first kind of segmentarity, the Dou-
|
||
ble of the second, and the Clandestine of the line of flight, there are so many
|
||
possible mixtures and passages.
|
||
There is one last problem, the most anguishing one, concerning the dan-
|
||
gers specific to each line. There is not much to say about the danger con-
|
||
fronting the first, for the chances are slim that its rigidification will fail.
|
||
There is not much to say about the ambiguity of the second. But why is the
|
||
line of flight, even aside from the danger it runs of reverting to one of the
|
||
other two lines, imbued with such singular despair in spite of its message of
|
||
joy, as if at the very moment things are coming to a resolution its undertak-
|
||
206 O 1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?"
|
||
|
||
ing were threatened by something reaching down to its core, by a death, a
|
||
demolition? Shestov said of Chekhov, a great creator of novellas: "There
|
||
can be practically no doubt that Chekhov exerted himself, and something
|
||
broke inside him. And the overstrain came not from hard and heavy labor;
|
||
no mighty overpowering exploit broke him: he stumbled and fell, he
|
||
slipped. . . . The old Chekhov of gaiety and mirth is no more. . . . Instead, a
|
||
morose and overshadowed man, a 'criminal.' "15 What happened? Once
|
||
again, this is the question facing all of Chekhov's characters. Is it not possi-
|
||
ble to exert oneself, and even break something, without falling into a black
|
||
hole of bitterness and sand? But did Chekhov really fall? Is that not to
|
||
judge him entirely from the outside? Was Chekhov not correct in saying
|
||
that however grim his characters are, he still carries "a hundred pounds of
|
||
love"? Of course, nothing is easy on the lines that compose us, and that con-
|
||
stitute the essence of the Novella (la Nouvelle), and sometimes of Good
|
||
News (la Bonne Nouvelle).
|
||
What are your couples, your doubles, your clandestines, and what are
|
||
their mixes? When one person says to another, love the taste of whiskey on
|
||
my lips like I love the gleam of madness in your eyes, what lines are they in
|
||
the process of composing, or, on the contrary, making incompossible?
|
||
Fitzgerald: "Perhaps fifty percent of our friends and relations will tell you
|
||
in good faith that it was my drinking that drove Zelda mad, and the other
|
||
half would assure you that it was her madness that drove me to drink. Nei-
|
||
ther of these judgments means much of anything. These two groups of
|
||
friends and relations would be unanimous in saying that each of us would
|
||
have been much better off without the other. The irony is that we have
|
||
never been more in love with each other in all of our lives. She loves the
|
||
alcohol on my lips. I cherish her most extravagant hallucinations." "In the
|
||
end, nothing really had much importance. We destroyed ourselves. But in
|
||
all honesty, I never thought we destroyed each other." Beautiful texts. All
|
||
of the lines are there: the lines of family and friends, of all those who
|
||
speak, explain, and psychoanalyze, assigning rights and wrongs, of the
|
||
whole binary machine of the Couple, united or divided, in rigid seg-
|
||
mentarity (50 percent). Then there is the line of supple segmentation,
|
||
from which the alcoholic and the madwoman extract, as from a kiss on the
|
||
lips and eyes, the multiplication of a double at the limit of what they can
|
||
endure in their state and with the tacit understandings serving them as
|
||
internal messages. Finally, there is a line of flight, all the more shared now
|
||
that they are separated, or vice versa, each of them the clandestine of the
|
||
other, a double all the more successful now that nothing has importance
|
||
any longer, now that everything can begin anew, since they have been
|
||
destroyed but not by each other. Nothing will enter memory, everything
|
||
was on the lines, between the lines, in the AND that made one and the.
|
||
1874: THREE NOVELLAS, OR "WHAT HAPPENED?" D 207
|
||
|
||
other imperceptible, without disjunction or conjunction but only a line of
|
||
flight forever in the process of being drawn, toward a new acceptance, the
|
||
opposite of renunciation or resignation—a new happiness?
|
||
9. 1933: Micropolitics and Segmentarity
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Segmentarities (Overview of the Types)
|
||
|
||
We are segmented from all around and in every direction. The human being
|
||
is a segmentary animal. Segmentarity is inherent to all the strata composing
|
||
us. Dwelling, getting around, working, playing: life is spatially and socially
|
||
segmented. The house is segmented according to its rooms' assigned pur-
|
||
poses; streets, according to the order of the city; the factory, according to the
|
||
nature of the work and operations performed in it. We are segmented in a
|
||
binary fashion, following the great major dualist oppositions: social classes,
|
||
but also men-women, adults-children, and so on. We are segmented in a cir-
|
||
208
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 209
|
||
|
||
cular fashion, in ever larger circles, ever wider disks or coronas, like Joyce's
|
||
"letter": my affairs, my neighborhood's affairs, my city's, my country's, the
|
||
world's . . . We are segmented in a linear fashion, along a straight line or a
|
||
number of straight lines, of which each segment represents an episode or
|
||
"proceeding": as soon as we finish one proceeding we begin another, forever
|
||
proceduring or procedured, in the family, in school, in the army, on the job.
|
||
School tells us, "You're not at home anymore"; the army tells us, "You're not
|
||
in school anymore" . .. Sometimes the various segments belong to different
|
||
individuals or groups, and sometimes the same individual or group passes
|
||
from one segment to another. But these figures of segmentarity, the binary,
|
||
circular, and linear, are bound up with one another, even cross over into each
|
||
other, changing according to the point of view. This is already evident among
|
||
"savage" peoples: Lizot shows how the communal House is organized in cir-
|
||
cular fashion, going from interior to exterior in a series of coronas within
|
||
which certain types of localizable activities take place (worship and ceremo-
|
||
nies, followed by exchange of goods, followed by family life, followed by
|
||
trash and excrement); at the same time "each of these coronas is itself trans-
|
||
versally divided, each segment devolves upon a particular lineage and is sub-
|
||
divided among different kinship groups."1 In a more general context,
|
||
Levi-Strauss shows that the dualist organization of primitive peoples has a
|
||
circular form, and also takes a linear form encompassing "any number of
|
||
groups" (at least three).2
|
||
Why return to the primitives, when it is a question of our own life? The
|
||
fact is that the notion of segmentarity was constructed by ethnologists to
|
||
account for so-called primitive societies, which have no fixed, central State
|
||
apparatus and no global power mechanisms or specialized political institu-
|
||
tions. In these societies, the social segments have a certain leeway, between
|
||
the two extreme poles effusion and scission, depending on the task and the
|
||
situation; there is also considerable communicability between heterogene-
|
||
ous elements, so that one segment can fit with another in a number of
|
||
different ways; and they have a local construction excluding the prior
|
||
determination of a base domain (economic, political, juridical, artistic);
|
||
they have extrinsic and situational properties, or relations irreducible to
|
||
the intrinsic properties of a structure; activity is continuous, so segmen-
|
||
tarity is not grasped as something separate from a segmentation-in-
|
||
progress operating by outgrowths, detachments, and mergings. Primitive
|
||
segmentarity is characterized by a polyvocal code based on lineages and
|
||
their varying situations and relations, and an itinerant territoriality based
|
||
on local, overlapping divisions. Codes and territories, clan lineages and tri-
|
||
bal territorialities, form a fabric of relatively supple segmentarity.3
|
||
However, it seems to us difficult to maintain that State societies, even
|
||
our modern States, are any less segmentary. The classical opposition
|
||
210 D 1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
between segmentarity and centralization hardly seems relevant.4 Not only
|
||
does the State exercise power over the segments it sustains or permits to
|
||
survive, but it possesses, and imposes, its own segmentarity. Perhaps the
|
||
opposition sociologists establish between the segmentary and the central is
|
||
biological deep down: the ringed worm, and the central nervous system.
|
||
But the central brain itself is a worm, even more segmented than the others,
|
||
in spite of and including all of its vicarious actions. There is no opposition
|
||
between the central and the segmentary. The modern political system is a
|
||
global whole, unified and unifying, but is so because it implies a constella-
|
||
tion of juxtaposed, imbricated, ordered subsystems; the analysis of deci-
|
||
sion making brings to light all kinds of compartmentalizations and partial
|
||
processes that interconnect, but not without gaps and displacements.
|
||
Technocracy operates by the segmentary division of labor (this applies to
|
||
the international division of labor as well). Bureaucracy exists only in com-
|
||
partmentalized offices and functions only by "goal displacements" and the
|
||
corresponding "dysfunctions." Hierarchy is not simply pyramidal; the
|
||
boss's office is as much at the end of the hall as on top of the tower. In short,
|
||
we would say that modern life has not done away with segmentarity but has
|
||
on the contrary made it exceptionally rigid.
|
||
Instead of setting up an opposition between the segmentary and the cen-
|
||
tralized, we should make a distinction between two types of segmentarity,
|
||
one "primitive" and supple, the other "modern" and rigid. This distinction
|
||
reframes each of the figures previously discussed.
|
||
1. Binary oppositions (men/women, those on top/those on the bottom,
|
||
etc.) are very strong in primitive societies, but seem to be the result of
|
||
machines and assemblages that are not in themselves binary. The social
|
||
binarity between men and women in a group applies rules according to
|
||
which both sexes must take their respective spouses from different groups
|
||
(which is why there are at least three groups). Thus Levi-Strauss can dem-
|
||
onstrate that dualist organization never stands on its own in this kind of
|
||
society. On the contrary, it is a particularity of modern societies, or rather
|
||
State societies, to bring into their own duality machines that function as
|
||
such, and proceed simultaneously by biunivocal relationships and succes-
|
||
sively by binarized choices. Classes and sexes come in twos, and phenom-
|
||
ena of tripartition result from a transposition of the dual, not the reverse.
|
||
We have already encountered this, notably in the case of the Face machine,
|
||
which differs in this respect from primitive head machines. It seems that
|
||
modern societies elevated dual segmentarity to the level of a self-sufficient
|
||
organization. The question, therefore, is not whether the status of women,
|
||
or those on the bottom, is better or worse, but the type of organization from
|
||
which that status results.
|
||
2. Similarly, we may note that in primitive societies circular segmen-
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 211
|
||
|
||
tarity does not necessarily imply that the circles are concentric, or have the
|
||
same center. In a supple regime, centers already act as so many knots, eyes,
|
||
or black holes', but they do not all resonate together, they do not fall on the
|
||
same point, they do not converge in the same black hole. There is a multi-
|
||
plicity of animist eyes, each of which is assigned, for example, a particular
|
||
animal spirit (snake-spirit, woodpecker-spirit, cayman-spirit ...). Each
|
||
black hole is occupied by a different animal eye. Doubtless, we see opera-
|
||
tions of rigidification and centralization take shape here and there: all of
|
||
the centers must collect on a single circle, which itself has a single center.
|
||
The shaman draws lines between all the points or spirits, outlines a constel-
|
||
lation, a radiating set of roots tied to a central tree. This is the birth of a cen-
|
||
tralized power with an arborescent system to discipline the outgrowths of
|
||
the primitive rhizome.5 Here, the tree simultaneously plays the role of a
|
||
principle of dichotomy or binarity, and an axis of rotation. But the power of
|
||
the shaman is still entirely localized, strictly dependent upon a particular
|
||
segment, contingent upon drugs, and each point continues to emit inde-
|
||
pendent sequences. The same cannot be said of modern societies, or even
|
||
of States. Of course, the centralized is not opposed to the segmentary, and
|
||
the circles remain distinct. But they become concentric, definitively
|
||
arborified. The segmentarity becomes rigid, to the extent that all centers
|
||
resonate in, and all black holes fall on, a single point of accumulation that is
|
||
like a point of intersection somewhere behind the eyes. The face of the
|
||
father, teacher, colonel, boss, enter into redundancy, refer back to a center
|
||
of signifiance that moves across the various circles and passes back over all
|
||
of the segments. The supple microheads with animal facializations are
|
||
replaced by a macroface whose center is everywhere and circumference
|
||
nowhere. There are no longer n eyes in the sky, or in becomings-animal and
|
||
-vegetable, but a central computing eye scanning all of the radii. The cen-
|
||
tral State is constituted not by the abolition of circular segmentarity but by
|
||
a concentricity of distinct circles, or the organization of a resonance among
|
||
centers. There are already just as many power centers in primitive societies;
|
||
or, if one prefers, there are still just as many in State societies. The latter,
|
||
however, behave as apparatuses of resonance; they organize resonance,
|
||
whereas the former inhibit it.6
|
||
3. Finally, in the case of linear segmentarity, we would say that each seg-
|
||
ment is underscored, rectified, and homogenized in its own right, but also
|
||
in relation to the others. Not only does each have its own unit of measure,
|
||
but there is an equivalence and translatability between units. The central
|
||
eye has as its correlate a space through which it moves, but it itself remains
|
||
invariant in relation to its movements. With the Greek city-state and
|
||
Cleisthenes' reform, a homogeneous and isotopic space appears that
|
||
overcodes the lineal segments, at the same time as distinct focal points
|
||
212 O 1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
begin to resonate in a center acting as their common denominator.7 Paul
|
||
Virilio shows that after the Greek city-state, the Roman Empire imposes a
|
||
geometrical or linear reason of State including a general outline of camps
|
||
and fortifications, a universal art of "marking boundaries by lines," a
|
||
laying-out of territories, a substitution of space for places and territoriali-
|
||
ties, and a transformation of the world into the city; in short, an increas-
|
||
ingly rigid segmentarity.8 The segments, once underscored or overcoded,
|
||
seem to lose their ability to bud, they seem to lose their dynamic relation to
|
||
segmentations-in-progress, or in the act of coming together or coming
|
||
apart. If there exists a primitive "geometry" (a protogeometry), it is an
|
||
operative geometry in which figures are never separable from the affecta-
|
||
tions befalling them, the lines of their becoming, the segments of their seg-
|
||
mentation: there is "roundness," but no circle, "alignments," but no
|
||
straight line, etc. On the contrary, State geometry, or rather the bond
|
||
between the State and geometry, manifests itself in the primacy of the
|
||
theorem-element, which substitutes fixed or ideal essences for supple mor-
|
||
phological formations, properties for affects, predetermined segments for
|
||
segmentations-in-progress. Geometry and arithmetic take on the power of
|
||
the scalpel. Private property implies a space that has been overcoded and
|
||
gridded by surveying. Not only does each line have its segments, but the
|
||
segments of one line correspond to those of another; for example, the wage
|
||
regime establishes a correspondence between monetary segments, produc-
|
||
tion segments, and consumable-goods segments.
|
||
We may summarize the principal differences between rigid segmentarity
|
||
and supple segmentarity. In the rigid mode, binary segmentarity stands on
|
||
its own and is governed by great machines of direct binarization, whereas in
|
||
the other mode, binarities result from "multiplicities of n dimensions." Sec-
|
||
ond, circular segmentarity tends to become concentric, in other words,
|
||
causes all of its focal points to coincide in a single center that is in constant
|
||
movement but remains invariant through its movements, and is part of a
|
||
machine of resonance. Finally, linear segmentarity feeds into a machine of
|
||
overcoding that constitutes more geometrico homogeneous space and
|
||
extracts segments that are determinate as to their substance, form, and rela-
|
||
tions. It will be noted that this rigid segmentarity is always expressed by the
|
||
Tree. The Tree is the knot of arborescence or principle of dichotomy; it is the
|
||
axis of'rotation guaranteeing concentricity; it is the structure or network
|
||
gridding the possible. This opposition between arborified and rhizomatic
|
||
segmentarity is not just meant to indicate two states of a single process, but
|
||
also to isolate two different processes. For primitive societies operate essen-
|
||
tially by codes and territorialities. It is in fact the distinction between these
|
||
two elements, the tribal system of territories and the clan system of lineages,
|
||
that prevents resonance.9 Modern, or State, societies, on the other hand,
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 213
|
||
|
||
have replaced the declining codes with a univocal overcoding, and the lost
|
||
territories with a specific reterritorialization (which takes place in an
|
||
overcoded geometrical space). Segmentarity is always the result of an
|
||
abstract machine, but different abstract machines operate in the rigid and
|
||
the supple.
|
||
|
||
It is not enough, therefore, to oppose the centralized to the segmentary.
|
||
Nor is it enough to oppose two kinds of segmentarity, one supple and prim-
|
||
itive, the other modern and rigidified. There is indeed a distinction
|
||
between the two, but they are inseparable, they overlap, they are entangled.
|
||
Primitive societies have nuclei of rigidity or arborification that as much
|
||
anticipate the State as ward it off. Conversely, our societies are still suf-
|
||
fused by a supple fabric without which their rigid segments would not hold.
|
||
Supple segmentarity cannot be restricted to primitive peoples. It is not the
|
||
vestige of the savage within us but a perfectly contemporary function,
|
||
inseparable from the other. Every society, and every individual, are thus
|
||
plied by both segmentarities simultaneously: one molar, the other molecu-
|
||
lar. If they are distinct, it is because they do not have the same terms or the
|
||
same relations or the same nature or even the same type of multiplicity. If
|
||
they are inseparable, it is because they coexist and cross over into each
|
||
other. The configurations differ, for example, between the primitives and
|
||
us, but the two segmentarities are always in presupposition. In short, every-
|
||
thing is political, but every politics is simultaneously a macropolitics and a
|
||
micropolitics. Take aggregates of the perception or feeling type: their molar
|
||
organization, their rigid segmentarity, does not preclude the existence of
|
||
an entire world of unconscious micropercepts, unconscious affects, fine
|
||
segmentations that grasp or experience different things, are distributed
|
||
and operate differently. There is a micropolitics of perception, affection,
|
||
conversation, and so forth. If we consider the great binary aggregates, such
|
||
as the sexes or classes, it is evident that they also cross over into molecular
|
||
assemblages of a different nature, and that there is a double reciprocal
|
||
dependency between them. For the two sexes imply a multiplicity of molec-
|
||
ular combinations bringing into play not only the man in the woman and
|
||
the woman in the man, but the relation of each to the animal, the plant, etc.:
|
||
a thousand tiny sexes. And social classes themselves imply "masses" that
|
||
do not have the same kind of movement, distribution, or objectives and do
|
||
not wage the same kind of struggle. Attempts to distinguish mass from class
|
||
effectively tend toward this limit: the notion of mass is a molecular notion
|
||
operating according to a type of segmentation irreducible to the molar
|
||
segmentarity of class. Yet classes are indeed fashioned from masses; they
|
||
crystallize them. And masses are constantly flowing or leaking from
|
||
classes. Their reciprocal presupposition, however, does not preclude a dif-
|
||
214 D 1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
ference in viewpoint, nature, scale, and function (understood in this way,
|
||
the notion of mass has entirely different connotations than Canetti's
|
||
"crowd").
|
||
It is not sufficient to define bureaucracy by a rigid segmentarity with
|
||
compartmentalization of contiguous offices, an office manager in each
|
||
segment, and the corresponding centralization at the end of the hall or on
|
||
top of the tower. For at the same time there is a whole bureaucratic segmen-
|
||
tation, a suppleness of and communication between offices, a bureaucratic
|
||
perversion, a permanent inventiveness or creativity practiced even against
|
||
administrative regulations. If Kafka is the greatest theorist of bureaucracy,
|
||
it is because he shows how, at a certain level (but which one? it is not
|
||
localizable), the barriers between offices cease to be "a definite dividing
|
||
line" and are immersed in a molecular medium (milieu) that dissolves
|
||
them and simultaneously makes the office manager proliferate into
|
||
microfigures impossible to recognize or identify, discernible only when
|
||
they are centralizable: another regime, coexistent with the separation and
|
||
totalization of the rigid segments.I0 We would even say that fascism implies
|
||
a molecular regime that is distinct both from molar segments and their cen-
|
||
tralization. Doubtless, fascism invented the concept of the totalitarian
|
||
State, but there is no reason to define fascism by a concept of its own devis-
|
||
ing: there are totalitarian States, of the Stalinist or military dictatorship
|
||
type, that are not fascist. The concept of the totalitarian State applies only
|
||
at the macropolitical level, to a rigid segmentarity and a particular mode of
|
||
totalization and centralization. But fascism is inseparable from a prolifera-
|
||
tion of molecular focuses in interaction, which skip from point to point,
|
||
before beginning to resonate together in the National Socialist State. Rural
|
||
fascism and city or neighborhood fascism, youth fascism and war veteran's
|
||
fascism, fascism of the Left and fascism of the Right, fascism of the couple,
|
||
family, school, and office: every fascism is defined by a micro-black hole
|
||
that stands on its own and communicates with the others, before resonat-
|
||
ing in a great, generalized central black hole.1' There is fascism when a war
|
||
machine is installed in each hole, in every niche. Even after the National
|
||
Socialist State had been established, microfascisms persisted that gave it
|
||
unequaled ability to act upon the "masses." Daniel Guerin is correct to say
|
||
that if Hitler took power, rather then taking over the German State admin-
|
||
istration, it was because from the beginning he had at his disposal
|
||
microorganizations giving him "an unequaled, irreplaceable ability to
|
||
penetrate every cell of society," in other words, a molecular and supple
|
||
segmentarity, flows capable of suffusing every kind of cell. Conversely, if
|
||
capitalism came to consider the fascist experience as catastrophic, if it pre-
|
||
ferred to ally itself with Stalinist totalitarianism, which from its point of
|
||
view was much more sensible and manageable, it was because the
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 215
|
||
|
||
segmentarity and centralization of the latter was more classical and less
|
||
fluid. What makes fascism dangerous is its molecular or micropolitical
|
||
power, for it is a mass movement: a cancerous body rather than a totalitar-
|
||
ian organism. American film has often depicted these molecular focal
|
||
points; band, gang, sect, family, town, neighborhood, vehicle fascisms
|
||
spare no one. Only microfascism provides an answer to the global ques-
|
||
tion: Why does desire desire its own repression, how can it desire its own
|
||
repression? The masses certainly do not passively submit to power; nor do
|
||
they "want" to be repressed, in a kind of masochistic hysteria; nor are they
|
||
tricked by an ideological lure. Desire is never separable from complex
|
||
assemblages that necessarily tie into molecular levels, from microforma-
|
||
tions already shaping postures, attitudes, perceptions, expectations,
|
||
semiotic systems, etc. Desire is never an undifferentiated instinctual
|
||
energy, but itself results from a highly developed, engineered setup rich in
|
||
interactions: a whole supple segmentarity that processes molecular ener-
|
||
gies and potentially gives desire a fascist determination. Leftist organiza-
|
||
tions will not be the last to secrete microfascisms. It's too easy to be
|
||
antifascist on the molar level, and not even see the fascist inside you, the
|
||
fascist you yourself sustain and nourish and cherish with molecules both
|
||
personal and collective.
|
||
Four errors concerning this molecular and supple segmentarity are to be
|
||
avoided. The first is axiological and consists in believing that a little sup-
|
||
pleness is enough to make things "better." But microfascisms are what
|
||
make fascism so dangerous, and fine segmentations are as harmful as the
|
||
most rigid of segments. The second is psychological, as if the molecular
|
||
were in the realm of the imagination and applied only to the individual and
|
||
interindividual. But there is just as much social-Real on one line as on the
|
||
other. Third, the two forms are not simply distinguished by size, as a small
|
||
form and a large form; although it is true that the molecular works in detail
|
||
and operates in small groups, this does not mean that it is any less coexten-
|
||
sive with the entire social field than molar organization. Finally, the quali-
|
||
tative difference between the two lines does not preclude their boosting or
|
||
cutting into each other; there is always a proportional relation between the
|
||
two, directly or inversely proportional.
|
||
In the first case, the stronger the molar organization is, the more it
|
||
induces a molecularization of its own elements, relations, and elementary
|
||
apparatuses. When the machine becomes planetary or cosmic, there is an
|
||
increasing tendency for assemblages to miniaturize, to become micro-
|
||
assemblages. Following Andre Gorz's formula, the only remaining element
|
||
of work left under world capitalism is the molecular, or molecularized,
|
||
individual, in other words, the "mass" individual. The administration of a
|
||
great organized molar security has as its correlate a whole micro-
|
||
216 D 1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
management of petty fears, a permanent molecular insecurity, to the point
|
||
that the motto of domestic policymakers might be: a macropolitics of soci-
|
||
ety by and for a micropolitics of insecurity.12 However, the second case is
|
||
even more important: molecular movements do not complement but
|
||
rather thwart and break through the great worldwide organization. That is
|
||
what French President Valery Giscard d'Estaing was saying in his military
|
||
and political geography lesson: the more balanced things are between East
|
||
and West, in an overcoding and overarmed dualist machine, the more
|
||
"destabilized" they become along the other, North-South, line. There is
|
||
always a Palestinian or Basque or Corsican to bring about a "regional
|
||
destabilization of security."13 The two great molar aggregates of the East
|
||
and West are perpetually being undermined by a molecular segmentation
|
||
causing a zigzag crack, making it difficult for them to keep their own seg-
|
||
ments in line. It is as if a line of flight, perhaps only a tiny trickle to begin
|
||
with, leaked between the segments, escaping their centralization, eluding
|
||
their totalization. The profound movements stirring in a society present
|
||
themselves in this fashion, even if they are necessarily "represented" as a
|
||
confrontation between molar segments. It is wrongly said (in Marxism in
|
||
particular) that a society is defined by its contradictions. That is true only
|
||
on the larger scale of things. From the viewpoint of micropolitics, a society
|
||
is defined by its lines of flight, which are molecular. There is always some-
|
||
thing that flows or flees, that escapes the binary organizations, the reso-
|
||
nance apparatus, and the overcoding machine: things that are attributed to
|
||
a "change in values," the youth, women, the mad, etc. May 1968 in France
|
||
was molecular, making what led up to it all the more imperceptible from
|
||
the viewpoint of macropolitics. It happens that people who are very lim-
|
||
ited in outlook or are very old grasp the event better than the most
|
||
advanced politicians, or politicians who consider themselves advanced
|
||
from the viewpoint of organization. As Gabriel Tarde said, what one needs
|
||
to know is which peasants, in which areas of the south of France, stopped
|
||
greeting the local landowners. A very old, outdated landowner can in this
|
||
case judge things better than a modernist. It was the same with May '68:
|
||
those who evaluated things in macropolitical terms understood nothing of
|
||
the event because something unaccountable was escaping. The politicians,
|
||
the parties, the unions, many leftists, were utterly vexed; they kept repeat-
|
||
ing over and over again that "conditions" were not ripe. It was as though
|
||
they had been temporarily deprived of the entire dualism machine that
|
||
made them valid spokespeople. Bizarrely, de Gaulle, and even Pompidou,
|
||
understood much more than the others. A molecular flow was escaping,
|
||
minuscule at first, then swelling, without, however, ceasing to be
|
||
unassignable. The reverse, however, is also true: molecular escapes and
|
||
movements would be nothing if they did not return to the molar orga-
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 217
|
||
|
||
nizations to reshuffle their segments, their binary distributions of sexes,
|
||
classes, and parties.
|
||
The issue is that the molar and the molecular are distinguished not by
|
||
size, scale, or dimension but by the nature of the system of reference envi-
|
||
sioned. Perhaps, then, the words "line" and "segment" should be reserved
|
||
for molar organization, and other, more suitable, words should be sought
|
||
for molecular composition. And in fact, whenever we can identify a well-
|
||
defined segmented line, we notice that it continues in another form, as a
|
||
quantum flow. And in every instance, we can locate a "power center" at the
|
||
border between the two, defined not by an absolute exercise of power
|
||
within its domain but by the relative adaptations and conversions it effects
|
||
between the line and the flow. Take a monetary flow with segments. These
|
||
segments can be defined from several points of view, for example, from the
|
||
viewpoint of a corporate budget (real wages, net profit, management sala-
|
||
ries, interest on assets, reserves, investments, etc.). Now this line of
|
||
payment-money is linked to another aspect, namely, the flow of financing-
|
||
money, which has, not segments, but rather poles, singularities, and quanta
|
||
(the poles of the flow are the creation of money and its destruction; the sin-
|
||
gularities are nominal liquid assets; the quanta are inflation, deflation,
|
||
stagflation, etc.). This has led some to speak of a "mutant, convulsive, cre-
|
||
ative and circulatory flow" tied to desire and always subjacent to the solid
|
||
line and its segments determining interest rates and supply and demand.14
|
||
In a balance of payment, we again encounter a binary segmentarity that
|
||
distinguishes, for example, so-called autonomous operations from
|
||
so-called compensatory operations. But movements of capital do not allow
|
||
themselves to be segmented in this way; because they are "the most thor-
|
||
oughly broken down, according to their nature, duration, and the personal-
|
||
ity of the creditor or debtor," one "no longer has any idea where to draw the
|
||
line when dealing with these flows."15 Yet there is always a correlation
|
||
between the two aspects since linearization and segmentation are where
|
||
flows run dry, but are also their point of departure for a new creation. When
|
||
we talk about banking power, concentrated most notably in the central
|
||
banks, it is indeed a question of the relative power to regulate "as much as"
|
||
possible the communication, conversion, and coadaptation of the two
|
||
parts of the circuit. That is why power centers are defined much more by
|
||
what escapes them or by their impotence than by their zone of power. In
|
||
short, the molecular, or microeconomics, micropolitics, is defined not by
|
||
the smallness of its elements but by the nature of its "mass"—the quantum
|
||
flow as opposed to the molar segmented line.16 The task of making the seg-
|
||
ments correspond to the quanta, of adjusting the segments to the quanta,
|
||
implies hit-and-miss changes in rhythm and mode rather than any omnip-
|
||
otence; and something always escapes.
|
||
218 D 1933:MICROPOLITICSANDSEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
We could take other examples, such as the power of the Church. Church
|
||
power has always been associated with a certain administration of sin
|
||
possessing a strong segmentarity (the seven deadly sins), units of measure
|
||
(how many times?), and rules of equivalence and atonement (confession,
|
||
penance . . .). But there is also what might be called the molecular flow of
|
||
sinfulness, something quite different yet complementary: it hugs close to
|
||
the linear zone, as though negotiated through it, but itself has only poles
|
||
(original sin-redemption or grace) and quanta ("that sin which is the
|
||
default of consciousness of sin"; the sin of having a consciousness of sin;
|
||
the sin of the consequence of having a consciousness of sin).17 The same
|
||
could be said of a flow of criminality, in contrast to the molar line of a legal
|
||
code and its divisions. Or to take another example, discussions of military
|
||
power, or the power of the army, consider a segmentable line broken down
|
||
into types of war corresponding exactly to the States waging war and the
|
||
political goals those States assign themselves (from "limited" war to "total"
|
||
war). But following Clausewitz's intuition, the war machine is very differ-
|
||
ent; it is a flow of absolute war stretching between an offensive and a defen-
|
||
sive pole, and is marked only by quanta (psychic and material forces that
|
||
are like the nominal liquid assets of war). We may say of the pure flow that it
|
||
is abstract yet real; ideal yet effective; absolute yet "differentiated." It is
|
||
true that the flow and its quanta can be grasped only by virtue of indexes on
|
||
the segmented line, but conversely, that line and those indexes exist only by
|
||
virtue of the flow suffusing them. In every case, it is evident that the seg-
|
||
mented line (macropolitics) is immersed in and prolonged by quantum
|
||
flows (micropolitics) that continually reshuffle and stir up its segments.
|
||
|
||
A: flow and poles
|
||
a: quanta
|
||
b: line and segments
|
||
B: power center
|
||
(all of which constitutes a
|
||
cycle or period)
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
In homage to Gabriel Tarde (1843-1904): his long-forgotton work has
|
||
assumed new relevance with the influence of American sociology, in par-
|
||
ticular microsociology. It had been quashed by Durkheim and his school
|
||
(in polemics similar to and as harsh as Cuvier's against Geoffrey Saint-
|
||
Hilaire). Durkheim's preferred objects of study were the great collective
|
||
representations, which are generally binary, resonant, and overcoded.
|
||
Tarde countered that collective representations presuppose exactly what
|
||
needs explaining, namely, "the similarity of millions of people." That is
|
||
why Tarde was interested instead in the world of detail, or of the infini-
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 219
|
||
|
||
tesimal: the little imitations, oppositions, and inventions constituting an
|
||
entire realm of subrepresentative matter. Tarde's best work was his analy-
|
||
ses of a minuscule bureaucratic innovation, or a linguistic innovation, etc.
|
||
The Durkheimians answered that what Tarde did was psychology or inter-
|
||
psychology, not sociology. But that is true only in appearance, as a first
|
||
approximation: a microimitation does seem to occur between two individ-
|
||
uals. But at the same time, and at a deeper level, it has to do not with an
|
||
individual but with a flow or a wave. Imitation is the propagation of a flow;
|
||
opposition is binarization, the making binary of flows; invention is a conju-
|
||
gation or connection of different flows. What, according to Tarde, is a flow?
|
||
It is belief or desire (the two aspects of every assemblage); a flow is always of
|
||
belief and of desire. Beliefs and desires are the basis of every society,
|
||
because they are flows and as such are "quantifiable"; they are veritable
|
||
social Quantities, whereas sensations are qualitative and representations
|
||
are simple resultants.18 Infinitesimal imitation, opposition, and invention
|
||
are therefore like flow quanta marking a propagation, binarization, or con-
|
||
jugation of beliefs and desires. Hence the importance of statistics, provid-
|
||
ing it concerns itself with the cutting edges and not only with the
|
||
"stationary" zone of representations. For in the end, the difference is not at
|
||
all between the social and the individual (or interindividual), but between
|
||
the molar realm of representations, individual or collective, and the molec-
|
||
ular realm of beliefs and desires in which the distinction between the social
|
||
and the individual loses all meaning since flows are neither attributable to
|
||
individuals nor overcodable by collective signifiers. Representations
|
||
already define large-scale aggregates, or determine segments on a line;
|
||
beliefs and desires, on the other hand, are flows marked by quanta, flows
|
||
that are created, exhausted, or transformed, added to one another, sub-
|
||
tracted or combined. Tarde invented microsociology and took it to its full
|
||
breadth and scope, denouncing in advance the misinterpretations to which
|
||
it would later fall victim.
|
||
This is how you tell the difference between the segmented line and the
|
||
quantum flow. A mutant flow always implies something tending to elude or
|
||
escape the codes; quanta are precisely signs or degrees of deterrito-
|
||
rialization in the decoded flow. The rigid line, on the other hand, implies
|
||
an overcoding that substitutes itself for the faltering codes; its segments are
|
||
like reterritorializations on the overcoding or overcoded line. Let us return
|
||
to the case of original sin: it is the very act of a flow marking a decoding in
|
||
relation to creation (with just one last island preserved for the Virgin), and
|
||
a deterritorialization in relation to the land of Adam; but it simultaneously
|
||
performs an overcoding by binary organizations and resonance (Powers,
|
||
Church, empires, rich-poor, men-women, etc.) and complementary reter-
|
||
ritorializations (on the land of Cain, on work, on reproduction, on
|
||
220 D 1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
money.. .)• Now the two systems of reference are in inverse relation to
|
||
each other, in the sense that the first eludes the second, or the second arrests
|
||
the first, prevents it from flowing further; but at the same time, they are
|
||
strictly complementary and coexistent, because one exists only as a func-
|
||
tion of the other; yet they are different and in direct relation to each
|
||
other, although corresponding term by term, because the second only
|
||
effectively arrests the first on a "plane" that is not the plane specific to the
|
||
first, while the momentum of the first continues on its own plane.
|
||
A social field is always animated by all kinds of movements of decoding
|
||
and deterritorialization affecting "masses" and operating at different
|
||
speeds and paces. These are not contradictions but escapes. At this level,
|
||
everything is a question of mass. For example, from the tenth to the four-
|
||
teenth centuries we see an acceleration of factors of decoding and deterri-
|
||
torialization: the masses of the last invaders swooping down from north,
|
||
east, and south; military masses turned into pillaging bands; ecclesiastical
|
||
masses confronted with infidels and heretics, and adopting increasingly
|
||
deterritorialized objectives; peasant masses leaving the seigneurial do-
|
||
mains; seigneurial masses forced to find means of exploitation less terri-
|
||
torial than serfdom; urban masses breaking away from the backcountry
|
||
and finding increasingly less territorialized social arrangements in the cit-
|
||
ies; women's masses detaching themselves from the old passional and con-
|
||
jugal code; monetary masses that cease to be a hoard object and inject
|
||
themselves into great commercial circuits.19 We may cite the Crusades as
|
||
effecting a connection of flows, each boosting and accelerating the others
|
||
(even the flow of femininity in the "faraway Princess," even the flow of chil-
|
||
dren in the Crusades of the thirteenth century). But at the same time, and
|
||
inseparably, there occur overcodings and reterritorializations. The Cru-
|
||
sades were overcoded by the pope and assigned territorial objectives. The
|
||
Holy Land, the Peace of God, a new type of abbey, new figures of money,
|
||
new modes of exploitation of the peasant through leasehold and the wage
|
||
system (or revivals of slavery), urban reterritorializations, etc., form a
|
||
complex system. At this point, we must introduce a distinction between the
|
||
two notions of connection and conjugation of flows. "Connection" indi-
|
||
cates the way in which decoded and deterritorialized flows boost one
|
||
another, accelerate their shared escape, and augment or stoke their quanta;
|
||
the "conjugation" of these same flows, on the other hand, indicates their
|
||
relative stoppage, like a point of accumulation that plugs or seals the lines
|
||
of flight, performs a general reterritorialization, and brings the flows under
|
||
the dominance of a single flow capable of overcoding them. But it is pre-
|
||
cisely the most deterritorialized flow, under the first aspect, that always
|
||
brings about the accumulation or conjunction of the processes, determines
|
||
the overcoding, and serves as the basis for reterritorialization under the
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 221
|
||
|
||
second aspect (we have already encountered a theorem according to which
|
||
it is always on the most deterritorialized element that reterritorialization
|
||
takes place). For example, the merchant bourgeoisie of the cities conju-
|
||
gated or capitalized a domain of knowledge, a technology, assemblages and
|
||
circuits into whose dependency the nobility, Church, artisans, and even
|
||
peasants would enter. It is precisely because the bourgeoisie was a cutting
|
||
edge of deterritorialization, a veritable particle accelerator, that it also per-
|
||
formed an overall reterritorialization.
|
||
The task of the historian is to designate the "period" of coexistence or
|
||
simultaneity of these two movements (decoding-deterritorialization and
|
||
overcoding-reterritorialization). For the duration of this period, one distin-
|
||
guishes between the molecular aspect and the molar aspect: on the one hand,
|
||
masses or flows, with their mutations, quanta of deterritorialization, con-
|
||
nections, and accelerations; on the other hand, classes or segments, with
|
||
their binary organization, resonance, conjunction or accumulation, and line
|
||
of overcoding favoring one line over the others.20 The difference between
|
||
macrohistory and microhistory has nothing to do with the length of the
|
||
durations envisioned, long or short, but rather concerns distinct systems of
|
||
reference, depending on whether it is an overcoded segmented line that is
|
||
under consideration or the mutant quantum flow. The rigid system does not
|
||
bring the other system to a halt: the flow continues beneath the line, forever
|
||
mutant, while the line totalizes. Mass and class do not have the same con-
|
||
tours or the same dynamic, even though the same group can be assigned both
|
||
signs. The bourgeoisie considered as a mass and as a class... The relations
|
||
of a mass to other masses are not the same as the relations of the "corre-
|
||
sponding" class to the other classes. Of course, there are just as many rela-
|
||
tions offeree, and just as much violence, on one side as the other. The point
|
||
is that the same struggle assumes two very different aspects, in relation to
|
||
which the victories and defeats differ. Mass movements accelerate and feed
|
||
into one another (or dim for a long while, enter long stupors), but jump from
|
||
one class to another, undergo mutation, emanate or emit new quanta that
|
||
then modify class relations, bring their overcoding and reterritorialization
|
||
into question, and run new lines of flight in new directions. Beneath the self-
|
||
reproduction of classes, there is always a variable map of masses. Politics
|
||
operates by macrodecisions and binary choices, binarized interests; but the
|
||
realm of the decidable remains very slim. Political decision making neces-
|
||
sarily descends into a world of microdeterminations, attractions, and
|
||
desires, which it must sound out or evaluate in a different fashion. Beneath
|
||
linear conceptions and segmentary decisions, an evaluation of flows and
|
||
their quanta. A curious passage by Michelet reproaches Fra^ois I for having
|
||
badly evaluated the flow of emigration bringing to France large numbers of
|
||
people in struggle against the Church: Francois saw it only as an influx of
|
||
222 D 1933:MICROPOLITICSANDSEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
potential soldiers, instead of perceiving a mass molecular flow which France
|
||
could have used to its own advantage by leading a different Reformation
|
||
than the one that occurred.21 Problems are always like this. Good or bad, pol-
|
||
itics and its judgments are always molar, but it is the molecular and its assess-
|
||
ment that makes it or breaks it.
|
||
|
||
Now we are in a better position to draw a map. If we return to a very gen-
|
||
eral sense of the word "line," we see that there are not just two kinds of lines
|
||
but three. First, a relatively supple line of interlaced codes and territoriali-
|
||
ties; that is why we started with so-called primitive segmentarity, in which
|
||
the social space is constituted by territorial and lineal segmentations. Sec-
|
||
ond, a rigid line, which brings about a dualist organization of segments, a
|
||
concentricity of circles in resonance, and generalized overcoding; here, the
|
||
social space implies a State apparatus. This system is different from the
|
||
primitive system precisely because overcoding is not a stronger code, but a
|
||
specific procedure different from that of codes (similarly, reterrito-
|
||
rialization is not an added territory, but takes place in a different space
|
||
than that of territories, namely, overcoded geometrical space). Third, one
|
||
or several lines of flight, marked by quanta and defined by decoding and
|
||
deterritorialization (there is always something like a war machine func-
|
||
tioning on these lines).
|
||
This way of presenting things still has the disadvantage of making it
|
||
seem as though primitive societies came first. In truth, codes are never sep-
|
||
arable from the movement of decoding, nor are territories from the vectors
|
||
of deterritorialization traversing them. And overcoding and reterrito-
|
||
rialization do not come after. It would be more accurate to say that there is a
|
||
space in which the three kinds of closely intermingled lines coexist, tribes,
|
||
empires, and war machines. We could also put it this way: lines of flight are
|
||
primary, or the already-rigid segments are, and supple segmentations
|
||
swing between the two. Take a proposition like the following one by the his-
|
||
torian Pirenne about barbarian tribes: "The Barbarians did not spontane-
|
||
ously hurl themselves upon the Empire. They were pushed forward by the
|
||
flood of the Hunnish advance, which in this way caused the whole series of
|
||
invasions."22 On one side, we have the rigid segmentarity of the Roman
|
||
Empire, with its center of resonance and periphery, its State, its pax
|
||
romana, its geometry, its camps, its limes (boundary lines). Then, on the
|
||
horizon, there is an entirely different kind of line, the line of the nomads
|
||
who come in off the steppes, venture a fluid and active escape, sow deterri-
|
||
torialization everywhere, launch flows whose quanta heat up and are swept
|
||
along by a Stateless war machine. The migrant barbarians are indeed
|
||
between the two: they come and go, cross and recross frontiers, pillage and
|
||
ransom, but also integrate themselves and reterritorialize. At times they
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 223
|
||
|
||
will subside into the empire, assigning themselves a segment of it, becom-
|
||
ing mercenaries or confederates, settling down, occupying land or carving
|
||
out their own State (the wise Visigoths). At other times, they will go over to
|
||
the nomads, allying with them, becoming indiscernible (the brilliant
|
||
Ostrogoths). Perhaps because they were constantly being defeated by the
|
||
Huns and Visigoths, the Vandals ("zone-two Goths") drew a line of flight
|
||
that made them as strong as their masters; they were the only band or mass
|
||
to cross the Mediterranean. But they were also the ones who produced the
|
||
most startling reterritorialization: an empire in Africa. 23 Thus it seems that
|
||
the three lines do not only coexist, but transform themselves into one
|
||
another, cross over into one another. Again, we have taken a summary
|
||
example in which the lines are illustrated by different groups. What we
|
||
have said applies all the more to cases in which all of the lines are in a single
|
||
group, a single individual.
|
||
In view of this, it would be better to talk about simultaneous states of the
|
||
abstract Machine. There is on the one hand an abstract machine of
|
||
overcoding: it defines a rigid segmentarity, a macrosegmentarity, because it
|
||
produces or rather reproduces segments, opposing them two by two, mak-
|
||
ing all the centers resonate, and laying out a divisible, homogeneous space
|
||
striated in all directions. This kind of abstract machine is linked to the
|
||
State apparatus. We do not, however, equate it with the State apparatus
|
||
itself. The abstract machine may be defined, for example, more geomet-
|
||
rico, or under other conditions by an "axiomatic"; but the State apparatus
|
||
is neither geometry nor axiomatics: it is only the assemblage of
|
||
reterritorialization effectuating the overcoding machine within given lim-
|
||
its and under given conditions. The most we can say is that the State appa-
|
||
ratus tends increasingly to identify with the abstract machine it effectu-
|
||
ates. This is where the notion of the totalitarian State becomes meaningful:
|
||
a State becomes totalitarian when, instead of effectuating, within its own
|
||
limits, the worldwide overcoding machine, it identifies with it, creating the
|
||
conditions for "autarky," producing a reterritorialization by "closed ves-
|
||
sel," in the artifice of the void (this is never an ideological operation, but
|
||
rather an economic and political one).24
|
||
On the other hand, at the other pole, there is an abstract machine of
|
||
mutation, which operates by decoding and deterritorialization. It is what
|
||
draws the lines of flight: it steers the quantum flows, assures the connec-
|
||
tion-creation of flows, and emits new quanta. It itself is in a state of flight,
|
||
and erects war machines on its lines. If it constitutes another pole, it is
|
||
because molar or rigid segments always seal, plug, block the lines of flight,
|
||
whereas this machine is always making them flow, "between" the rigid seg-
|
||
ments and in another, submolecular, direction. But between the two poles
|
||
there is also a whole realm of properly molecular negotiation, translation,
|
||
224 D 1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
and transduction in which at times molar lines are already undermined by
|
||
fissures and cracks, and at other times lines of flight are already drawn
|
||
toward black holes, flow connections are already replaced by limitative
|
||
conjunctions, and quanta emissions are already converted into center-
|
||
points. All of this happens at the same time. It is at the same time that lines
|
||
of flight connect and continue their intensities, whip particles-signs out of
|
||
black holes; and also retreat into the swirl of micro-black holes or mo-
|
||
lecular conjunctions that interrupt them; or again, enter overcoded,
|
||
concentricized, binarized, stable segments arrayed around a central black
|
||
hole.
|
||
What is a center or focal point ofpowerl Answering this question will
|
||
illustrate the entanglement of the lines. We speak of the power of the army,
|
||
Church, and school, of public and private power . . . Power centers obvi-
|
||
ously involve rigid segments. Each molar segment has one or more centers.
|
||
It might be objected that the segments themselves presuppose a power cen-
|
||
ter, as what distinguishes and unites them, sets them in opposition and
|
||
makes them resonate. But there is no contradiction between the segmfpn-
|
||
tary parts and the centralized apparatus. On the one hand, the most rigid of
|
||
segmentarities does not preclude centralization: this is because the com-
|
||
mon central point is not where all the other points melt together, but
|
||
instead acts as a point of resonance on the horizon, behind all the other
|
||
points. The State is not a point taking all the others upon itself, but a reso-
|
||
nance chamber for them all. Even when the State is totalitarian, its func-
|
||
tion as resonator for distinct centers and segments remains unchanged: the
|
||
only difference is that it takes place under closed-vessel conditions that
|
||
increase its internal reach, or couples "resonance" with a "forced move-
|
||
ment." On the other hand, and conversely, the strictest of centralizations
|
||
does not eradicate the distinctiveness of the centers, segments, and circles.
|
||
When the overcoding line is drawn, it assures the prevalence of one seg-
|
||
ment, as such, over the other (in the case of binary segmentarity), gives a
|
||
certain center a power of relative resonance over the others (in the case of
|
||
circular segmentarity), and underscores the dominant segment through
|
||
which it itself passes (in the case of linear segmentarity). Thus centraliza-
|
||
tion is always hierarchical, but hierarchy is always segmentary.
|
||
Each power center is also molecular and exercises its power on a
|
||
micrological fabric in which it exists only as diffuse, dispersed, geared
|
||
down, miniaturized, perpetually displaced, acting by fine segmentation,
|
||
working in detail and in the details of detail. Foucault's analysis of "disci-
|
||
plines" or micropowers (school, army, factory, hospital, etc.) testifies to
|
||
these "focuses of instability" where groupings and accumulations confront
|
||
each other, but also confront breakaways and escapes, and where inver-
|
||
sions occur.25 What we have is no longer The Schoolmaster but the monitor,
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 225
|
||
|
||
the best student, the class dunce, the janitor, etc. No longer the general, but
|
||
the junior officers, the noncommissioned officers, the soldier inside me,
|
||
and also the malcontent: all have their own tendencies, poles, conflicts, and
|
||
relations offeree. Even the warrant officer and janitor are only invoked for
|
||
explanatory purposes; for they have a molar side and a molecular side, and
|
||
make us realize that the general or the landlord also had both sides all
|
||
along. We would not say that the proper name loses its power when it enters
|
||
these zones of indiscernibility, but that it takes on a new kind of power. To
|
||
talk like Kafka, what we have is no longer the public official Klamm, but
|
||
maybe his secretary Momus, or other molecular Klamms the differences
|
||
between which, and with Klamm, are all the greater for no longer being
|
||
assignable. ("[The officials] don't always stick to the same book, yet it isn't
|
||
the books they change, but their places, and [they] have to squeeze past one
|
||
another when they change places, because there's so little room." "This
|
||
official is rarely very like Klamm, and if he were sitting in his own office at
|
||
his own desk with his name on the door I would have no more doubt at
|
||
all,"26 says Barnabas, whose dream would be a uniquely molar segmen-
|
||
tarity, no matter how rigid and horrendous, as the only guarantee of cer-
|
||
tainty and security. But he cannot but notice that the molar segments are
|
||
necessarily immersed in the molecular soup that nourishes them and
|
||
makes their outlines waver.) And every power center has this microtexture.
|
||
The microtextures—not masochism—are what explain how the oppressed
|
||
can take an active role in oppression: the workers of the rich nations
|
||
actively participate in the exploitation of the Third World, the arming of
|
||
dictatorships, and the pollution of the atmosphere.
|
||
This is not surprising since the texture lies between the line of
|
||
overcoding with rigid segments and the ultimate quantum line. It continu-
|
||
ally swings between the two, now channeling the quantum line back into
|
||
the segmented line, now causing flows and quanta to escape from the seg-
|
||
mented line. This is the third aspect of power centers, or their limit. For the
|
||
only purpose these centers have is to translate as best they can flow quanta
|
||
into line segments (only segments are totalizable, in one way or another).
|
||
But this is both the principle of their power and the basis of their impo-
|
||
tence. Far from being opposites, power and impotence complement and
|
||
reinforce each other in a kind of fascinating satisfaction that is found above
|
||
all in the most mediocre Statesmen, and defines their "glory." For they
|
||
extract glory from their shortsightedness, and power from their impotence,
|
||
because it confirms that there is no choice. The only "great" Statesmen are
|
||
those who connect with flows, like pilot-signs or particles-signs, and who
|
||
emit quanta that get out of the black holes: it is not by chance that these
|
||
men encounter each other only on lines of flight, in the act of drawing
|
||
them, sounding them out, following them, or forging ahead of them, even
|
||
226 D 1933:MICROPOLITICSANDSEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
though they may make a mistake and take a fall (Moses the Hebrew,
|
||
Genseric the Vandal, Genghis the Mongol, Mao the Chinese . . .)-But there
|
||
is no Power regulating the flows themselves. No one dominates the growth
|
||
of the "monetary mass," or money supply. If an image of the master or an
|
||
idea of the State is projected outward to the limits of the universe, as if
|
||
something had domination over flows as well as segments, and in the same
|
||
manner, the result is a fictitious and ridiculous representation. The stock
|
||
exchange gives a better image of flows and their quanta than does the State.
|
||
Capitalists may be the masters of surplus value and its distribution, but
|
||
they do not dominate the flows from which surplus value derives. Rather,
|
||
power centers function at the points where flows are converted into seg-
|
||
ments: they are exchangers, converters, oscillators. Not that the segments
|
||
themselves are governed by a decision-making power. We have seen, on the
|
||
contrary, that segments (classes, for example) form at the conjunction of
|
||
masses and deterritorialized flows and that the most deterritorialized flow
|
||
determines the dominant segment; thus the dollar segment dominates cur-
|
||
rency, the bourgeoisie dominates capitalism, etc. Segments, then, are
|
||
themselves governed by an abstract machine. But what power centers gov-
|
||
ern are the assemblages that effectuate that abstract machine, in other
|
||
words, that continually adapt variations in mass and flow to the segments
|
||
of the rigid line, as a function of a dominant segment and dominated seg-
|
||
ments. Much perverse invention can enter into the adaptations.
|
||
This is the sense in which we would speak, for example, of banking
|
||
power (the World Bank, central banks, credit banks): if the flow of
|
||
financing-money, or credit money, involves the mass of economic transac-
|
||
tions, what banks govern is the conversion of the credit money that has
|
||
been created into segmentary payment-money that is appropriated, in
|
||
other words, coinage or State money for the purchase of goods that are
|
||
themselves segmented (the importance of the interest rate in this respect).
|
||
What banks govern is the conversion between the two kinds of money, and
|
||
the conversion of the segments of the second kind into any given good.27
|
||
The same could be said of every central power. Every central power has
|
||
three aspects or zones: (1) its zone of power, relating to the segments of a
|
||
solid rigid line; (2) its zone of indiscernibility, relating to its diffusion
|
||
throughout a microphysical fabric; (3) its zone of impotence, relatingto the
|
||
flows and quanta it can only convert without being able to control or
|
||
define. It is always from the depths of its impotence that each power center
|
||
draws its power, hence their extreme maliciousness, and vanity. Better to
|
||
be a tiny quantum flow than a molar converter, oscillator, or distributor!
|
||
Returning to the example of money, the first zone is represented by the
|
||
public central banks; the second by the "indefinite series of private rela-
|
||
tions between banks and borrowers"; the third by the desiring flow of
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 227
|
||
|
||
money, whose quanta are defined by the mass of economic transactions. It
|
||
is true that the same problems are reformulated at the level of these very
|
||
transactions, in relation to other power centers. But the first zone of the
|
||
power center is always defined by the State apparatus, which is the assem-
|
||
blage that effectuates the abstract machine of molar overcoding; the sec-
|
||
ond is defined in the molecular fabric immersing this assemblage; the third
|
||
by the abstract machine of mutation, flows, and quanta.
|
||
|
||
We cannot say that one of these three lines is bad and another good, by
|
||
nature and necessarily. The study of the dangers of each line is the object of
|
||
pragmatics or schizoanalysis, to the extent that it undertakes not to repre-
|
||
sent, interpret, or symbolize, but only to make maps and draw lines, mark-
|
||
ing their mixtures as well as their distinctions. According to Nietzsche's
|
||
Zarathustra and Castaneda's Indian Don Juan, there are three or even four
|
||
dangers: first, Fear, then Clarity, then Power, and finally the great Disgust,
|
||
the longing to kill and to die, the Passion for abolition.28 We can guess what
|
||
fear is. We are always afraid of losing. Our security, the great molar organi-
|
||
zation that sustains us, the arborescences we cling to, the binary machines
|
||
that give us a well-defined status, the resonances we enter into, the system
|
||
of overcoding that dominates us—we desire all that. "The values, morals,
|
||
fatherlands, religions and private certitudes our vanity and self-compla-
|
||
cency generously grant us are so many abodes the world furnishes for those
|
||
who think on that account that they stand and rest amid stable things; they
|
||
know nothing of the enormous rout they are heading f o r . . . in flight from
|
||
flight."™ We flee from flight, rigidify our segments, give ourselves over to
|
||
binary logic; the harder they have been to us on one segment, the harder we
|
||
will be on another; we reterritorialize on anything available; the only
|
||
segmentarity we know is molar, at the level of the large-scale aggregates we
|
||
belong to, as well as at the level of the little groups we get into, as well as at
|
||
the level of what goes on in our most intimate and private recesses. Every-
|
||
thing is involved: modes of perception, kinds of actions, ways of moving,
|
||
life-styles, semiotic regimes. A man comes home and says, "Is the grub
|
||
ready?", and the wife answers, "What a scowl! Are you in a bad mood?":
|
||
two rigid segments in confrontation. The more rigid the segmentarity, the
|
||
more reassuring it is for us. That is what fear is, and how it makes us retreat
|
||
into the first line.
|
||
The second danger, Clarity, seems less obvious. Clarity, in effect, con-
|
||
cerns the molecular. Once again, everything is involved, even perception,
|
||
even the semiotic regime, but this time on the second line. Castaneda illus-
|
||
trates, for example, the existence of a molecular perception to which drugs
|
||
give us access (but so many things can be drugs): we attain a visual and
|
||
sonorous microperception revealing spaces and voids, like holes in the
|
||
228 D 1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
molar structure. That is precisely what clarity is: the distinctions that
|
||
appear in what used to seem full, the holes in what used to be compact; and
|
||
conversely, where just before we saw end points of clear-cut segments, now
|
||
there are indistinct fringes, encroachments, overlappings, migrations, acts
|
||
of segmentation that no longer coincide with the rigid segmentarity. Every-
|
||
thing now appears supple, with holes in fullness, nebulas in forms, and flut-
|
||
ter in lines. Everything has the clarity of the microscope. We think we have
|
||
understood everything, and draw conclusions. We are the new knights; we
|
||
even have a mission. A microphysics of the migrant has replaced the
|
||
macrogeometry of the sedentary. But this suppleness and clarity do not
|
||
only present dangers, they are themselves a danger. First, supple segmen-
|
||
tarity runs the risk of reproducing in miniature the affections, the affecta-
|
||
tions, of the rigid: the family is replaced by a community, conjugality by a
|
||
regime of exchange and migration; worse, micro-Oedipuses crop up,
|
||
microfascisms lay down the law, the mother feels obliged to titillate her
|
||
child, the father becomes a mommy. A dark light that falls from no star and
|
||
emanates such sadness: this shifting segmentarity derives directly from the
|
||
most rigid, for which it is indirect compensation. The more molar the
|
||
aggregates become, the more molecular become their elements and the
|
||
relations between their elements: molecular man for molar humanity. One
|
||
deterritorializes, massifies, but only in order to knot and annul the mass
|
||
movements and movements of deterritorialization, to invent all kinds of
|
||
marginal reterritorializations even worse than the others. But above all,
|
||
supple segmentarity brings dangers of its own that do not merely reproduce
|
||
in small scale the dangers of molar segmentarity, which do not derive from
|
||
them or compensate for them. As we have seen, microfascisms have a spe-
|
||
cificity of their own that can crystallize into a macro fascism, but may also
|
||
float along the supple line on their own account and suffuse every little cell.
|
||
A multitude of black holes may very well not become centralized, and acts
|
||
instead as viruses adapting to the most varied situations, sinking voids in
|
||
molecular perceptions and semiotics. Interactions without resonance.
|
||
Instead of the great paranoid fear, we are trapped in a thousand little mono-
|
||
manias, self-evident truths, and clarities that gush from every black hole
|
||
and no longer form a system, but are only rumble and buzz, blinding lights
|
||
giving any and everybody the mission of self-appointed judge, dispenser of
|
||
justice, policeman, neighborhood SS man. We have overcome fear, we have
|
||
sailed from the shores of security, only to enter a system that is no less
|
||
concentricized, no less organized: the system of petty insecurities that
|
||
leads everyone to their own black hole in which to turn dangerous, possess-
|
||
ing a clarity on their situation, role, and mission even more disturbing than
|
||
the certitudes of the first line.
|
||
Power (Pouvoir) is the third danger, because it is on both lines simultane-
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 229
|
||
|
||
ously. It stretches from the rigid segments with their overcoding and reso-
|
||
nance to the fine segmentations with their diffusion and interactions, and
|
||
back again. Every man of power jumps from one line to the other, alternat-
|
||
ing between a petty and a lofty style, the rogue's style and the grandiloquent
|
||
style, drugstore demagoguery and the imperialism of the high-ranking gov-
|
||
ernment man. But this whole chain and web of power is immersed in a
|
||
world of mutant flows that eludes them. It is precisely its impotence that
|
||
makes power so dangerous. The man of power will always want to stop the
|
||
lines of flight, and to this end to trap and stabilize the mutation machine in
|
||
the overcoding machine. But he can do so only by creating a void, in other
|
||
words, by first stabilizing the overcoding machine itself by containing it
|
||
within the local assemblage charged with effectuating it, in short, by giving
|
||
the assemblage the dimensions of the machine. This is what takes place in
|
||
the artificial conditions of totalitarianism or the "closed vessel."
|
||
But there is a fourth danger as well, and this is the one that interests us
|
||
most, because it concerns the lines of flight themselves. We may well have
|
||
presented these lines as a sort of mutation or creation drawn not only in the
|
||
imagination but also in the very fabric of social reality; we may well have
|
||
attributed to them the movement of the arrow and the speed of an
|
||
absolute—but it would be oversimplifying to believe that the only risk they
|
||
fear and confront is allowing themselves to be recaptured in the end, letting
|
||
themselves be sealed in, tied up, reknotted, reterritorialized. They them-
|
||
selves emanate a strange despair, like an odor of death and immolation, a
|
||
state of war from which one returns broken: they have their own dangers
|
||
distinct from the ones previously discussed. This is exactly what led
|
||
Fitzgerald to say: "I had a feeling that I was standing at twilight on a
|
||
deserted range, with an empty rifle in my hands and the targets down. No
|
||
problem set—simply a silence with only the sound of my own breathing.
|
||
. . . My self-immolation was something sodden-dark."30 Why is the line of
|
||
flight a war one risks coming back from defeated, destroyed, after having
|
||
destroyed everything one could? This, precisely, is the fourth danger: the
|
||
line of flight crossing the wall, getting out of the black holes, but instead of
|
||
connecting with other lines and each time augmenting its valence, turning
|
||
to destruction, abolition pure and simple, the passion of abolition. Like
|
||
Kleist's line of flight, and the strange war he wages; like suicide, double sui-
|
||
cide, a way out that turns the line of flight into a line of death.
|
||
We are not invoking any kind of death drive. There are no internal
|
||
drives in desire, only assemblages. Desire is always assembled; it is what
|
||
the assemblage determines it to be. The assemblage that draws lines of
|
||
flight is on the same level as they are, and is of the war machine type. Muta-
|
||
tions spring from this machine, which in no way has war as its object, but
|
||
rather the emission of quanta of deterritorialization, the passage of mutant
|
||
230 D 1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY
|
||
|
||
flows (in this sense, every creation is brought about by a war machine).
|
||
There are many reasons to believe that the war machine is of a different ori-
|
||
gin, is a different assemblage, than the State apparatus. It is of nomadic ori-
|
||
gin and is directed against the State apparatus. One of the fundamental
|
||
problems of the State is to appropriate this war machine that is foreign to it
|
||
and make it a piece in its apparatus, in the form of a stable military institu-
|
||
tion; and the State has always encountered major difficulties in this. It is
|
||
precisely when the war machine has reached the point that it has no other
|
||
object but war, it is when it substitutes destruction for mutation, that it
|
||
frees the most catastrophic charge. Mutation is in no way a transformation
|
||
of war; on the contrary, war is like the fall or failure of mutation, the only
|
||
object left for the war machine after it has lost its power to change. War, it
|
||
must be said, is only the abominable residue of the war machine, either
|
||
after it has allowed itself to be appropriated by the State apparatus, or even
|
||
worse, has constructed itself a State apparatus capable only of destruction.
|
||
When this happens, the war machine no longer draws mutant lines of
|
||
flight, but a pure, cold line of abolition. (Later, we will propose a theory of
|
||
the complex relation between the war machine and war.)31
|
||
This brings us back to the paradox of fascism, and the way in which fas-
|
||
cism differs from totalitarianism. For totalitarianism is a State affair: it
|
||
essentially concerns the relation between the State as a localized assem-
|
||
blage and the abstract machine of overcoding it effectuates. Even in the
|
||
case of a military dictatorship, it is a State army, not a war machine, that
|
||
takes power and elevates the State to the totalitarian stage. Totalitarianism
|
||
is quintessentially conservative. Fascism, on the other hand, involves a war
|
||
machine. When fascism builds itself a totalitarian State, it is not in the
|
||
sense of a State army taking power, but of a war machine taking over the
|
||
State. A bizarre remark by Virilio puts us on the trail: in fascism, the State
|
||
is far less totalitarian than it is suicidal. There is in fascism a realized nihil-
|
||
ism. Unlike the totalitarian State, which does its utmost to seal all possible
|
||
lines of flight, fascism is constructed on an intense line of flight, which it
|
||
transforms into a line of pure destruction and abolition. It is curious that
|
||
from the very beginning the Nazis announced to Germany what they were
|
||
bringing: at once wedding bells and death, including their own death, and
|
||
the death of the Germans. They thought they would perish but that their
|
||
undertaking would be resumed, all across Europe, all over the world,
|
||
throughout the solar system. And the people cheered, not because they did
|
||
not understand, but because they wanted that death through the death of
|
||
others. Like a will to wager everything you have every hand, to stake your
|
||
own death against the death of others, and measure everything by
|
||
"deleometers." Klaus Mann's novel, Mephisto, gives samplings of entirely
|
||
ordinary Nazi speeches and conversations: "Heroism was something that
|
||
1933: MICROPOLITICS AND SEGMENTARITY D 231
|
||
|
||
was being ruled out of our lives. . . . In reality, we are not marching forward,
|
||
we are reeling, staggering. Our beloved Fiihrer is dragging us toward the
|
||
shades of darkness and everlasting nothingness. How can we poets, we who
|
||
have a special affinity for darkness and lower depths, not admire him? . . .
|
||
Fires blazing on the horizon; rivers of blood in all the streets; and the fren-
|
||
zied dancing of the survivors, of those who are still spared, around the bod-
|
||
ies of the dead!"32 Suicide is presented not as a punishment but as the
|
||
crowning glory of the death of others. One can always say that it is just a
|
||
matter of foggy talk and ideology, nothing but ideology. But that is not true.
|
||
The insufficiency of economic and political definitions of fascism does not
|
||
simply imply a need to tack on vague, so-called ideological determinations.
|
||
We prefer to follow Faye's inquiry into the precise formation of Nazi state-
|
||
ments, which are just as much in evidence in politics and economics as in
|
||
the most absurd of conversations. They always contain the "stupid and
|
||
repugnant" cry, Long live death!, even at the economic level, where the
|
||
arms expansion replaces growth in consumption and where investment
|
||
veers from the means of production toward the means of pure destruction.
|
||
Paul Virilio's analysis strikes us as entirely correct in defining fascism not
|
||
by the notion of the totalitarian State but by the notion of the suicidal State:
|
||
so-called total war seems less a State undertaking than an undertaking of a
|
||
war machine that appropriates the State and channels into it a flow of abso-
|
||
lute war whose only possible outcome is the suicide of the State itself. "The
|
||
triggering of a hitherto unknown material process, one that is limitless and
|
||
aimless. . . . Once triggered, its mechanism cannot stop at peace, for the
|
||
indirect strategy effectively places the dominant powers outside the usual
|
||
categories of space and time. . . . It was in the horror of daily life and its
|
||
environment that Hitler finally found his surest means of governing, the
|
||
legitimation of his policies and military strategy; and it lasted right up to
|
||
the end, for the ruins and horrors and crimes and chaos of total war, far
|
||
from discharging the repulsive nature of its power, normally only increase
|
||
its scope. Telegram 71 is the normal outcome: If the war is lost, may the
|
||
nation perish. Here, Hitler decides to join forces with his enemies in order
|
||
to complete the destruction of his own people, by obliterating the last
|
||
remaining resources of its life-support system, civil reserves of every kind
|
||
(potable water, fuel, provisions, etc.)."33 It was this reversion of the line of
|
||
flight into a line of destruction that already animated the molecular
|
||
focuses of fascism, and made them interact in a war machine instead of res-
|
||
onating in a State apparatus. A war machine that no longer had anything
|
||
but war as its object and would rather annihilate its own servants than stop
|
||
the destruction. All the dangers of the other lines pale by comparison.
|
||
10. 1730: Becoming-Intense, Becoming-
|
||
Animal, Becoming-Imperceptible . . .
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
232
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 233
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Moviegoer. I recall the fine film Willard (1972, Daniel
|
||
Mann). A "B" movie perhaps, but a fine unpopular film: unpopular be-
|
||
cause the heroes are rats. My memory of it is not necessarily accurate. I will
|
||
recount the story in broad outline. Willard lives with his authoritarian
|
||
mother in the old family house. Dreadful Oedipal atmosphere. His mother
|
||
orders him to destroy a litter of rats. He spares one (or two or several). After
|
||
a violent argument, the mother, who "resembles" a dog, dies. The house is
|
||
coveted by a businessman, and Willard is in danger of losing it. He likes the
|
||
principal rat he saved, Ben, who proves to be of prodigious intelligence.
|
||
There is also a white female rat, Ben's companion. Willard spends all his
|
||
free time with them. They multiply. Willard takes the rat pack, led by Ben,
|
||
to the home of the businessman, who is put to a terrible death. But he fool-
|
||
ishly takes his two favorites to the office with him and has no choice but to
|
||
let the employees kill the white rat. Ben escapes, after throwing Willard a
|
||
long, hard glare. Willard then experiences a pause in his destiny, in his
|
||
becoming-rat. He tries with all his might to remain among humans. He
|
||
even responds to the advances of a young woman in the office who bears a
|
||
strong "resemblance" to a rat—but it is only a resemblance. One day when
|
||
he has invited the young woman over, all set to be conjugalized, reoedi-
|
||
palized, Ben suddenly reappears, full of hate. Willard tries to drive him
|
||
away, but succeeds only in driving away the young woman: he then is lured
|
||
to the basement by Ben, where a pack of countless rats is waiting to tear him
|
||
to shreds. It is like a tale; it is never disturbing.
|
||
It is all there: there is a becoming-animal not content to proceed by
|
||
resemblance and for which resemblance, on the contrary, would represent
|
||
an obstacle or stoppage; the proliferation of rats, the pack, brings a
|
||
becoming-molecular that undermines the great molar powers of family,
|
||
career, and conjugality; there is a sinister choice since there is a "favorite"
|
||
in the pack with which a kind of contract of alliance, a hideous pact, is
|
||
made; there is the institution of an assemblage, a war machine or criminal
|
||
machine, which can reach the point of self-destruction; there is a circula-
|
||
tion of impersonal affects, an alternate current that disrupts signifying
|
||
projects as well as subjective feelings, and constitutes a nonhuman sexual-
|
||
ity; and there is an irresistible deterritorialization that forestalls attempts
|
||
at professional, conjugal, or Oedipal reterritorialization. (Are there Oedi-
|
||
pal animals with which one can "play Oedipus," play family, my little dog,
|
||
my little cat, and then other animals that by contrast draw us into an irre-
|
||
sistible becoming? Or another hypothesis: Can the same animal be taken
|
||
up by two opposing functions and movements, depending on the case?)
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Naturalist. One of the main problems of natural history
|
||
was to conceptualize the relationships between animals. It is very different
|
||
234 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
in this respect from later evolutionism, which defined itself in terms of
|
||
genealogy, kinship, descent, and filiation. As we know, evolutionism would
|
||
arrive at the idea of an evolution that does not necessarily operate by
|
||
filiation. But it was unavoidable that it begin with the genealogical motif.
|
||
Darwin himself treats the evolutionist theme of kinship and the naturalist
|
||
theme of the sum and value of differences or resemblances as very separate
|
||
things: groups that are equally related can display highly variable degrees
|
||
of difference with respect to the ancestor. Precisely because natural history
|
||
is concerned primarily with the sum and value of differences, it can con-
|
||
ceive of progressions and regressions, continuities and major breaks, but
|
||
not an evolution in the strict sense, in other words, the possibility of a
|
||
descent the degrees of modification of which depend on external condi-
|
||
tions. Natural history can think only in terms of relationships (between A
|
||
and B), not in terms of production (from A to x).
|
||
But something very important transpires at the level of relationships.
|
||
For natural history conceives of the relationships between animals in two
|
||
ways: series and structure. In the case of a series, I say a resembles b, b
|
||
resembles c, etc.; all of these terms conform in varying degrees to a single,
|
||
eminent term, perfection, or quality as the principle behind the series. This
|
||
is exactly what the theologians used to call an analogy of proportion. In the
|
||
case of a structure, I say a is to b as c is to d; and each of these relationships
|
||
realizes after its fashion the perfection under consideration: gills are to
|
||
breathing under water as lungs are to breathing air; or the heart is to gills as
|
||
the absence of a heart is to tracheas [in insects]. . . This is an analogy of pro-
|
||
portionality. In the first case, I have resemblances that differ from one
|
||
another in a single series, and between series. In the second case, I have dif-
|
||
ferences that resemble each other within a single structure, and between
|
||
structures. The first form of analogy passes for the most sensible and popu-
|
||
lar, and requires imagination; but the kind of imagination it requires is a
|
||
studious one that has to take branchings in the series into account, fill in
|
||
apparent ruptures, ward off false resemblances and graduate the true ones,
|
||
and take both progressions and regressions or degraduations into account.
|
||
The second form of analogy is considered royal because it requires instead
|
||
all the resources of understanding (entendement), in order to define equiv-
|
||
alent relations by discovering, on the one hand, the independent variables
|
||
that can be combined to form a structure and, on the other hand, the corre-
|
||
lates that entail one another within each structure. As different as they are,
|
||
the two themes of series and structure have always coexisted in natural his-
|
||
tory; in appearance contradictory, in practice they have reached a more or
|
||
less stable compromise.1 In the same way, the two figures of analogy coex-
|
||
isted in the minds of the theologians in various equilibriums. This is
|
||
because in both cases Nature is conceived as an enormous mimesis: either
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 235
|
||
|
||
in the form of a chain of beings perpetually imitating one another, progres-
|
||
sively and regressively, and tending toward the divine higher term they all
|
||
imitate by graduated resemblance, as the model for and principle behind
|
||
the series; or in the form of a mirror Imitation with nothing left to imitate
|
||
because it itself is the model everything else imitates, this time by ordered
|
||
difference. (This mimetic or mimological vision is what made the idea of
|
||
an evolution-production possible at that moment.)
|
||
This problem is in no way behind us. Ideas do not die. Not that they
|
||
survive simply as archaisms. At a given moment they may reach a scien-
|
||
tific stage, and then lose that status or emigrate to other sciences. Their
|
||
application and status, even their form and content, may change; yet they
|
||
retain something essential throughout the process, across the displace-
|
||
ment, in the distribution of a new domain. Ideas are always reusable,
|
||
because they have been usable before, but in the most varied of actual
|
||
modes. For, on the one hand, the relationships between animals are the
|
||
object not only of science but also of dreams, symbolism, art and poetry,
|
||
practice and practical use. And on the other hand, the relationships
|
||
between animals are bound up with the relations between man and ani-
|
||
mal, man and woman, man and child, man and the elements, man and the
|
||
physical and microphysical universe. The twofold idea "series-structure"
|
||
crosses a scientific threshold at a certain moment; but it did not start
|
||
there and it does not stay there, or else crosses over into other sciences,
|
||
animating, for example, the human sciences, serving in the study of
|
||
dreams, myths, and organizations. The history of ideas should never be
|
||
continuous; it should be wary of resemblances, but also of descents or
|
||
filiations; it should be content to mark the thresholds through which an
|
||
idea passes, the journeys it takes that change its nature or object. Yet the
|
||
objective relationships between animals have been applied to certain sub-
|
||
jective relations between man and animal, from the standpoint of a col-
|
||
lective imagination or a faculty of social understanding.
|
||
Jung elaborated a theory of the Archetype as collective unconscious; it
|
||
assigns the animal a particularly important role in dreams, myths, and
|
||
human collectivities. The animal is inseparable from a series exhibiting the
|
||
double aspect of progression-regression, in which each term plays the role
|
||
of a possible transformer of the libido (metamorphosis). A whole approach
|
||
to the dream follows from this; given a troubling image, it becomes a ques-
|
||
tion of integrating it into its archetypal series. That series may include fem-
|
||
inine, masculine, or infantile sequences, as well as animal, vegetable, even
|
||
elementary or molecular sequences. In contrast to natural history, man is
|
||
now no longer the eminent term of the series; that term may be an ani-
|
||
mal for man, the lion, crab, bird of prey, or louse, in relation to a given act
|
||
or function, in accordance with a given demand of the unconscious.
|
||
236 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL .. .
|
||
|
||
Bachelard wrote a fine Jungian book when he elaborated the ramified
|
||
series of Lautreamont, taking into account the speed coefficient of the
|
||
metamorphoses and the degree of perfection of each term in relation to a
|
||
pure aggressiveness as the principle of the series: the serpent's fang, the
|
||
horn of the rhinoceros, the dog's tooth, the owl's beak; and higher up, the
|
||
claw of the eagle or the vulture, the pincer of the crab, the legs of the louse,
|
||
the suckers of the octopus. Throughout Jung's work a process of mimesis
|
||
brings nature and culture together in its net, by means of analogies of pro-
|
||
portion in which the series and their terms, and above all the animals occu-
|
||
pying a middle position, assure cycles of conversion nature-culture-nature:
|
||
archetypes as "analogical representations."2
|
||
Is it by chance that structuralism so strongly denounced the prestige
|
||
accorded the imagination, the establishment of resemblances in a series,
|
||
the imitation pervading the entire series and carrying it to its term, and
|
||
the identification with this final term? Nothing is more explicit than
|
||
Levi-Strauss's famous texts on totemism: transcend external resem-
|
||
blances to arrive at internal homologies.3 It is no longer a question of
|
||
instituting a serial organization of the imaginary, but instead a symbolic
|
||
and structural order of understanding. It is no longer a question of gradu-
|
||
ating resemblances, ultimately arriving at an identification between Man
|
||
and Animal at the heart of a mystical participation. It is a question of
|
||
ordering differences to arrive at a correspondence of relations. The ani-
|
||
mal is distributed according to differential relations or distinctive oppo-
|
||
sitions between species; the same goes for human beings, according to the
|
||
groups considered. When analyzing the institution of the totem, we do
|
||
not say that this group of people identifies with that animal species. We
|
||
say that what group A is to group B, species A' is to species B'. This method
|
||
is profoundly different from the preceding one: given two human groups,
|
||
each with its totem animal, we must discover the way in which the two
|
||
totems entertain relations analogous to those between the two groups—
|
||
the Crow is to the Falcon . . .
|
||
The method also applies to Man-child, man-woman relations, etc. If we
|
||
note, for example, that the warrior has a certain astonishing relation to the
|
||
young woman, we refrain from establishing an imaginary series tying the
|
||
two together; instead, we look for a term effecting an equivalence of rela-
|
||
tions. Thus Vernant can say that marriage is to the woman what war is to
|
||
the man. The result is a homology between the virgin who refuses marriage
|
||
and the warrior who disguises himself as a woman.4 In short, symbolic
|
||
understanding replaces the analogy of proportion with an analogy of pro-
|
||
portionality; the serialization of resemblances with a structuration of dif-
|
||
ferences; the identification of terms with an equality of relations; the
|
||
metamorphoses of the imagination with conceptual metaphors; the great
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 237
|
||
|
||
continuity between nature and culture with a deep rift distributing corre-
|
||
spondences without resemblance between the two; the imitation of a pri-
|
||
mal model with a mimesis that is itself primary and without a model. A
|
||
man can never say: "I am a bull, a wolf..." But he can say: "I am to a
|
||
woman what the bull is to a cow, I am to another man what the wolf is to the
|
||
sheep." Structuralism represents a great revolution; the whole world
|
||
becomes more rational. Levi-Strauss is not content to grant the structural
|
||
model all the prestige of a true classification system; he relegates the serial
|
||
model to the dark domain of sacrifice, which he depicts as illusory, even
|
||
devoid of good sense. The serial theme of sacrifice must yield to the struc-
|
||
tural theme of the institution of the totem, correctly understood. But here,
|
||
as in natural history, many compromises are reached between archetypal
|
||
series and symbolic structures.5
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Bergsonian. None of the preceding satisfies us, from our
|
||
restricted viewpoint. We believe in the existence of very special becom-
|
||
ings-animal traversing human beings and sweeping them away, affecting
|
||
the animal no less than the human. "From 1730 to 1735, all we hear about
|
||
are vampires." Structuralism clearly does not account for these becomings,
|
||
since it is designed precisely to deny or at least denigrate their existence: a
|
||
correspondence of relations does not add up to a becoming. When
|
||
structuralism encounters becomings of this kind pervading a society, it
|
||
sees them only as phenomena of degradation representing a deviation
|
||
from the true order and pertaining to the adventures of diachrony. Yet in
|
||
his study of myths, Levi-Strauss is always encountering these rapid acts by
|
||
which a human becomes animal at the same time as the animal becomes
|
||
. . . (Becomes what? Human, or something else?). It is always possible to try
|
||
to explain these blocks ofbecomingby a correspondence between two rela-
|
||
tions, but to do so most certainly impoverishes the phenomenon under
|
||
study. Must it not be admitted that myth as a frame of classification is quite
|
||
incapable of registering these becomings, which are more like fragments of
|
||
tales? Must we not lend credence to Jean Duvignaud's hypothesis that
|
||
there are "anomic" phenomena pervading societies that are not degrada-
|
||
tions of the mythic order but irreducible dynamisms drawing lines of flight
|
||
and implying other forms of expression than those of myth, even if myth
|
||
recapitulates them in its own terms in order to curb them?6 Does it not
|
||
seem that alongside the two models, sacrifice and series, totem institution
|
||
and structure, there is still room for something else, something more secret,
|
||
more subterranean: the sorcerer and becomings (expressed in tales instead
|
||
of myths or rites)?
|
||
A becoming is not a correspondence between relations. But neither is it a
|
||
resemblance, an imitation, or, at the limit, an identification. The whole
|
||
238 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
structuralist critique of the series seems irrefutable. To become is not to
|
||
progress or regress along a series. Above all, becoming does not occur in the
|
||
imagination, even when the imagination reaches the highest cosmic or
|
||
dynamic level, as in Jung or Bachelard. Becomings-animal are neither
|
||
dreams nor phantasies. They are perfectly real. But which reality is at issue
|
||
here? For if becoming animal does not consist in playing animal or imitat-
|
||
ing an animal, it is clear that the human being does not "really" become an
|
||
animal any more than the animal "really" becomes something else. Becom-
|
||
ing produces nothing other than itself. We fall into a false alternative if we
|
||
say that you either imitate or you are. What is real is the becoming itself, the
|
||
block of becoming, not the supposedly fixed terms through which that
|
||
which becomes passes. Becoming can and should be qualified as be-
|
||
coming-animal even in the absence of a term that would be the animal
|
||
become. The becoming-animal of the human being is real, even if the ani-
|
||
mal the human being becomes is not; and the becoming-other of the animal
|
||
is real, even if that something other it becomes is not. This is the point to
|
||
clarify: that a becoming lacks a subject distinct from itself; but also that it
|
||
has no term, since its term in turn exists only as taken up in another becom-
|
||
ing of which it is the subject, and which coexists, forms a block, with the
|
||
first. This is the principle according to which there is a reality specific to
|
||
becoming (the Bergsonian idea of a coexistence of very different "dura-
|
||
tions," superior or inferior to "ours," all of them in communication).
|
||
Finally, becoming is not an evolution, at least not an evolution by
|
||
descent and filiation. Becoming produces nothing by filiation; all filiation
|
||
is imaginary. Becoming is always of a different order than filiation. It con-
|
||
cerns alliance. If evolution includes any veritable becomings, it is in the
|
||
domain ofsymbioses that bring into play beings of totally different scales
|
||
and kingdoms, with no possible filiation. There is a block of becoming that
|
||
snaps up the wasp and the orchid, but from which no wasp-orchid can ever
|
||
descend. There is a block of becoming that takes hold of the cat and
|
||
baboon, the alliance between which is effected by a C virus. There is a block
|
||
of becoming between young roots and certain microorganisms, the alliance
|
||
between which is effected by the materials synthesized in the leaves
|
||
(rhizosphere). If there is originality in neoevolutionism, it is attributable in
|
||
part to phenomena of this kind in which evolution does not go from some-
|
||
thing less differentiated to something more differentiated, in which it
|
||
ceases to be a hereditary filiative evolution, becoming communicative or
|
||
contagious. Accordingly, the term we would prefer for this form of evolu-
|
||
tion between heterogeneous terms is "involution," on the condition that
|
||
involution is in no way confused with regression. Becoming is involu-
|
||
tionary, involution is creative. To regress is to move in the direction of
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 239
|
||
|
||
something less differentiated. But to involve is to form a block that runs its
|
||
own line "between" the terms in play and beneath assignable relations.
|
||
Neoevolutionism seems important for two reasons: the animal is
|
||
defined not by characteristics (specific, generic, etc.) but by populations
|
||
that vary from milieu to milieu or within the same milieu; movement
|
||
occurs not only, or not primarily, by filiative productions but also by
|
||
transversal communications between heterogeneous populations.
|
||
Becoming is a rhizome, not a classificatory or genealogical tree. Becom-
|
||
ing is certainly not imitating, or identifying with something; neither is it
|
||
regressing-progressing; neither is it corresponding, establishing corre-
|
||
sponding relations; neither is it producing, producing a filiation or pro-
|
||
ducing through filiation. Becoming is a verb with a consistency all its
|
||
own; it does not reduce to, or lead back to, "appearing," "being," "equal-
|
||
ing," or "producing."
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Sorcerer, I. A becoming-animal always involves a pack, a
|
||
band, a population, a peopling, in short, a multiplicity. We sorcerers have
|
||
always known that. It may very well be that other agencies, moreover very
|
||
different from one another, have a different appraisal of the animal. One
|
||
may retain or extract from the animal certain characteristics: species and
|
||
genera, forms and functions, etc. Society and the State need animal charac-
|
||
teristics to use for classifying people; natural history and science need char-
|
||
acteristics in order to classify the animals themselves. Serialism and
|
||
structuralism either graduate characteristics according to their resem-
|
||
blances, or order them according to their differences. Animal characteris-
|
||
tics can be mythic or scientific. But we are not interested in characteristics;
|
||
what interests us are modes of expansion, propagation, occupation, conta-
|
||
gion, peopling. I am legion. The Wolf-Man fascinated by several wolves
|
||
watching him. What would a lone wolf be? Or a whale, a louse, a rat, a fly?
|
||
Beelzebub is the Devil, but the Devil as lord of the flies. The wolf is not fun-
|
||
damentally a characteristic or a certain number of characteristics; it is a
|
||
wolfing. The louse is a lousing, and so on. What is a cry independent of the
|
||
population it appeals to or takes as its witness? Virginia Woolfs experi-
|
||
ences herself not as a monkey or a fish but as a troop of monkeys, a school of
|
||
fish, according to her variable relations of becoming with the people she
|
||
approaches. We do not wish to say that certain animals live in packs. We
|
||
want nothing to do with ridiculous evolutionary classifications a la Lorenz,
|
||
according to which there are inferior packs and superior societies. What we
|
||
are saying is that every animal is fundamentally a band, a pack. That it has
|
||
pack modes, rather than characteristics, even if further distinctions within
|
||
these modes are called for. It is at this point that the human being encoun-
|
||
ters the animal. We do not become animal without a fascination for the
|
||
240 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . ..
|
||
|
||
pack, for multiplicity. A fascination for the outside? Or is the multiplicity
|
||
that fascinates us already related to a multiplicity dwelling within us? In
|
||
one of his masterpieces, H. P. Lovecraft recounts the story of Randolph
|
||
Carter, who feels his "self reel and who experiences a fear worse than that
|
||
of annihilation: "Carters of forms both human and non-human, vertebrate
|
||
and invertebrate, conscious and mindless, animal and vegetable. And
|
||
more, there were Carters having nothing in common with earthly life, but
|
||
moving outrageously amidst backgrounds of other planets and systems
|
||
and galaxies and cosmic continua. .. . Merging with nothingness is peace-
|
||
ful oblivion; but to be aware of existence and yet to know that one is no
|
||
longer a definite being distinguished from other beings," nor from all of the
|
||
becomings running through us, "that is the nameless summit of agony and
|
||
dread."7 Hofmannsthal, or rather Lord Chandos, becomes fascinated with
|
||
a "people" of dying rats, and it is in him, through him, in the interstices of
|
||
his disrupted self that the "soul of the animal bares its teeth at monsterous
|
||
fate":8 not pity, but unnatural participation. Then a strange imperative
|
||
wells up in him: either stop writing, or write like a r a t . . . If the writer is a
|
||
sorcerer, it is because writing is a becoming, writing is traversed by strange
|
||
becomings that are not becomings-writer, but becomings-rat, becomings-
|
||
insect, becomings-wolf, etc. We will have to explain why. Many suicides by
|
||
writers are explained by these unnatural participations, these unnatural
|
||
nuptials. Writers are sorcerers because they experience the animal as the
|
||
only population before which they are responsible in principle. The Ger-
|
||
man preromantic Karl Philipp Moritz feels responsible not for the calves
|
||
that die but before the calves that die and give him the incredible feeling of
|
||
an unknown Nature—affect? For the affect is not a personal feeling, nor is
|
||
it a characteristic; it is the effectuation of a power of the pack that throws
|
||
the self into upheaval and makes it reel. Who has not known the violence of
|
||
these animal sequences, which uproot one from humanity, if only for an
|
||
instant, making one scrape at one's bread like a rodent or giving one the yel-
|
||
low eyes of a feline? A fearsome involution calling us toward unheard-of
|
||
becomings. These are not regressions, although fragments of regression,
|
||
sequences of regression may enter in.
|
||
We must distinguish three kinds of animals. First, individuated ani-
|
||
mals, family pets, sentimental, Oedipal animals each with its own petty
|
||
history, "my" cat, "my" dog. These animals invite us to regress, draw us
|
||
into a narcissistic contemplation, and they are the only kind of animal psy-
|
||
choanalysis understands, the better to discover a daddy, a mommy, a little
|
||
brother behind them (when psychoanalysis talks about animals, animals
|
||
learn to laugh): anyone who likes cats or dogs is a fool. And then there is a
|
||
second kind: animals with characteristics or attributes; genus, classifica-
|
||
tion, or State animals; animals as they are treated in the great divine myths,
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 241
|
||
|
||
in such a way as to extract from them series or structures, archetypes or
|
||
models (Jung is in any event profounder than Freud). Finally, there are
|
||
more demonic animals, pack or affect animals that form a multiplicity, a
|
||
becoming, a population, a tale . . . Or once again, cannot any animal be
|
||
treated in all three ways? There is always the possibility that a given animal,
|
||
a louse, a cheetah or an elephant, will be treated as a pet, my little beast.
|
||
And at the other extreme, it is also possible for any animal to be treated in
|
||
the mode of the pack or swarm; that is our way, fellow sorcerers. Even the
|
||
cat, even the dog. And the shepherd, the animal trainer, the Devil, may
|
||
have a favorite animal in the pack, although not at all in the way we were
|
||
just discussing. Yes, any animal is or can be a pack, but to varying degrees
|
||
of vocation that make it easier or harder to discover the multiplicity, or
|
||
multiplicity-grade, an animal contains (actually or virtually according to
|
||
the case). Schools, bands, herds, populations are not inferior social forms;
|
||
they are affects and powers, involutions that grip every animal in a becom-
|
||
ing just as powerful as that of the human being with the animal.
|
||
Jorge Luis Borges, an author renowned for his excess of culture, botched
|
||
at least two books, only the titles of which are nice: first, A Universal His-
|
||
tory of Infamy, because he did not see the sorcerer's fundamental distinc-
|
||
tion between deception and treason (becomings-animal are there from the
|
||
start, on the treason side); second, his Manual dezoolog'iafantastica, where
|
||
he not only adopts a composite and bland image of myth but also elimi-
|
||
nates all of the problems of the pack and the corresponding becoming-
|
||
animal of the human being: "We have deliberately excluded from this
|
||
manual legends of transformations of the human being, the lobizbn, the
|
||
werewolf, etc."10 Borges is interested only in characteristics, even the most
|
||
fantastic ones, whereas sorcerers know that werewolves are bands, and
|
||
vampires too, and that bands transform themselves into one another. But
|
||
what exactly does that mean, the animal as band or pack? Does a band not
|
||
imply a filiation, bringing us back to the reproduction of given characteris-
|
||
tics? How can we conceive of a peopling, a propagation, a becoming that is
|
||
without filiation or hereditary production? A multiplicity without the
|
||
unity of an ancestor? It is quite simple; everybody knows it, but it is dis-
|
||
cussed only in secret. We oppose epidemic to filiation, contagion to hered-
|
||
ity, peopling by contagion to sexual reproduction, sexual production.
|
||
Bands, human or animal, proliferate by contagion, epidemics, battlefields,
|
||
and catastrophes. Like hybrids, which are in themselves sterile, born of a
|
||
sexual union that will not reproduce itself, but which begins over again
|
||
every time, gaining that much more ground. Unnatural participations or
|
||
nuptials are the true Nature spanning the kingdoms of nature. Propagation
|
||
by epidemic, by contagion, has nothing to do with filiation by heredity,
|
||
even if the two themes intermingle and require each other. The vampire
|
||
242 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
does not filiate, it infects. The difference is that contagion, epidemic,
|
||
involves terms that are entirely heterogeneous: for example, a human
|
||
being, an animal, and a bacterium, a virus, a molecule, a microorganism.
|
||
Or in the case of the truffle, a tree, a fly, and a pig. These combinations are
|
||
neither genetic nor structural; they are interkingdoms, unnatural partici-
|
||
pations. That is the only way Nature operates—against itself. This is a far
|
||
cry from filiative production or hereditary reproduction, in which the only
|
||
differences retained are a simple duality between sexes within the same
|
||
species, and small modifications across generations. For us, on the other
|
||
hand, there are as many sexes as there are terms in symbiosis, as many dif-
|
||
ferences as elements contributing to a process of contagion. We know that
|
||
many beings pass between a man and a woman; they come from different
|
||
worlds, are borne on the wind, form rhizomes around roots; they cannot be
|
||
understood in terms of production, only in terms of becoming. The Uni-
|
||
verse does not function by filiation. All we are saying is that animals are
|
||
packs, and that packs form, develop, and are transformed by contagion.
|
||
These multiplicities with heterogeneous terms, cofunctioning by conta-
|
||
gion, enter certain assemblages; it is there that human beings effect their
|
||
becomings-animal. But we should not confuse these dark assemblages,
|
||
which stir what is deepest within us, with organizations such as the institu-
|
||
tion of the family and the State apparatus. We could cite hunting societies,
|
||
war societies, secret societies, crime societies, etc. Becomings-animal are
|
||
proper to them. We will not expect to find filiative regimes of the family
|
||
type or modes of classification and attribution of the State or pre-State
|
||
type or even serial organizations of the religious type. Despite appearances
|
||
and possible confusions, this is not the site of origin or point of application
|
||
for myths. These are tales, or narratives and statements of becoming. It is
|
||
therefore absurd to establish a hierarchy even of animal collectivities from
|
||
the standpoint of a whimsical evolutionism according to which packs are
|
||
lower on the scale and are superseded by State or familial societies. On the
|
||
contrary, there is a difference in nature. The origin of packs is entirely dif-
|
||
ferent from that of families and States; they continually work them from
|
||
within and trouble them from without, with other forms of content, other
|
||
forms of expression. The pack is simultaneously an animal reality, and the
|
||
reality of the becoming-animal of the human being; contagion is simulta-
|
||
neously an animal peopling, and the propagation of the animal peopling of
|
||
the human being. The hunting machine, the war machine, the crime
|
||
machine entail all kinds of becomings-animal that are not articulated in
|
||
myth, still less in totemism. Dumezil showed that becomings of this kind
|
||
pertain essentially to the man of war, but only insofar as he is external to
|
||
families and States, insofar as he upsets filiations and classifications. The
|
||
war machine is always exterior to the State, even when the State uses it,
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 243
|
||
|
||
appropriates it. The man of war has an entire becoming that implies multi-
|
||
plicity, celerity, ubiquity, metamorphosis and treason, the power of affect.
|
||
Wolf-men, bear-men, wildcat-men, men of every animality, secret brother-
|
||
hoods, animate the battlefields. But so do the animal packs used by men in
|
||
battle, or which trail the battles and take advantage of them. And together
|
||
they spread contagion.11 There is a complex aggregate: the becoming-
|
||
animal of men, packs of animals, elephants and rats, winds and tempests,
|
||
bacteria sowing contagion. A single Furor. War contained zoological se-
|
||
quences before it became bacteriological. It is in war, famine, and epidemic
|
||
that werewolves and vampires proliferate. Any animal can be swept up in
|
||
these packs and the corresponding becomings; cats have been seen on the
|
||
battlefield, and even in armies. That is why the distinction we must make is
|
||
less between kinds of animals than between the different states according
|
||
to which they are integrated into family institutions, State apparatuses,
|
||
war machines, etc. (and what is the relation of the writing machine and the
|
||
musical machine to becomings-animal?)
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Sorcerer, II. Our first principle was: pack and contagion,
|
||
the contagion of the pack, such is the path becoming-animal takes. But a
|
||
second principle seemed to tell us the opposite: wherever there is multipli-
|
||
city, you will also find an exceptional individual, and it is with that individ-
|
||
ual that an alliance must be made in order to become-animal. There may be
|
||
no such thing as a lone wolf, but there is a leader of the pack, a master of the
|
||
pack, or else the old deposed head of the pack now living alone, there is the
|
||
Loner, and there is the Demon. Willard has his favorite, the rat Ben, and
|
||
only becomes-rat through his relation with him, in a kind of alliance of
|
||
love, then of hate. Moby-Dick in its entirety is one of the greatest master-
|
||
pieces of becoming; Captain Ahab has an irresistible becoming-whale, but
|
||
one that bypasses the pack or the school, operating directly through a mon-
|
||
strous alliance with the Unique, the Leviathan, Moby-Dick. There is
|
||
always a pact with a demon; the demon sometimes appears as the head of
|
||
the band, sometimes as the Loner on the sidelines of the pack, and some-
|
||
times as the higher Power (Puissance) of the band. The exceptional individ-
|
||
ual has many possible positions. Kafka, another great author of real
|
||
becomings-animal, sings of mouse society; but Josephine, the mouse
|
||
singer, sometimes holds a privileged position in the pack, sometimes a
|
||
position outside the pack, and sometimes slips into and is lost in the ano-
|
||
nymity of the collective statements of the pack.12 In short, every Animal
|
||
has its Anomalous. Let us clarify that: every animal swept up in its pack or
|
||
multiplicity has its anomalous. It has been noted that the origin of the word
|
||
anomal ("anomalous"), an adjective that has fallen into disuse in French,
|
||
is very different from that of anormal ("abnormal"): a-normal, a Latin
|
||
244 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
adjective lacking a noun in French, refers to that which is outside rules or
|
||
goes against the rules, whereas an-omalie, a Greek noun that has lost its
|
||
adjective, designates the unequal, the coarse, the rough, the cutting edge of
|
||
deterritorialization.13 The abnormal can be defined only in terms of char-
|
||
acteristics, specific or generic; but the anomalous is a position or set of
|
||
positions in relation to a multiplicity. Sorcerers therefore use the old adjec-
|
||
tive "anomalous" to situate the positions of the exceptional individual in
|
||
the pack. It is always with the Anomalous, Moby-Dick or Josephine, that
|
||
one enters into alliance to become-animal.
|
||
It does seem as though there is a contradiction: between the pack and the
|
||
loner; between mass contagion and preferential alliance; between pure
|
||
multiplicity and the exceptional individual; between the aleatory aggre-
|
||
gate and a predestined choice. And the contradiction is real: Ahab chooses
|
||
Moby-Dick, in a choosing that exceeds him and comes from elsewhere, and
|
||
in so doing breaks with the law of the whalers according to which one
|
||
should first pursue the pack. Penthesilea shatters the law of the pack, the
|
||
pack of women, the pack of she-dogs, by choosing Achilles as her favorite
|
||
enemy. Yet it is by means of this anomalous choice that each enters into his
|
||
or her becoming-animal, the becoming-dog of Penthesilea, the becoming-
|
||
whale of Captain Ahab. We sorcerers know quite well that the contradic-
|
||
tions are real but that real contradictions are not just for laughs. For the
|
||
whole question is this: What exactly is the nature of the anomalous? What
|
||
function does it have in relation to the band, to the pack? It is clear that the
|
||
anomalous is not simply an exceptional individual; that would be to equate
|
||
it with the family animal or pet, the Oedipalized animal as psychoanalysis
|
||
sees it, as the image of the father, etc. Ahab's Moby-Dick is not like the little
|
||
cat or dog owned by an elderly woman who honors and cherishes it.
|
||
Lawrence's becoming-tortoise has nothing to do with a sentimental or
|
||
domestic relation. Lawrence is another of the writers who leave us troubled
|
||
and filled with admiration because they were able to tie their writing to real
|
||
and unheard-of becomings. But the objection is raised against Lawrence:
|
||
"Your tortoises aren't real!" And he answers: Possibly, but my becoming is,
|
||
my becoming is real, even and especially if you have no way of judging it,
|
||
because you're just little house dogs . . .14 The anomalous, the preferential
|
||
element in the pack, has nothing to do with the preferred, domestic, and
|
||
psychoanalytic individual. Nor is the anomalous the bearer of a species
|
||
presenting specific or generic characteristics in their purest state; nor is it a
|
||
model or unique specimen; nor is it the perfection of a type incarnate; nor
|
||
is it the eminent term of a series; nor is it the basis of an absolutely harmo-
|
||
nious correspondence. The anomalous is neither an individual nor a spe-
|
||
cies; it has only affects, it has neither familiar or subjectified feelings, nor
|
||
specific or significant characteristics. Human tenderness is as foreign to it
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL ... D 245
|
||
|
||
as human classifications. Lovecraft applies the term "Outsider" to this
|
||
thing or entity, the Thing, which arrives and passes at the edge, which is lin-
|
||
ear yet multiple, "teeming, seething, swelling, foaming, spreading like an
|
||
infectious disease, this nameless horror."
|
||
If the anomalous is neither an individual nor a species, then what is it? It
|
||
is a phenomenon, but a phenomenon of bordering. This is our hypothesis:
|
||
a multiplicity is defined not by the elements that compose it in extension,
|
||
not by the characteristics that compose it in comprehension, but by the
|
||
lines and dimensions it encompasses in "intension." If you change dimen-
|
||
sions, if you add or subtract one, you change multiplicity. Thus there is a
|
||
borderline for each multiplicity; it is in no way a center but rather the envel-
|
||
oping line or farthest dimension, as a function of which it is possible to
|
||
count the others, all those lines or dimensions constitute the pack at a given
|
||
moment (beyond the borderline, the multiplicity changes nature). That is
|
||
what Captain Ahab says to his first mate: I have no personal history with
|
||
Moby-Dick, no revenge to take, any more than I have a myth to play out;
|
||
but I do have a becoming! Moby-Dick is neither an individual nor a genus;
|
||
he is the borderline, and I have to strike him to get at the pack as a whole, to
|
||
reach the pack as a whole and pass beyond it. The elements of the pack are
|
||
only imaginary "dummies," the characteristics of the pack are only sym-
|
||
bolic entities; all that counts is the borderline—the anomalous. "To me,
|
||
the white whale is that wall, shoved near to me." The white wall. "Some-
|
||
times I think there is naught beyond. But 'tis enough."15 That the anoma-
|
||
lous is the borderline makes it easier for us to understand the various
|
||
positions it occupies in relation to the pack or the multiplicity it borders,
|
||
and the various positions occupied by a fascinated Self (Moi). It is now
|
||
even possible to establish a classification system for packs while avoiding
|
||
the pitfalls of an evolutionism that sees them only as an inferior collective
|
||
stage (instead of taking into consideration the particular assemblages they
|
||
bring into play). In any event, the pack has a borderline, and an anomalous
|
||
position, whenever in a given space an animal is on the line or in the act of
|
||
drawing the line in relation to which all the other members of the pack will
|
||
fall into one of two halves, left or right: a peripheral position, such that it is
|
||
impossible to tell if the anomalous is still in the band, already outside the
|
||
band, or at the shifting boundary of the band. Sometimes each and every
|
||
animal reaches this line or occupies this dynamic position, as in a swarm of
|
||
mosquitoes, where "each individual moves randomly unless it sees the rest
|
||
of [the swarm] in the same half-space; then it hurries to re-enter the group.
|
||
Thus stability is assured in catastrophe by a barrier."16 Sometimes it is a
|
||
specific animal that draws and occupies the borderline, as leader of the
|
||
pack. Sometimes the borderline is defined or doubled by a being of another
|
||
nature that no longer belongs to the pack, or never belonged to it, and that
|
||
246 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL ...
|
||
|
||
represents a power of another order, potentially acting as a threat as well as
|
||
a trainer, outsider, etc. In any case, no band is without this phenomenon of
|
||
bordering, or the anomalous. It is true that bands are also undermined by
|
||
extremely varied forces that establish in them interior centers of the conju-
|
||
gal, familial, or State type, and that make them pass into an entirely differ-
|
||
ent form of sociability, replacing pack affects with family feelings or State
|
||
intelligibilities. The center, or internal black holes, assumes the principal
|
||
role. This is what evolutionism sees as progress, this adventure also befalls
|
||
bands of humans when they reconstitute group familialism, or even
|
||
authoritarianism or pack fascism.
|
||
Sorcerers have always held the anomalous position, at the edge of the
|
||
fields or woods. They haunt the fringes. They are at the borderline of the
|
||
village, or between villages. The important thing is their affinity with alli-
|
||
ance, with the pact, which gives them a status opposed to that of filiation.
|
||
The relation with the anomalous is one of alliance. The sorcerer has a
|
||
relation of alliance with the demon as the power of the anomalous. The
|
||
old-time theologians drew a clear distinction between two kinds of curses
|
||
against sexuality. The first concerns sexuality as a process of filiation
|
||
transmitting the original sin. But the second concerns it as a power of alli-
|
||
ance inspiring illicit unions or abominable loves. This differs signifi-
|
||
cantly from the first in that it tends to prevent procreation; since the
|
||
demon does not himself have the ability to procreate, he must adopt indi-
|
||
rect means (for example, being the female succubus of a man and then
|
||
becoming the male incubus of a woman, to whom he transmits the man's
|
||
semen). It is true that the relations between alliance and filiation come to
|
||
be regulated by laws of marriage, but even then alliance retains a danger-
|
||
ous and contagious power. Leach was able to demonstrate that despite all
|
||
the exceptions that seemingly disprove the rule, the sorcerer belongs first
|
||
of all to a group united to the group over which he or she exercises influ-
|
||
ence only by alliance: thus in a matrilineal group we look to the father's
|
||
side for the sorcerer or witch. And there is an entire evolution of sorcery
|
||
depending on whether the relation of alliance acquires permanence or
|
||
assumes political weight.17 In order to produce werewolves in your own
|
||
family it is not enough to resemble a wolf, or to live like a wolf: the pact
|
||
with the Devil must be coupled with an alliance with another family, and
|
||
it is the return of this alliance to the first family, the reaction of this alli-
|
||
ance on the first family, that produces werewolves by feedback effect. A
|
||
fine tale by Erckmann and Chatrian, Hugues-le-loup, assembles the tradi-
|
||
tions concerning this complex situation.18
|
||
The contradiction between the two themes, "contagion through the ani-
|
||
mal as pack," and "pact with the anomalous as exceptional being," is pro-
|
||
gressively fading. It is with good reason that Leach links the two concepts of
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 247
|
||
|
||
alliance and contagion, pact and epidemic. Analyzing Kachin sorcery, he
|
||
writes: "Witch influence was thought to be transmitted in the food that the
|
||
women prepared. . . . Kachin witchcraft is contagious rather than heredi-
|
||
tary . . . it is associated with affinity, not filiation."19 Alliance or the pact is
|
||
the form of expression for an infection or epidemic constituting the form of
|
||
content. In sorcery, blood is of the order of contagion and alliance. It can be
|
||
said that becoming-animal is an affair of sorcery because (1) it implies an
|
||
initial relation of alliance with a demon; (2) the demon functions as the
|
||
borderline of an animal pack, into which the human being passes or in
|
||
which his or her becoming takes place, by contagion; (3) this becoming
|
||
itself implies a second alliance, with another human group; (4) this new
|
||
borderline between the two groups guides the contagion of animal and
|
||
human being within the pack. There is an entire politics of becomings-
|
||
animal, as well as a politics of sorcery, which is elaborated in assemblages
|
||
that are neither those of the family nor of religion nor of the State. Instead,
|
||
they express minoritarian groups, or groups that are oppressed, prohib-
|
||
ited, in revolt, or always on the fringe of recognized institutions, groups all
|
||
the more secret for being extrinsic, in other words, anomic. If becoming-
|
||
animal takes the form of a Temptation, and of monsters aroused in the
|
||
imagination by the demon, it is because it is accompanied, at its origin as in
|
||
its undertaking, by a rupture with the central institutions that have estab-
|
||
lished themselves or seek to become established.
|
||
Let us cite pell-mell, not as mixes to be made, but as different cases to be
|
||
studied: becomings-animal in the war machine, wildmen of all kinds (the
|
||
war machine indeed comes from without, it is extrinsic to the State, which
|
||
treats the warrior as an anomalous power); becomings-animal in crime
|
||
societies, leopard-men, crocodile-men (when the State prohibits tribal and
|
||
local wars); becomings-animal in riot groups (when the Church and State
|
||
are faced with peasant movements containing a sorcery component, which
|
||
they repress by setting up a whole trial and legal system designed to expose
|
||
pacts with the Devil); becomings-animal in asceticism groups, the grazing
|
||
anchorite or wild-beast anchorite (the asceticism machine is in an anoma-
|
||
lous position, on a line of flight, off to the side of the Church, and disputes
|
||
the Church's pretension to set itself up as an imperial institution);20
|
||
becomings-animal in societies practicing sexual initiation of the "sacred
|
||
deflowerer" type, wolf-men, goat-men, etc. (who claim an Alliance supe-
|
||
rior and exterior to the order of families; families have to win from them
|
||
the right to regulate their own alliances, to determine them according to
|
||
relations of complementary lines of descent, and to domesticate this unbri-
|
||
dled power of alliance).21
|
||
The politics of becomings-animal remains, of course, extremely ambig-
|
||
uous. For societies, even primitive societies, have always appropriated
|
||
248 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
these becomings in order to break them, reduce them to relations of
|
||
totemic or symbolic correspondence. States have always appropriated the
|
||
war machine in the form of national armies that strictly limit the be-
|
||
comings of the warrior. The Church has always burned sorcerers, or
|
||
reintegrated anchorites into the toned-down image of a series of saints
|
||
whose only remaining relation to animals is strangely familiar, domestic.
|
||
Families have always warded off the demonic Alliance gnawing at them, in
|
||
order to regulate alliances among themselves as they see fit. We have seen
|
||
sorcerers serve as leaders, rally to the cause of despotism, create the
|
||
countersorcery of exorcism, pass over to the side of the family and descent.
|
||
But this spells the death of the sorcerer, and also the death of becoming. We
|
||
have seen becoming spawn nothing more than a big domestic dog, as in
|
||
Henry Miller's damnation ("it would be better to feign, to pretend to be an
|
||
animal, a dog for example, and catch the bone thrown to me from time to
|
||
time") or Fitzgerald's ("I will try to be a correct animal though, and if you
|
||
throw me a bone with enough meat on it I may even lick your hand"). Invert
|
||
Faust's formula: So that is what it was, the form of the traveling scholar? A
|
||
mere poodle?22
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Sorcerer, III. Exclusive importance should not be
|
||
attached to becomings-animal. Rather, they are segments occupying a
|
||
median region. On the near side, we encounter becomings-woman,
|
||
becomings-child (becoming-woman, more than any other becoming, pos-
|
||
sesses a special introductory power; it is not so much that women are
|
||
witches, but that sorcery proceeds by way of this becoming-woman). On
|
||
the far side, we find becomings-elementary, -cellular, -molecular, and even
|
||
becomings-imperceptible. Toward what void does the witch's broom lead?
|
||
And where is Moby-Dick leading Ahab so silently? Lovecraft's hero
|
||
encounters strange animals, but he finally reaches the ultimate regions of a
|
||
Continuum inhabited by unnameable waves and unfindable particles. Sci-
|
||
ence fiction has gone through a whole evolution taking it from animal, veg-
|
||
etable, and mineral becomings to becomings of bacteria, viruses, mole-
|
||
cules, and things imperceptible.23 The properly musical content of music is
|
||
plied by becomings-woman, becomings-child, becomings-animal; how-
|
||
ever, it tends, under all sorts of influences, having to do also with the instru-
|
||
ments, to become progressively more molecular in a kind of cosmic
|
||
lapping through which the inaudible makes itself heard and the impercep-
|
||
tible appears as such: no longer the songbird, but the sound molecule.
|
||
If the experimentation with drugs has left its mark on everyone, even
|
||
nonusers, it is because it changed the perceptive coordinates of space-time
|
||
and introduced us to a universe of microperceptions in which becomings-
|
||
molecular take over where becomings-animal leave off. Carlos Castaneda's
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 249
|
||
|
||
books clearly illustrate this evolution, or rather this involution, in which
|
||
the affects of a becoming-dog, for example, are succeeded by those of a
|
||
becoming-molecular, microperceptions of water, air, etc. A man totters
|
||
from one door to the next and disappears into thin air: "All I can tell you is
|
||
that we are fluid, luminous beings made of fibers."24 All so-called initiatory
|
||
journeys include these thresholds and doors where becoming itself
|
||
becomes, and where one changes becoming depending on the "hour" of the
|
||
world, the circles of hell, or the stages of a journey that sets scales, forms,
|
||
and cries in variation. From the howling of animals to the wailing of ele-
|
||
ments and particles.
|
||
Thus packs, or multiplicities, continually transform themselves into
|
||
each other, cross over into each other. Werewolves become vampires when
|
||
they die. This is not surprising, since becoming and multiplicity are the
|
||
same thing. A multiplicity is defined not by its elements, nor by a center of
|
||
unification or comprehension. It is defined by the number of dimensions it
|
||
has; it is not divisible, it cannot lose or gain a dimension without changing
|
||
its nature. Since its variations and dimensions are immanent to it, it
|
||
amounts to the same thing to say that each multiplicity is already composed
|
||
of heterogeneous terms in symbiosis, and that a multiplicity is continually
|
||
transforming itself into a string of other multiplicities, according to its
|
||
thresholds and doors. For example, the Wolf-Man's pack of wolves also
|
||
becomes a swarm of bees, and a field of anuses, and a collection of small
|
||
holes and tiny ulcerations (the theme of contagion): all these heterogene-
|
||
ous elements compose "the" multiplicity of symbiosis and becoming. If we
|
||
imagined the position of a fascinated Self, it was because the multiplicity
|
||
toward which it leans, stretching to the breaking point, is the continuation
|
||
of another multiplicity that works it and strains it from the inside. In fact,
|
||
the self is only a threshold, a door, a becoming between two multiplicities.
|
||
Each multiplicity is defined by a borderline functioning as Anomalous, but
|
||
there is a string of borderlines, a continuous line of borderlines (fiber) fol-
|
||
lowing which the multiplicity changes. And at each threshold or door, a
|
||
new pact? A fiber stretches from a human to an animal, from a human or an
|
||
animal to molecules, from molecules to particles, and so on to the imper-
|
||
ceptible. Every fiber is a Universe fiber. A fiber strung across borderlines
|
||
constitutes a line of flight or of deterritorialization. It is evident that the
|
||
Anomalous, the Outsider, has several functions: not only does it border
|
||
each multiplicity, of which it determines the temporary or local stability
|
||
(with the highest number of dimensions possible under the circum-
|
||
stances), not only is it the precondition for the alliance necessary to becom-
|
||
ing, but it also carries the transformations of becoming or crossings of
|
||
multiplicities always farther down the line of flight. Moby-Dick is the
|
||
White Wall bordering the pack; he is also the demonic Term of the Alliance;
|
||
250 O 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
finally, he is the terrible Fishing Line with nothing on the other end, the line
|
||
that crosses the wall and drags the captain .. . where? Into the void . . .
|
||
The error we must guard against is to believe that there is a kind of logi-
|
||
cal order to this string, these crossings or transformations. It is already
|
||
going too far to postulate an order descending from the animal to the vege-
|
||
table, then to molecules, to particles. Each multiplicity is symbiotic; its
|
||
becoming ties together animals, plants, microorganisms, mad particles, a
|
||
whole galaxy. Nor is there a preformed logical order to these heterogenei-
|
||
ties, the Wolf-Man's wolves, bees, anuses, little scars. Of course, sorcery
|
||
always codifies certain transformations of becomings. Take a novel
|
||
steeped in the traditions of sorcery, Alexandre Dumas's Meneur de loups;
|
||
in a first pact, the man of the fringes gets the Devil to agree to make his
|
||
wishes come true, with the stipulation that a lock of his hair turn red each
|
||
time he gets a wish. We are in the hair-multiplicity, hair is the borderline.
|
||
The man himself takes a position on the wolves' borderline, as leader of the
|
||
pack. Then when he no longer has a single human hair left, a second pact
|
||
makes him become-wolf himself; it is an endless becoming since he is only
|
||
vulnerable one day in the year. We are aware that between the hair-
|
||
multiplicity and the wolf-multiplicity it is always possible to induce an
|
||
order of resemblance (red like the fur of a wolf); but the resemblance
|
||
remains quite secondary (the wolf of the transformation is black, with one
|
||
white hair). In fact, there is a first multiplicity, of hair, taken up in a
|
||
becoming-red fur; and a second multiplicity, of wolves, which in turn takes
|
||
up the becoming-animal of the man. Between the two, there is threshold
|
||
and fiber, symbiosis of or passage between heterogeneities. That is how we
|
||
sorcerers operate. Not following a logical order, but following alogical con-
|
||
sistencies or compatibilities. The reason is simple. It is because no one, not
|
||
even God, can say in advance whether two borderlines will string together
|
||
or form a fiber, whether a given multiplicity will or will not cross over into
|
||
another given multiplicity, or even if given heterogeneous elements will
|
||
enter symbiosis, will form a consistent, or cofunctioning, multiplicity sus-
|
||
ceptible to transformation. No one can say where the line of flight will pass:
|
||
Will it let itself get bogged down and fall back to the Oedipal family animal,
|
||
a mere poodle? Or will it succumb to another danger, for example, turning
|
||
into a line of abolition, annihilation, self-destruction, Ahab, Ahab... ?We
|
||
are all too familiar with the dangers of the line of flight, and with its ambi-
|
||
guities. The risks are ever-present, but it is always possible to have the good
|
||
fortune of avoiding them. Case by case, we can tell whether the line is con-
|
||
sistent, in other words, whether the heterogeneities effectively function in
|
||
a multiplicity of symbiosis, whether the multiplicities are effectively trans-
|
||
formed through the becomings of passage. Let us take an example as simple
|
||
as: x starts practicing piano again. Is it an Oedipal return to childhood? Is it
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 251
|
||
|
||
a way of dying, in a kind of sonorous abolition? Is it a new borderline, an
|
||
active line that will bring other becomings entirely different from becom-
|
||
ing or rebecoming a pianist, that will induce a transformation of all of the
|
||
preceding assemblages to which x was prisoner? Is it a way out? Is it a pact
|
||
with the Devil? Schizoanalysis, or pragmatics, has no other meaning: Make
|
||
a rhizome. But you don't know what you can make a rhizome with, you
|
||
don't know which subterranean stem is effectively going to make a rhi-
|
||
zome, or enter a becoming, people your desert. So experiment.
|
||
That's easy to say? Although there is no preformed logical order to
|
||
becomings and multiplicities, there are criteria, and the important thing is
|
||
that they not be used after the fact, that they be applied in the course of
|
||
events, that they be sufficient to guide us through the dangers. If multiplici-
|
||
ties are defined and transformed by the borderline that determines in each
|
||
instance their number of dimensions, we can conceive of the possibility of
|
||
laying them out on a plane, the borderlines succeeding one another, form-
|
||
ing a broken line. It is only in appearance that a plane of this kind "reduces"
|
||
the number of dimensions; for it gathers in all the dimensions to the extent
|
||
that flat multiplicities—which nonetheless have an increasing or decreas-
|
||
ing number of dimensions—are inscribed upon it. It is in grandiose and
|
||
simplified terms that Lovecraft attempted to pronounce sorcery's final
|
||
word: "Then the waves increased in strength and sought to improve his
|
||
understanding, reconciling him to the multiform entity of which his pres-
|
||
ent fragment was an infinitesimal part. They told him that every figure of
|
||
space is but the result of the intersection by a plane of some corresponding
|
||
figure of one more dimension—as a square is cut from a cube, or a circle
|
||
from a sphere. The cube and sphere, of three dimensions, are thus cut from
|
||
corresponding forms of four dimensions, which men know only through
|
||
guesses and dreams; and these in turn are cut from forms of five dimen-
|
||
sions, and so on up to the dizzy and reachless heights of archetypal infin-
|
||
ity."25 Far from reducing the multiplicities' number of dimensions to two,
|
||
the plane of consistency cuts across them all, intersects them in order to
|
||
bring into coexistence any number of multiplicities, with any number of
|
||
dimensions. The plane of consistency is the intersection of all concrete
|
||
forms. Therefore all becomings are written like sorcerers' drawings on this
|
||
plane of consistency, which is the ultimate Door providing a way out for
|
||
them. This is the only criterion to prevent them from bogging down, or
|
||
veering into the void. The only question is: Does a given becoming reach
|
||
that point? Can a given multiplicity flatten and conserve all its dimensions
|
||
in this way, like a pressed flower that remains just as alive dry? Lawrence, in
|
||
his becoming-tortoise, moves from the most obstinate animal dynamism
|
||
to the abstract, pure geometry of scales and "cleavages of division," with-
|
||
out, however, losing any of the dynamism: he pushes becoming-tortoise all
|
||
252 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL .. .
|
||
|
||
the way to the plane of consistency.26 Everything becomes imperceptible,
|
||
everything is becoming-imperceptible on the plane of consistency, which is
|
||
nevertheless precisely where the imperceptible is seen and heard. It is the
|
||
Planomenon, or the Rhizosphere, the Criterium (and still other names, as
|
||
the number of dimensions increases). At n dimensions, it is called the
|
||
Hypersphere, the Mechanosphere. It is the abstract Figure, or rather, since
|
||
it has no form itself, the abstract Machine of which each concrete assem-
|
||
blage is a multiplicity, a becoming, a segment, a vibration. And the abstract
|
||
machine is the intersection of them all.
|
||
Waves are vibrations, shifting borderlines inscribed on the plane of con-
|
||
sistency as so many abstractions. The abstract machine of the waves. In
|
||
The Waves, Virginia Woolf—who made all of her life and work a passage, a
|
||
becoming, all kinds of becomings between ages, sexes, elements, and king-
|
||
doms—intermingles seven characters, Bernard, Neville, Louis, Jinny,
|
||
Rhoda, Suzanne, and Percival. But each of these characters, with his or her
|
||
name, its individuality, designates a multiplicity (for example, Bernard
|
||
and the school offish). Each is simultaneously in this multiplicity and at its
|
||
edge, and crosses over into the others. Percival is like the ultimate multipli-
|
||
city enveloping the greatest number of dimensions. But he is not yet the
|
||
plane of consistency. Although Rhoda thinks she sees him rising out of the
|
||
sea, no, it is not he. "When the white arm rests upon the knee it is a triangle;
|
||
now it is upright—a column; now a fountain.. .. Behind it roars the sea. It
|
||
is beyond our reach."27 Each advances like a wave, but on the plane of con-
|
||
sistency they are a single abstract Wave whose vibration propagates follow-
|
||
ing a line of flight or deterritorialization traversing the entire plane (each
|
||
chapter of Woolf s novel is preceded by a meditation on an aspect of the
|
||
waves, on one of their hours, on one of their becomings).
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Theologian. Theology is very strict on the following point:
|
||
there are no werewolves, human beings cannot become animal. That is
|
||
because there is no transformation of essential forms; they are inalienable
|
||
and only entertain relations of analogy. The Devil and the witch, and the
|
||
pact between them, are no less real for that, for there is in reality a local
|
||
movement that is properly diabolical. Theology distinguishes two cases,
|
||
used as models during the Inquisition: that of Ulysses' companions, and
|
||
that of Diomedes' companions, the imaginary vision and the spell. In the
|
||
first, the subject believes him- or herself to be transformed into an animal,
|
||
pig, ox, or wolf, and the observers believe it too; but this is an internal local
|
||
movement bringing sensible images back to the imagination and bouncing
|
||
them off external meanings. In the second, the Devil "assumes" real ani-
|
||
mal bodies, even transporting the accidents and affects befalling them to
|
||
other bodies (for example, a cat or a wolf that has been taken over by the
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 253
|
||
|
||
Devil can receive wounds that are relayed to an exactly corresponding part
|
||
of a human body).28 This is a way of saying that the human being does not
|
||
become animal in reality, but that there is nevertheless a demonic reality of
|
||
the becoming-animal of the human being. Therefore it is certain that the
|
||
demon performs local transports of all kinds. The Devil is a transporter; he
|
||
transports humors, affects, or even bodies (the Inquisition brooks no com-
|
||
promises on this power of the Devil: the witch's broom, or "the Devil take
|
||
you"). But these transports cross neither the barrier of essential forms nor
|
||
that of substances or subjects.
|
||
There is another, altogether different, problem concerning the laws of
|
||
nature that has to do not with demonology but with alchemy, and above all
|
||
physics. It is the problem of accidental forms, distinct from both essential
|
||
forms and determined subjects. For accidental forms are susceptible to
|
||
more and less: more or less charitable, but also more or less white, more or
|
||
less warm. A degree of heat is a perfectly individuated warmth distinct
|
||
from the substance or the subject that receives it. A degree of heat can enter
|
||
into composition with a degree of whiteness, or with another degree of
|
||
heat, to form a third unique individuality distinct from that of the subject.
|
||
What is the individuality of a day, a season, an event? A shorter day and a
|
||
longer day are not, strictly speaking, extensions but degrees proper to
|
||
extension, just as there are degrees proper to heat, color, etc. An accidental
|
||
form therefore has a "latitude" constituted by a certain number of
|
||
composable individuations. A degree, an intensity, is an individual, a
|
||
Haecceity that enters into composition with other degrees, other intensi-
|
||
ties, to form another individual. Can latitude be explained by the fact that
|
||
the subject participates more or less in the accidental form? But do these
|
||
degrees of participation not imply a flutter, a vibration in the form itself
|
||
that is not reducible to the properties of a subject? Moreover, if intensities
|
||
of heat are not composed by addition, it is because one must add their
|
||
respective subjects; it is the subjects that prevent the heat of the whole from
|
||
increasing. All the more reason to effect distributions of intensity, to estab-
|
||
lish latitudes that are "deformedly deformed," speeds, slownesses, and
|
||
degrees of all kinds corresponding to a body or set of bodies taken as longi-
|
||
tude: a cartography.29 In short, between substantial forms and determined
|
||
subjects, between the two, there is not only a whole operation of demonic
|
||
local transports but a natural play of haecceities, degrees, intensities,
|
||
events, and accidents that compose individuations totally different from
|
||
those of the well-formed subjects that receive them.
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Spinozist, I. Substantial or essential forms have been cri-
|
||
tiqued in many different ways. Spinoza's approach is radical: Arrive at ele-
|
||
ments that no longer have either form or function, that are abstract in this
|
||
254 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL ...
|
||
|
||
sense even though they are perfectly real. They are distinguished solely by
|
||
movement and rest, slowness and speed. They are not atoms, in other
|
||
words, finite elements still endowed with form. Nor are they indefinitely
|
||
divisible. They are infinitely small, ultimate parts of an actual infinity, laid
|
||
out on the same plane of consistency or composition. They are not defined
|
||
by their number since they always come in infinities. However, depending
|
||
on their degree of speed or the relation of movement and rest into which
|
||
they enter, they belong to a given Individual, which may itself be part of
|
||
another Individual governed by another, more complex, relation, and so
|
||
on to infinity. There are thus smaller and larger infinities, not by virtue of
|
||
their number, but by virtue of the composition of the relation into which
|
||
their parts enter. Thus each individual is an infinite multiplicity, and the
|
||
whole of Nature is a multiplicity of perfectly individuated multiplicities.
|
||
The plane of consistency of Nature is like an immense Abstract Machine,
|
||
abstract yet real and individual; its pieces are the various assemblages and
|
||
individuals, each of which groups together an infinity of particles entering
|
||
into an infinity of more or less interconnected relations. There is therefore
|
||
a unity to the plane of nature, which applies equally to the inanimate and
|
||
the animate, the artificial and the natural. This plane has nothing to do
|
||
with a form or a figure, nor with a design or a function. Its unity has nothing
|
||
to do with a ground buried deep within things, nor with an end or a project
|
||
in the mind of God. Instead, it is a plane upon which everything is laid out,
|
||
and which is like the intersection of all forms, the machine of all functions;
|
||
its dimensions, however, increase with those of the multiplicities of indi-
|
||
vidualities it cuts across. It is a fixed plane, upon which things are dis-
|
||
tinguished from one another only by speed and slowness. A plane of
|
||
immanence or univocality opposed to analogy. The One is said with a single
|
||
meaning of all the multiple. Being expresses in a single meaning all that
|
||
differs. What we are talking about is not the unity of substance but the infinity
|
||
of the modifications that are part of one another on this unique plane of life.
|
||
The never-ending debate between Cuvier and Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire:
|
||
both agree at least in denouncing resemblances, or imaginary, sensible
|
||
analogies, but in Cuvier, scientific definition concerns the relations
|
||
between organs, and between organs and functions. Cuvier thus takes anal-
|
||
ogy to the scientific stage, making it an analogy of proportionality. The
|
||
unity of the plane, according to him, can only be a unity of analogy, there-
|
||
fore a transcendent unity that cannot be realized without fragmenting into
|
||
distinct branches, according to irreducible, uncrossable, heterogeneous
|
||
compositions. Baer would later add: according to noncommunicating
|
||
types of development and differentiation. The plane is a hidden plan(e) of
|
||
organization, a structure or genesis. Geoffroy has an entirely different
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL.. . D 255
|
||
|
||
point of view because he goes beyond organs and functions to abstract ele-
|
||
ments he terms "anatomical," even to particles, pure materials that enter
|
||
into various combinations, forming a given organ and assuming a given
|
||
function depending on their degree of speed or slowness. Speed and slow-
|
||
ness, movement and rest, tardiness and rapidity subordinate not only the
|
||
forms of structure but also the types of development. This approach later
|
||
reappears in an evolutionist framework, with Perrier's tachygenesis and
|
||
differential rates of growth in allometry: species as kinematic entities that
|
||
are either precocious or retarded. (Even the question of fertility is less one
|
||
of form and function than speed; do the paternal chromosomes arrive early
|
||
enough to be incorporated into the nuclei?) In any case, there is a pure
|
||
plane of immanence, univocality, composition, upon which everything is
|
||
given, upon which unformed elements and materials dance that are distin-
|
||
guished from one another only by their speed and that enter into this or
|
||
that individuated assemblage depending on their connections, their rela-
|
||
tions of movement. A fixed plane of life upon which everything stirs, slows
|
||
down or accelerates. A single abstract Animal for all the assemblages that
|
||
effectuate it. A unique plane of consistency or composition for the cephalo-
|
||
pod and the vertebrate; for the vertebrate to become an Octopus or Cuttle-
|
||
fish, all it would have to do is fold itself in two fast enough to fuse the
|
||
elements of the halves of its back together, then bring its pelvis up to the
|
||
nape of its neck and gather its limbs together into one of its extremities, like
|
||
"a clown who throws his head and shoulders back and walks on his head
|
||
and hands."30 Plication. It is no longer a question of organs and functions,
|
||
and of a transcendent Plane that can preside over their organization only
|
||
by means of analogical relations and types of divergent development. It is a
|
||
question not of organization but of composition; not of development or
|
||
differentiation but of movement and rest, speed and slowness. It is a ques-
|
||
tion of elements and particles, which do or do not arrive fast enough to
|
||
effect a passage, a becoming or jump on the same plane of pure imma-
|
||
nence. And if there are in fact jumps, rifts between assemblages, it is not by
|
||
virtue of their essential irreducibility but rather because there are always
|
||
elements that do not arrive on time, or arrive after everything is over; thus
|
||
it is necessary to pass through fog, to cross voids, to have lead times and
|
||
delays, which are themselves part of the plane of immanence. Even the
|
||
failures are part of the plane. We must try to conceive of this world in which
|
||
a single fixed plane—which we shall call a plane of absolute immobility or
|
||
absolute movement—is traversed by nonformal elements of relative speed
|
||
that enter this or that individuated assemblage depending on their de-
|
||
grees of speed and slowness. A plane of consistency peopled by anony-
|
||
mous matter, by infinite bits of impalpable matter entering into varying
|
||
connections.
|
||
256 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
Children are Spinozists. When Little Hans talks about a "peepee-
|
||
maker," he is referring not to an organ or an organic function but basically
|
||
to a material, in other words, to an aggregate whose elements vary accord-
|
||
ing to its connections, its relations of movement and rest, the different
|
||
individuated assemblages it enters. Does a girl have a peepee-maker? The
|
||
boy says yes, and not by analogy, nor in order to conjure away a fear of cas-
|
||
tration. It is obvious that girls have a peepee-maker because they effec-
|
||
tively pee: a machinic functioning rather than an organic function. Quite
|
||
simply, the same material has different connections, different relations of
|
||
movement and rest, enters different assemblages in the case of the boy and
|
||
the girl (a girl does not pee standing or into the distance). Does a locomo-
|
||
tive have a peepee-maker? Yes, in yet another machinic assemblage. Chairs
|
||
don't have them: but that is because the elements of the chair were not able
|
||
to integrate this material into their relations, or decomposed the relation
|
||
with that material to the point that it yielded something else, a rung, for
|
||
example. It has been noted that for children an organ has "a thousand vicis-
|
||
situdes," that it is "difficult to localize, difficult to identify, it is in turn a
|
||
bone, an engine, excrement, the baby, a hand, daddy's heart..." This is not
|
||
at all because the organ is experienced as a part-object. It is because the
|
||
organ is exactly what its elements make it according to their relation of
|
||
movement or rest, and the way in which this relation combines with or
|
||
splits off from that of neighboring elements. This is not animism, any more
|
||
than it is mechanism; rather, it is universal machinism: a plane of consis-
|
||
tency occupied by an immense abstract machine comprising an infinite
|
||
number of assemblages. Children's questions are poorly understood if they
|
||
are not seen as question-machines; that is why indefinite articles play so
|
||
important a role in these questions (a belly, a child, a horse, a chair, "how is
|
||
a person made?"). Spinozism is the becoming-child of the philosopher. We
|
||
call the longitude of a body the particle aggregates belonging to that body in
|
||
a given relation; these aggregates are part of each other depending on the
|
||
composition of the relation that defines the individuated assemblage of
|
||
the body.
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Spinozist, II. There is another aspect to Spinoza. To every
|
||
relation of movement and rest, speed and slowness grouping together an
|
||
infinity of parts, there corresponds a degree of power. To the relations com-
|
||
posing, decomposing, or modifying an individual there correspond inten-
|
||
sities that affect it, augmenting or diminishing its power to act; these
|
||
intensities come from external parts or from the individual's own parts.
|
||
Affects are becomings. Spinoza asks: What can a body do? We call the lati-
|
||
tude of a body the affects of which it is capable at a given degree of power, or
|
||
rather within the limits of that degree. Latitude is made up of intensive parts
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 257
|
||
|
||
falling under a capacity, and longitude of extensive partsfalling under a rela-
|
||
tion. In the same way that we avoided defining a body by its organs and
|
||
functions, we will avoid defining it by Species or Genus characteristics;
|
||
instead we will seek to count its affects. This kind of study is called
|
||
ethology, and this is the sense in which Spinoza wrote a true Ethics. A race-
|
||
horse is more different from a workhorse than a workhorse is from an ox.
|
||
Von Uexkiill, in defining animal worlds, looks for the active and passive
|
||
affects of which the animal is capable in the individuated assemblage of
|
||
which it is a part. For example, the Tick, attracted by the light, hoists itself
|
||
up to the tip of a branch; it is sensitive to the smell of mammals, and lets
|
||
itself fall when one passes beneath the branch; it digs into its skin, at the
|
||
least hairy place it can find. Just three affects; the rest of the time the tick
|
||
sleeps, sometimes for years on end, indifferent to all that goes on in the
|
||
immense forest. Its degree of power is indeed bounded by two limits: the
|
||
optimal limit of the feast after which it dies, and the pessimal limit of the
|
||
fast as it waits. It will be said that the tick's three affects assume generic and
|
||
specific characteristics, organs and functions, legs and snout. This is true
|
||
from the standpoint of physiology, but not from the standpoint of Ethics.
|
||
Quite the contrary, in Ethics the organic characteristics derive from longi-
|
||
tude and its relations, from latitude and its degrees. We know nothing
|
||
about a body until we know what it can do, in other words, what its affects
|
||
are, how they can or cannot enter into composition with other affects, with
|
||
the affects of another body, either to destroy that body or to be destroyed by
|
||
it, either to exchange actions and passions with it or to join with it in com-
|
||
posing a more powerful body.
|
||
Once again, we turn to children. Note how they talk about animals, and
|
||
are moved by them. They make a list of affects. Little Hans's horse is not
|
||
representative but affective. It is not a member of a species but an element
|
||
or individual in a machinic assemblage: draft horse-omnibus-street. It is
|
||
defined by a list of active and passive affects in the context of the
|
||
individuated assemblage it is part of: having eyes blocked by blinders, hav-
|
||
ing a bit and a bridle, being proud, having a big peepee-maker, pulling
|
||
heavy loads, being whipped, falling, making a din with its legs, biting, etc.
|
||
These affects circulate and are transformed within the assemblage: what a
|
||
horse "can do." They indeed have an optimal limit at the summit of horse-
|
||
power, but also a pessimal threshold: a horse falls down in the street! It can't
|
||
get back on its feet with that heavy load on its back, and the excessive whip-
|
||
ping; a horse is going to die!—this was an ordinary sight in those days
|
||
(Nietzsche, Dostoyevsky, Nijinsky lamented it). So just what is the
|
||
becoming-horse of Little Hans? Hans is also taken up in an assemblage: his
|
||
mother's bed, the paternal element, the house, the cafe across the street, the
|
||
nearby warehouse, the street, the right to go out onto the street, the winning
|
||
258 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL ...
|
||
|
||
of this right, the pride of winning it, but also the dangers of winning it, the
|
||
fall, shame .. . These are not phantasies or subjective reveries: it is not a
|
||
question of imitating a horse, "playing" horse, identifying with one, or
|
||
even experiencing feelings of pity or sympathy. Neither does it have to do
|
||
with an objective analogy between assemblages. The question is whether
|
||
Little Hans can endow his own elements with the relations of movement
|
||
and rest, the affects, that would make it become horse, forms and subjects
|
||
aside. Is there an as yet unknown assemblage that would be neither Hans's
|
||
nor the horse's, but that of the becoming-horse of Hans? An assemblage,
|
||
for example, in which the horse would bare its teeth and Hans might show
|
||
something else, his feet, his legs, his peepee-maker, whatever? And in what
|
||
way would that ameliorate Hans's problem, to what extent would it open a
|
||
way out that had been previously blocked? When Hofmannsthal contem-
|
||
plates the death throes of a rat, it is in him that the animal "bares his teeth at
|
||
monstrous fate." This is not a feeling of pity, as he makes clear; still less an
|
||
identification. It is a composition of speeds and affects involving entirely
|
||
different individuals, a symbiosis; it makes the rat become a thought, a
|
||
feverish thought in the man, at the same time as the man becomes a rat
|
||
gnashing its teeth in its death throes. The rat and the man are in no way the
|
||
same thing, but Being expresses them both in a single meaning in a lan-
|
||
guage that is no longer that of words, in a matter that is no longer that of
|
||
forms, in an affectability that is no longer that of subjects. Unnatural par-
|
||
ticipation. But the plane of composition, the plane of Nature, is precisely
|
||
for participations of this kind, and continually makes and unmakes their
|
||
assemblages, employing every artifice.
|
||
This is not an analogy, or a product of the imagination, but a composi-
|
||
tion of speeds and affects on the plane of consistency: a plan(e), a program,
|
||
or rather a diagram, a problem, a question-machine. Vladimir Slepian for-
|
||
mulates the "problem" in a thoroughly curious text: I'm hungry, always
|
||
hungry, a man should not be hungry, so I'll have to become a dog—but
|
||
how? This will not involve imitating a dog, nor an analogy of relations. I
|
||
must succeed in endowing the parts of my body with relations of speed and
|
||
slowness that will make it become dog, in an original assemblage proceed-
|
||
ing neither by resemblance nor by analogy. For I cannot become dog with-
|
||
out the dog itself becoming something else. Slepian gets the idea of using
|
||
shoes to solve this problem, the artifice of the shoes. If I wear shoes on my
|
||
hands, then their elements will enter into a new relation, resulting in the
|
||
affect or becoming I seek. But how will I be able to tie the shoe on my sec-
|
||
ond hand, once the first is already occupied? With my mouth, which in
|
||
turn receives an investment in the assemblage, becoming a dog muzzle,
|
||
insofar as a dog muzzle is now used to tie shoes. At each stage of the prob-
|
||
lem, what needs to be done is not to compare two organs but to place ele-
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 259
|
||
|
||
ments or materials in a relation that uproots the organ from its specificity,
|
||
making it become "with" the other organ. But this becoming, which has
|
||
already taken in feet, hands, and mouth, will nevertheless fail. It founders
|
||
on the tail. The tail would have had to have been invested, forced to exhibit
|
||
elements common to the sexual organ and the caudal appendage, so that
|
||
the former would be taken up in the becoming-dog of the man at the same
|
||
time as the latter were taken up in a becoming of the dog, in another becom-
|
||
ing that would also be part of the assemblage. The plan(e) fails, Slepian fal-
|
||
ters on this point. The tail remains an organ of the man on the one hand and
|
||
an appendage of the dog on the other; their relations do not enter into com-
|
||
position in the new assemblage. This is where psychoanalytic drift sets in,
|
||
bringing back all the cliches about the tail, the mother, the childhood mem-
|
||
ory of the mother threading needles, all those concrete figures and sym-
|
||
bolic analogies.31 But this is the way Slepian wants it in this fine text. For
|
||
there is a way in which the failure of the plan(e) is part of the plan(e) itself:
|
||
The plan(e) is infinite, you can start it in a thousand different ways; you will
|
||
always find something that comes too late or too early, forcing you to
|
||
recompose all of your relations of speed and slowness, all of your affects,
|
||
and to rearrange the overall assemblage. An infinite undertaking. But there
|
||
is another way in which the plan(e) fails; this time, it is because another
|
||
plan(e) returns full force, breaking the becoming-animal, folding the ani-
|
||
mal back onto the animal and the person onto the person, recognizing only
|
||
resemblances between elements and analogies between relations. Slepian
|
||
confronts both dangers.
|
||
We wish to make a simple point about psychoanalysis: from the begin-
|
||
ning, it has often encountered the question of the becomings-animal of the
|
||
human being: in children, who continually undergo becomings of this
|
||
kind; in fetishism and in particular masochism, which continually con-
|
||
front this problem. The least that can be said is that the psychoanalysts,
|
||
even Jung, did not understand, or did not want to understand. They killed
|
||
becoming-animal, in the adult as in the child. They saw nothing. They see
|
||
the animal as a representative of drives, or a representation of the parents.
|
||
They do not see the reality of a becoming-animal, that it is affect in itself,
|
||
the drive in person, and represents nothing. There exist no other drives
|
||
than the assemblages themselves. There are two classic texts in which
|
||
Freud sees nothing but the father in the becoming-horse of Hans, and
|
||
Ferenczi sees the same in the becoming-cock of Arpad. The horse's blind-
|
||
ers are the father's eyeglasses, the black around its mouth is his mustache,
|
||
its kicks are the parents' "lovemaking." Not one word about Hans's rela-
|
||
tion to the street, on how the street was forbidden to him, on what it is for a
|
||
child to see the spectacle "a horse is proud, a blinded horse pulls, a horse
|
||
falls, a horse is whipped..." Psychoanalysis has no feeling for unnatural
|
||
260 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL. ..
|
||
|
||
participations, nor for the assemblages a child can mount in order to solve
|
||
a problem from which all exits are barred him: a plan(e), not a phantasy.
|
||
Similarly, fewer stupidities would be uttered on the topic of pain, humilia-
|
||
tion, and anxiety in masochism if it were understood that it is the
|
||
becomings-animal that lead the masochism, not the other way around.
|
||
There are always apparatuses, tools, engines involved, there are always
|
||
artifices and constraints used in taking Nature to the fullest. That is
|
||
because it is necessary to annul the organs, to shut them away so that their
|
||
liberated elements can enter into the new relations from which the
|
||
becoming-animal, and the circulation of affects within the machinic
|
||
assemblage, will result. As we have seen elsewhere, this was the case for the
|
||
mask, the bridle, the bit, and the penis sheath in Equus eroticus: paradoxi-
|
||
cally, in the becoming-horse assemblage the man subdues his own "instinc-
|
||
tive" forces while the animal transmits to him its "acquired" forces.
|
||
Reversal, unnatural participation. And the boots of the woman-master
|
||
function to annul the leg as a human organ, to make the elements of the leg
|
||
enter a relation suited to the overall assemblage: "In this way, it will no
|
||
longer be women's legs that have an effect on me . . ,"32 But to break the
|
||
becoming-animal all that is needed is to extract a segment from it, to
|
||
abstract one of its moments, to fail to take into account its internal speeds
|
||
and slownesses, to arrest the circulation of affects. Then nothing remains
|
||
but imaginary resemblances between terms, or symbolic analogies
|
||
between relations. This segment refers to the father, that relation of move-
|
||
ment and rest refers to the primal scene, etc. It must be recognized that psy-
|
||
choanalysis alone is not enough to bring about this breakage. It only brings
|
||
out a danger inherent in becoming. There is always the danger of finding
|
||
yourself "playing" the animal, the domestic Oedipal animal, Miller going
|
||
bowwow and taking a bone, Fitzgerald licking your hand, Slepian returning
|
||
to his mother, or the old man playing horse or dog on an erotic postcard
|
||
from 1900 (and "playing" at being a wild animal would be no better).
|
||
Becomings-animal continually run these dangers.
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Haecceity. A body is not defined by the form that deter-
|
||
mines it nor as a determinate substance or subject nor by the organs it pos-
|
||
sesses or the functions it fulfills. On the plane of consistency, a body is
|
||
defined only by a longitude and a latitude: in other words the sum total of
|
||
the material elements belonging to it under given relations of movement
|
||
and rest, speed and slowness (longitude); the sum total of the intensive
|
||
affects it is capable of at a given power or degree of potential (latitude).
|
||
Nothing but affects and local movements, differential speeds. The credit
|
||
goes to Spinoza for calling attention to these two dimensions of the Body,
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 261
|
||
|
||
and for having defined the plane of Nature as pure longitude and latitude.
|
||
Latitude and longitude are the two elements of a cartography.
|
||
There is a mode of individuation very different from that of a person,
|
||
subject, thing, or substance. We reserve the name haecceity for it.33 A sea-
|
||
son, a winter, a summer, an hour, a date have a perfect individuality lacking
|
||
nothing, even though this individuality is different from that of a thing or a
|
||
subject. They are haecceities in the sense that they consist entirely of rela-
|
||
tions of movement and rest between molecules or particles, capacities to
|
||
affect and be affected. When demonology expounds upon the diabolical
|
||
art of local movements and transports of affect, it also notes the impor-
|
||
tance of rain, hail, wind, pestilential air, or air polluted by noxious parti-
|
||
cles, favorable conditions for these transports. Tales must contain
|
||
haecceities that are not simply emplacements, but concrete individuations
|
||
that have a status of their own and direct the metamorphosis of things and
|
||
subjects. Among types of civilizations, the Orient has many more
|
||
individuations by haecceity than by subjectivity or substantiality: the
|
||
haiku, for example, must include indicators as so many floating lines con-
|
||
stituting a complex individual. In Charlotte Bronte, everything is in terms
|
||
of wind, things, people, faces, loves, words. Lorca's "five in the evening,"
|
||
when love falls and fascism rises. That awful five in the evening! We say,
|
||
"What a story!" "What heat!" "What a life!" to designate a very singular
|
||
individuation. The hours of the day in Lawrence, in Faulkner. A degree of
|
||
heat, an intensity of white, are perfect individualities; and a degree of heat
|
||
can combine in latitude with another degree to form a new individual, as in
|
||
a body that is cold here and hot there depending on its longitude. Norwe-
|
||
gian omelette. A degree of heat can combine with an intensity of white, as
|
||
in certain white skies of a hot summer. This is in no way an individuality of
|
||
the instant, as opposed to the individuality of permanences or durations. A
|
||
tear-off calendar has just as much time as a perpetual calendar, although
|
||
the time in question is not the same. There are animals that live no longer
|
||
than a day or an hour; conversely, a group of years can be as long as the most
|
||
durable subject or object. We can conceive of an abstract time that is equal
|
||
for haecceities and for subjects or things. Between the extreme slownesses
|
||
and vertiginous speeds of geology and astronomy, Michel Tournier places
|
||
meteorology, where meteors live at our pace: "A cloud forms in the sky like
|
||
an image in my brain, the wind blows like I breathe, a rainbow spans the
|
||
horizon for as long as my heart needs to reconcile itself to life, the summer
|
||
passes like vacation drifts by." But is it by chance that in Tournier's novel
|
||
this certitude can come only to a twin hero who is deformed and
|
||
desubjectified, and has acquired a certain ubiquity?34 Even when times are
|
||
abstractly equal, the individuation of a life is not the same as the
|
||
individuation of the subject that leads it or serves as its support. It is not the
|
||
262 O 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
same Plane: in the first case, it is the plane of consistency or of composition
|
||
of haecceities, which knows only speeds and affects; and in the second case,
|
||
it is the altogether different plane of forms, substances, and subjects. And it
|
||
is not in the same time, the same temporality. Aeon: the indefinite time of
|
||
the event, the floating line that knows only speeds and continually divides
|
||
that which transpires into an already-there that is at the same time not-yet-
|
||
here, a simultaneous too-late and too-early, a something that is both going
|
||
to happen and has just happened. Chronos: the time of measure that situ-
|
||
ates things and persons, develops a form, and determines a subject.35
|
||
Boulez distinguishes tempo and nontempo in music: the "pulsed time" of a
|
||
formal and functional music based on values versus the "nonpulsed time"
|
||
of a floating music, both floating and machinic, which has nothing but
|
||
speeds or differences in dynamic.36 In short, the difference is not at all
|
||
between the ephemeral and the durable, nor even between the regular and
|
||
the irregular, but between two modes of individuation, two modes of
|
||
temporality.
|
||
We must avoid an oversimplified conciliation, as though there were on
|
||
the one hand formed subjects, of the thing or person type, and on the other
|
||
hand spatiotemporal coordinates of the haecceity type. For you will yield
|
||
nothing to haecceities unless you realize that that is what you are, and that
|
||
you are nothing but that. When the face becomes a haecceity: "It seemed a
|
||
curious mixture that simply made do with time, weather and these peo-
|
||
ple."37 You are longitude and latitude, a set of speeds and slownesses
|
||
between unformed particles, a set of nonsubjectified affects. You have the
|
||
individuality of a day, a season, a year, a life (regardless of its duration)—a
|
||
climate, a wind, a fog, a swarm, a pack (regardless of its regularity). Or at
|
||
least you can have it, you can reach it. A cloud of locusts carried in by the
|
||
wind at five in the evening; a vampire who goes out at night, a werewolf at
|
||
full moon. It should not be thought that a haecceity consists simply of a
|
||
decor or backdrop that situates subjects, or of appendages that hold things
|
||
and people to the ground. It is the entire assemblage in its individuated
|
||
aggregate that is a haecceity; it is this assemblage that is defined by a longi-
|
||
tude and a latitude, by speeds and affects, independently of forms and sub-
|
||
jects, which belong to another plane. It is the wolf itself, and the horse, and
|
||
the child, that cease to be subjects to become events, in assemblages that
|
||
are inseparable from an hour, a season, an atmosphere, an air, a life. The
|
||
street enters into composition with the horse, just as the dying rat enters
|
||
into composition with the air, and the beast and the full moon enter into
|
||
composition with each other. At most, we may distinguish assemblage
|
||
haecceities (a body considered only as longitude and latitude) and
|
||
interassemblage haecceities, which also mark the potentialities of becom-
|
||
ing within each assemblage (the milieu of intersection of the longitudes
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL.. . D 263
|
||
|
||
and latitudes). But the two are strictly inseparable. Climate, wind, season,
|
||
hour are not of another nature than the things, animals, or people that pop-
|
||
ulate them, follow them, sleep and awaken within them. This should be
|
||
read without a pause: the animal-stalks-at-five-o'clock. The becoming-
|
||
evening, becoming-night of an animal, blood nuptials. Five o'clock is this
|
||
animal! This animal is this place! "The thin dog is running in the road,
|
||
this dog is the road," cries Virginia Woolf. That is how we need to feel.
|
||
Spatiotemporal relations, determinations, are not predicates of the thing
|
||
but dimensions of multiplicities. The street is as much a part of the
|
||
omnibus-horse assemblage as the Hans assemblage the becoming-horse of
|
||
which it initiates. We are all five o'clock in the evening, or another hour, or
|
||
rather two hours simultaneously, the optimal and the pessimal, noon-
|
||
midnight, but distributed in a variable fashion. The plane of consistency
|
||
contains only haecceities, along intersecting lines. Forms and subjects are
|
||
not of that world. Virginia Woolf s walk through the crowd, among the
|
||
taxis. Taking a walk is a haecceity; never again will Mrs. Dalloway say to
|
||
herself, "I am this, I am that, he is this, he is that." And "She felt very young;
|
||
at the same time unspeakably aged. She sliced like a knife through every-
|
||
thing; at the same time was outside, looking o n . . . . She always had the feel-
|
||
ing that it was very, very dangerous to live even one day."38 Haecceity, fog,
|
||
glare. A haecceity has neither beginning nor end, origin nor destination; it
|
||
is always in the middle. It is not made of points, only of lines. It is a
|
||
rhizome.
|
||
And it is not the same language, at least not the same usage of language.
|
||
For if the plane of consistency only has haecceities for content, it also has
|
||
its own particular semiotic to serve as expression. A plane of content and a
|
||
plane of expression. This semiotic is composed above all of proper names,
|
||
verbs in the infinitive and indefinite articles or pronouns. Indefinite article
|
||
+ proper name + infinitive verb constitutes the basic chain of expression,
|
||
correlative to the least formalized contents, from the standpoint of a
|
||
semiotic that has freed itself from both formal signifiances and personal
|
||
subjectifications. In the first place, the verb in the infinitive is in no way
|
||
indeterminate with respect to time; it expresses the floating, nonpulsed
|
||
time proper to Aeon, in other words, the time of the pure event or of becom-
|
||
ing, which articulates relative speeds and slownesses independently of the
|
||
chronometric or chronological values that time assumes in the other
|
||
modes. There is good reason to oppose the infinitive as mode and tense of
|
||
becoming to all of the other modes and tenses, which pertain to Chronos
|
||
since they form pulsations or values of being (the verb "to be" is precisely
|
||
the only one that has no infinitive, or rather the infinitive of which is only
|
||
an indeterminate, empty expression, taken abstractly to designate the sum
|
||
total of definite modes and tenses).39 Second, the proper name is no way
|
||
264 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
the indicator of a subject; thus it seems useless to ask whether its operation
|
||
resembles the nomination of a species, according to whether the subject is
|
||
considered to be of another nature than that of the Form under which it is
|
||
classified, or only the ultimate act of that Form, the limit of classifica-
|
||
tion.40 The proper name does not indicate a subject; nor does a noun take
|
||
on the value of a proper name as a function of a form or a species. The
|
||
proper name fundamentally designates something that is of the order of
|
||
the event, of becoming or of the haecceity. It is the military men and meteo-
|
||
rologists who hold the secret of proper names, when they give them to a
|
||
strategic operation or a hurricane. The proper name is not the subject of a
|
||
tense but the agent of an infinitive. It marks a longitude and a latitude. If
|
||
Tick, Wolf, Horse, etc., are true proper names, they are so not by virtue of
|
||
the specific and generic denominators that characterize them but of the
|
||
speeds that compose them and the affects that fill them; it is by virtue of the
|
||
event they are in themselves and in the assemblages—the becoming-horse
|
||
of Little Hans, the becoming-wolf of the Were [which etymologically
|
||
means "man"—Trans.], the becoming-tick of the Stoic (other proper
|
||
names).
|
||
Third, the indefinite article and the indefinite pronoun are no more
|
||
indeterminate than the infinitive. Or rather they are lacking a determina-
|
||
tion only insofar as they are applied to a form that is itself indeterminate,
|
||
or to a determinable subject. On the other hand, they lack nothing when
|
||
they introduce haecceities, events, the individuation of which does not
|
||
pass into a form and is not effected by a subject. The indefinite then has
|
||
maximum determination: once upon a time; a child is being beaten; a horse
|
||
is falling . . . Here, the elements in play find their individuation in the
|
||
assemblage of which they are a part, independent of the form of their con-
|
||
cept and the subjectivity of their person. We have remarked several times
|
||
the extent to which children use the indefinite not as something indetermi-
|
||
nate but, on the contrary, as an individuating function within a collectivity.
|
||
That is why we are dumbfounded by the efforts of psychoanalysis, which
|
||
desperately wants there to be something definite hidden behind the indefi-
|
||
nite, a possessive, a person. When the child says "a belly," "a horse," "how
|
||
do people grow up?" "someone is beating a child," the psychoanalyst hears
|
||
"my belly," "the father," "will I grow up to be like daddy?" The psychoana-
|
||
lyst asks: Who is being beaten, and by whom?41 Even linguistics is not
|
||
immune from the same prejudice, inasmuch as it is inseparable from a
|
||
personology; according to linguistics, in addition to the indefinite -article
|
||
and the pronoun, the third-person pronoun also lacks the determination of
|
||
subjectivity that is proper to the first two persons and is supposedly the
|
||
necessary condition for all enunciation.42
|
||
We believe on the contrary that the third person indefinite, HE, THEY,
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 265
|
||
|
||
implies no indetermination from this point of view; it ties the statement to
|
||
a collective assemblage, as its necessary condition, rather than to a subject
|
||
of the enunciation. Blanchot is correct in saying that ONE and HE—one is
|
||
dying, he is unhappy—in no way take the place of a subject, but instead do
|
||
away with any subject in favor of an assemblage of the haecceity type that
|
||
carries or brings out the event insofar as it is unformed and incapable of
|
||
being effectuated by persons ("something happens to them that they can
|
||
only get a grip on again by letting go of their ability to say I").43 The HE does
|
||
not represent a subject but rather makes a diagram of an assemblage. It
|
||
does not overcode statements, it does not transcend them as do the first
|
||
two persons; on the contrary, it prevents them from falling under the tyr-
|
||
anny of subjective or signifying constellations, under the regime of empty
|
||
redundancies. The contents of the chains of expression it articulates are
|
||
those that can be assembled for a maximum number of occurrences and
|
||
becomings. "They arrive like fate ... where do they come from, how have
|
||
they pushed this far .. .?"44 He or one, indefinite article, proper name,
|
||
infinitive verb: A HANS TO BECOME HORSE, A PACK NAMED WOLF TO LOOK AT
|
||
HE, ONE TO DIE, WASP TO MEET ORCHID, THEY ARRIVE HUNS. Classified ads,
|
||
telegraphic machines on the plane of consistency (once again, we are
|
||
reminded of the procedures of Chinese poetry and the rules for translation
|
||
suggested by the best commentators).45
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Plan(e) Maker. Perhaps there are two planes, or two ways
|
||
of conceptualizing the plane. The plane can be a hidden principle, which
|
||
makes visible what is seen and audible what is heard, etc., which at every
|
||
instant causes the given to be given, in this or that state, at this or that
|
||
moment. But the plane itself is not given. It is by nature hidden. It can only
|
||
be inferred, induced, concluded from that to which it gives rise (simultane-
|
||
ously or successively, synchronically or diachronically). A plane of this
|
||
kind is as much a plan(e) of organization as of development: it is structural
|
||
or genetic, and both at once, structure and genesis, the structural plan(e) of
|
||
formed organizations with their developments, the genetic plan(e) of evo-
|
||
lutionary developments with their organizations. These are only nuances
|
||
of this first conception of the plane. To accord these nuances too much
|
||
importance would prevent us from grasping something more important;
|
||
that the plan(e), conceived or made in this fashion, always concerns the
|
||
development of forms and the formation of subjects. A hidden structure
|
||
necessary for forms, a secret signifier necessary for subjects. It ensues that
|
||
the plan(e) itself will not be given. It exists only in a supplementary dimen-
|
||
sion to that to which it gives rise (n +1). This makes it a teleological plan(e),
|
||
a design, a mental principle. It is a plan(e) of transcendence. It is a plan(e)
|
||
of analogy, either because it assigns the eminent term of a development or
|
||
266 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . ..
|
||
|
||
because it establishes the proportional relations of a structure. It may be in
|
||
the mind of a god, or in the unconscious of life, of the soul, or of language: it
|
||
is always concluded from its own effects. It is always inferred. Even if it is
|
||
said to be immanent, it is so only by absence, analogically (metaphorically,
|
||
metonymically, etc.). The tree is given in the seed, but as a function of a
|
||
plan(e) that is not given. The same applies to music. The developmental or
|
||
organizational principle does not appear in itself, in a direct relation with
|
||
that which develops or is organized: There is a transcendent compositional
|
||
principle that is not of the nature of sound, that is not "audible" by itself or
|
||
for itself. This opens the way for all possible interpretations. Forms and
|
||
their developments, and subjects and their formations, relate to a plan(e)
|
||
that operates as a transcendent unity or hidden principle. The plan(e) can
|
||
always be described, but as a part aside, as ungiven in that to which it gives
|
||
rise. Is this not how even Balzac, even Proust, describe their work's plan(e)
|
||
of organization or development, as though in a metalanguage? Is not
|
||
Stockhausen also obliged to describe the structure of his sound forms as
|
||
existing "alongside" them, since he is unable to make it audible? Life
|
||
plan(e), music plan(e), writing plan(e), it's all the same: a plan(e) that can-
|
||
not be given as such, that can only be inferred from the forms it develops
|
||
and the subjects it forms, since it is for these forms and these subjects.
|
||
Then there is an altogether different plane, or an altogether different
|
||
conception of the plane. Here, there are no longer any forms or develop-
|
||
ments of forms; nor are there subjects or the formation of subjects. There is
|
||
no structure, any more than there is genesis. There are only relations of
|
||
movement and rest, speed and slowness between unformed elements, or at
|
||
least between elements that are relatively unformed, molecules and
|
||
particles of all kinds. There are only haecceities, affects, subjectless indi-
|
||
viduations that constitute collective assemblages. Nothing develops, but
|
||
things arrive late or early, and form this or that assemblage depending on
|
||
their compositions of speed. Nothing subjectifies, but haecceities form
|
||
according to compositions of nonsubjectified powers or affects. We call
|
||
this plane, which knows only longitudes and latitudes, speeds and haec-
|
||
ceities, the plane of consistency or composition (as opposed to the plan(e)
|
||
of organization or development). It is necessarily a plane of immanence
|
||
and univocality. We therefore call it the plane of Nature, although nature
|
||
has nothing to do with it, since on this plane there is no distinction between
|
||
the natural and the artificial. However many dimensions it may have, it
|
||
never has a supplementary dimension to that which transpires upon it.
|
||
That alone makes it natural and immanent. The same goes for the principle
|
||
of contradiction: this plane could also be called the plane of
|
||
noncontradiction. The plane of consistency could be called the plane of
|
||
nonconsistency. It is a geometrical plane, no longer tied to a mental design
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 267
|
||
|
||
but to an abstract design. Its number of dimensions continually increases
|
||
as what happens happens, but even so it loses nothing of its planitude. It is
|
||
thus a plane of proliferation, peopling, contagion; but this proliferation of
|
||
material has nothing to do with an evolution, the development of a form or
|
||
the filiation of forms. Still less is it a regression leading back to a principle.
|
||
It is on the contrary an involution, in which form is constantly being dis-
|
||
solved, freeing times and speeds. It is a fixed plane, a fixed sound plane, or
|
||
visual plane, or writing plane, etc. Here, fixed does not mean immobile: it
|
||
is the absolute state of movement as well as of rest, from which all relative
|
||
speeds and slownesses spring, and nothing but them. Certain modern
|
||
musicians oppose the transcendent plan(e) of organization, which is said
|
||
to have dominated all of Western classical music, to the immanent sound
|
||
plane, which is always given along with that to which it gives rise, brings the
|
||
imperceptible to perception, and carries only differential speeds and
|
||
slownesses in a kind of molecular lapping: the work of art must mark sec-
|
||
onds, tenths and hundredths of seconds.46 Or rather it is a question of a free-
|
||
ing of time, Aeon, a nonpulsed time for a floating music, as Boulez says, an
|
||
electronic music in which forms are replaced by pure modifications of
|
||
speed. It is undoubtedly John Cage who first and most perfectly deployed
|
||
this fixed sound plane, which affirms a process against all structure and
|
||
genesis, a floating time against pulsed time or tempo, experimentation
|
||
against any kind of interpretation, and in which silence as sonorous rest
|
||
also marks the absolute state of movement. The same could be said of
|
||
the fixed visual plane: Godard, for example, effectively carries the fixed
|
||
plane of cinema to this state where forms dissolve, and all that subsists are
|
||
tiny variations of speed between movements in composition. Nathalie
|
||
Sarraute, for her part, proposes a clear distinction between two planes of
|
||
writing: a transcendent plan(e) that organizes and develops forms (genres,
|
||
themes, motifs) and assigns and develops subjects (personages, characters,
|
||
feelings); and an altogether different plane that liberates the particles of an
|
||
anonymous matter, allowing them to communicate through the "enve-
|
||
lope" of forms and subjects, retaining between them only relations of
|
||
movement and rest, speed and slowness, floating affects, so that the plane
|
||
itself is perceived at the same time as it allows us to perceive the impercep-
|
||
tible (the microplane, the molecular plane).47 So from the point of view of a
|
||
well-founded abstraction, we can make it seem as though the two planes,
|
||
the two conceptions of the plane, were in clear and absolute opposition.
|
||
From this point of view, we can say, You can see the difference between the
|
||
following two types of propositions: (1) forms develop and subjects form as
|
||
a function of a plan(e) that can only be inferred (the planfe] of organi-
|
||
zation-development); (2) there are only speeds and slownesses between
|
||
unformed elements, and affects between nonsubjectified powers, as a func-
|
||
268 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
tion of a plane that is necessarily given at the same time as that to which it
|
||
gives rise (the plane of consistency or composition).48
|
||
Let us consider three major cases from nineteenth-century German lit-
|
||
erature, Holderlin, Kleist, and Nietzsche. First, Holderlin's extraordinary
|
||
composition, Hyperion, as analyzed by Robert Rovini: the importance of
|
||
haecceities of the season type. These constitute, in two different ways, the
|
||
"frame of the narrative" (plan[e]) and the details of what happens within
|
||
that frame (the assemblages and interassemblages).49 He also notes how the
|
||
succession of the seasons and the superposition of the same season from
|
||
different years dissolves forms and persons and gives rise to movements,
|
||
speeds, delays, and affects, as if as the narrative progressed something were
|
||
escaping from an impalpable matter. And perhaps also the relation to a
|
||
"realpolitik," to a war machine, to a musical machine of dissonance.
|
||
Kleist: everything with him, in his writing as in his life, becomes speed
|
||
and slowness. A succession of catatonic freezes and extreme velocities,
|
||
fainting spells and shooting arrows. Sleep on your steed, then take off at a
|
||
gallop. Jump from one assemblage to another, with the aid of a faint, by
|
||
crossing a void. Kleist multiplies "life plan(e)s," but his voids and failures,
|
||
his leaps, earthquakes, and plagues are always included on a single plane.
|
||
The plane is not a principle of organization but a means of transportation.
|
||
No form develops, no subject forms; affects are displaced, becomings cata-
|
||
pult forward and combine into blocks, like the becoming-woman of Achil-
|
||
les and the becoming-dog of Penthesilea. Kleist offers a wonderful
|
||
explanation of how forms and persons are only appearances produced by
|
||
the displacement of a center of gravity on an abstract line, and by the con-
|
||
junction of these lines on a plane of immanence. He is fascinated by bears;
|
||
they are impossible to fool because their cruel little eyes see through
|
||
appearances to the true "soul of movement," the Gemiit or nonsubjective
|
||
affect: the becoming-bear of Kleist. Even death can only be conceptualized
|
||
as the intersection of elementary reactions of different speeds. A skull
|
||
exploding, one of Kleist's obsessions. All of Kleist's work is traversed by a
|
||
war machine invoked against the State, by a musical machine invoked
|
||
against painting or the "picture." It is odd how Goethe and Hegel hated this
|
||
new kind of writing. Because for them the plan(e) must indissolubly be a
|
||
harmonious development of Form and a regulated formation of the Sub-
|
||
ject, personage, or character (the sentimental education, the interior and
|
||
substantial solidity of the character, the harmony or analogy of the forms
|
||
and continuity of development, the cult of the State, etc.). Their concep-
|
||
tion of the Plane is totally opposed to that of Kleist. The anti-Goetheism,
|
||
anti-Hegelianism of Kleist, and already of Holderlin. Goethe gets to the
|
||
crux of the matter when he reproaches Kleist for simultaneously setting up
|
||
a pure "stationary process" that is like the fixed plane, introducing voids
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 269
|
||
|
||
and jumps that prevent any development of a central character, and mobi-
|
||
lizing a violence of affects that causes an extreme confusion of feelings.50
|
||
Nietzsche does the same thing by different means. There is no longer
|
||
any development of forms or formation of subjects. He criticizes Wagner
|
||
for retaining too much harmonic form, and too many pedagogical person-
|
||
ages, or "characters": too much Hegel and Goethe. Now Bizet, on the other
|
||
hand, Nietzsche says . . . It seems to us that fragmentary writing is not so
|
||
much the issue in Nietzsche. It is instead speeds and slownesses: not writ-
|
||
ing slowly or rapidly, but rather writing, and everything else besides, as a
|
||
production of speeds and slownesses between particles. No form will resist
|
||
that, no character or subject will survive it. Zarathustra is only speeds and
|
||
slownesses, and the eternal return, the life of the eternal return, is the first
|
||
great concrete freeing of nonpulsed time. Ecce Homo has only individ-
|
||
uations by haecceities. It is inevitable that the Plan(e), thus conceived, will
|
||
always fail, but that the failures will be an integral part of the plan(e): See
|
||
the multitude of plans for The Will to Power. For a given aphorism, it is
|
||
always possible, even necessary, to introduce new relations of speed and
|
||
slowness between its elements that truly make it change assemblages, jump
|
||
from one assemblage to the next (the issue is therefore not the fragment).
|
||
As Cage says, it is of the nature of the plan(e) that it fail.51 Precisely because
|
||
it is not a plan(e) of organization, development, or formation, but of
|
||
nonvoluntary transmutation. Or Boulez: "Program the machine so that
|
||
each time a tape is played on it, it produces different time characteristics."
|
||
So the plan(e)—life plan(e), writing plan(e), music plan(e)—must neces-
|
||
sarily fail for it is impossible to be faithful to it; but the failures are a part of
|
||
the plan(e) for the plan(e) expands or shrinks along with the dimensions of
|
||
that which it deploys in each instance (planitude of n dimensions). A
|
||
strange machine that is simultaneously a machine of war, music, and
|
||
contagion-proliferation-involution.
|
||
Why does the opposition between the two kinds of planes lead to a still
|
||
more abstract hypothesis? Because one continually passes from one to the
|
||
other, by unnoticeable degrees and without being aware of it, or one be-
|
||
comes aware of it only afterward. Because one continually reconstitutes
|
||
one plane atop another, or extricates one from the other. For example, all
|
||
we need to do is to sink the floating plane of immanence, bury it in the
|
||
depths of Nature instead of allowing it to play freely on the surface, for it to
|
||
pass to the other side and assume the role of a ground that can no longer be
|
||
anything more than a principle of analogy from the standpoint of organiza-
|
||
tion, and a law of continuity from the standpoint of development.52 The
|
||
plane of organization or development effectively covers what we have
|
||
called stratification: Forms and subjects, organs and functions, are
|
||
"strata" or relations between strata. The plane of consistency or imma-
|
||
270 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL.. .
|
||
|
||
nence, on the other hand, implies a destratification of all of Nature, by
|
||
even the most artificial of means. The plane of consistency is the body
|
||
without organs. Pure relations of speed and slowness between particles
|
||
imply movements of deterritorialization, just as pure affects imply an
|
||
enterprise of desubjectification. Moreover, the plane of consistency does
|
||
not preexist the movements of deterritorialization that unravel it, the lines
|
||
of flight that draw it and cause it to rise to the surface, the becomings that
|
||
compose it. The plane of organization is constantly working away at the
|
||
plane of consistency, always trying to plug the lines of flight, stop or inter-
|
||
rupt the movements of deterritorialization, weigh them down, restratify
|
||
them, reconstitute forms and subjects in a dimension of depth. Conversely,
|
||
the plane of consistency is constantly extricating itself from the plane of
|
||
organization, causing particles to spin off the strata, scrambling forms by
|
||
dint of speed or slowness, breaking down functions by means of assem-
|
||
blages or microassemblages. But once again, so much caution is needed to
|
||
prevent the plane of consistency from becoming a pure plane of abolition
|
||
or death, to prevent the involution from turning into a regression to the
|
||
undifferentiated. Is it not necessary to retain a minimum of strata, a mini-
|
||
mum of forms and functions, a minimal subject from which to extract
|
||
materials, affects, and assemblages?
|
||
In fact, the opposition we should set up between the two planes is that
|
||
between two abstract poles: for example, to the transcendent, organiza-
|
||
tional plane of Western music based on sound forms and their develop-
|
||
ment, we oppose the immanent plane of consistency of Eastern music,
|
||
composed of speeds and slownesses, movements and rest. In keeping with
|
||
our concrete hypothesis, the whole becoming of Western music, all musical
|
||
becoming, implies a minimum of sound forms and even of melodic and
|
||
harmonic functions; speeds and slownesses are made to pass across them,
|
||
and it is precisely these speeds and slownesses that reduce the forms and
|
||
functions to the minimum. Beethoven produced the most astonishing
|
||
polyphonic richness with relatively scanty themes of three or four notes.
|
||
There is a material proliferation that goes hand in hand with a dissolution
|
||
of form (involution) but is at the same time accompanied by a continuous
|
||
development of form. Perhaps Schumann's genius is the most striking case
|
||
of form being developed only for the relations of speed and slowness one
|
||
materially and emotionally assigns it. Music has always submitted its
|
||
forms and motifs to temporal transformations, augmentations or diminu-
|
||
tions, slowdowns or accelerations, which do not occur solely according to
|
||
laws of organization or even of development. Expanding and contracting
|
||
microintervals are at play within coded intervals. Wagner and the post-
|
||
Wagnerians free variations of speed between sound particles to an even
|
||
greater extent. Ravel and Debussy retain just enough form to shatter it,
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 271
|
||
|
||
affect it, modify it through speeds and slownesses. Bolero is the classic
|
||
example, nearly a caricature, of a machinic assemblage that preserves a
|
||
minimum of form in order to take it to the bursting point. Boulez speaks of
|
||
proliferations of little motifs, accumulations of little notes that proceed
|
||
kinematically and affectively, sweeping away a simple form by adding indi-
|
||
cations of speed to it; this allows one to produce extremely complex
|
||
dynamic relations on the basis of intrinsically simple formal relations.
|
||
Even a rubato by Chopin cannot be reproduced because it will have differ-
|
||
ent time characteristics at each playing.53 It is as though an immense plane
|
||
of consistency of variable speed were forever sweeping up forms and func-
|
||
tions, forms and subjects, extracting from them particles and affects. A
|
||
clock keeping a whole assortment of times.
|
||
What is a girl, what is a group of girls? Proust at least has shown us once
|
||
and for all that their individuation, collective or singular, proceeds not by
|
||
subjectivity but by haecceity, pure haecceity. "Fugitive beings." They are
|
||
pure relations of speeds and slownesses, and nothing else. A girl is late on
|
||
account of her speed: she did too many things, crossed too many spaces in
|
||
relation to the relative time of the person waiting for her. Thus her apparent
|
||
slowness is transformed into the breakneck speed of our waiting. It must be
|
||
said in this connection, and for the whole of the Recherche du temps perdu,
|
||
that Swann does not at all occupy the same position as the narrator. Swann
|
||
is not a rough sketch or precursor of the narrator, except secondarily and at
|
||
rare moments. They are not at all on the same plane. Swann is always think-
|
||
ing and feeling in terms of subjects, forms, resemblances between subjects,
|
||
and correspondences between forms. For him, one of Odette's lies is a form
|
||
whose secret subjective content must be discovered, provoking amateur
|
||
detective activity. To him Vinteuil's music is a form that must evoke some-
|
||
thing else, fall back on something else, echo other forms, whether paint-
|
||
ings, faces, or landscapes. Although the narrator may follow in Swann's
|
||
footsteps, he is nonetheless in a different element, on a different plane. One
|
||
of Albertine's lies is nearly devoid of content; it tends on the contrary to
|
||
merge with the emission of a particle issuing from the eyes of the beloved, a
|
||
particle that stands only for itself and travels too fast through the narrator's
|
||
auditory or visual field. This molecular speed is unbearable because it
|
||
indicates a distance, a proximity where Albertine would like to be, and
|
||
already is.54 So that the narrator's pose is not principally that of the investi-
|
||
gating detective but (a very different figure) that of the jailer. How can he
|
||
become master of speed, how can he stand it nervously (as a headache) and
|
||
perceptually (as a flash)? How can he build a prison for Albertine? Jealousy
|
||
is different in Swann and the narrator, as is the perception of music:
|
||
Vinteuil gradually ceases to be apprehended in terms of forms and compa-
|
||
rable subjects, and assumes incredible speeds and slownesses that combine
|
||
272 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
on a plane of consistency of variation, the plane of music and of the
|
||
Recherche (just as Wagnerian motifs abandon all fixity of form and all
|
||
assignation of personages). It is as though Swann's desperate efforts to
|
||
reterritorialize the flow of things (to reterritorialize Odette on a secret,
|
||
painting on a face, music on the Bois de Boulogne) were replaced by the
|
||
sped-up movement of deterritorialization, by a linear speedup of the
|
||
abstract machine, sweeping away faces and landscapes, and then love, jeal-
|
||
ousy, painting, and music itself, according to increasingly stronger coeffi-
|
||
cients that nourish the Work at risk of dissolving everything and dying. For
|
||
the narrator, despite partial victories, fails in his project; that project was
|
||
not at all to regain time or to force back memories, but to become master of
|
||
speeds to the rhythm of his asthma. It was to face annihilation. But another
|
||
outcome was possible, or was made possible by Proust.
|
||
|
||
Memories of a Molecule. Becoming-animal is only one becoming among
|
||
others. A kind of order or apparent progression can be established for the
|
||
segments of becoming in which we find ourselves; becoming-woman,
|
||
becoming-child; becoming-animal, -vegetable, or -mineral; becomings-
|
||
molecular of all kinds, becomings-particles. Fibers lead us from one to the
|
||
other, transform one into the other as they pass through doors and across
|
||
thresholds. Singing or composing, painting, writing have no other aim: to
|
||
unleash these becomings. Especially music; music is traversed by a
|
||
becoming-woman, becoming-child, and not only at the level of themes and
|
||
motifs: the little refrain, children's games and dances, childhood scenes.
|
||
Instrumentation and orchestration are permeated by becomings-animal,
|
||
above all becomings-bird, but many others besides. The lapping, wailing of
|
||
molecular discordances have always been present, even if instrumental
|
||
evolution with other factors is now giving them growing importance, as the
|
||
value of a new threshold for a properly musical content: the sound mole-
|
||
cule, relations of speed and slowness between particles. Becomings-animal
|
||
plunge into becomings-molecular. This raises all kinds of questions.
|
||
In a way, we must start at the end: all becomings are already molecular.
|
||
That is because becoming is not to imitate or identify with something or
|
||
someone. Nor is it to proportion formal relations. Neither of these two fig-
|
||
ures of analogy is applicable to becoming: neither the imitation of a subject
|
||
nor the proportionality of a form. Starting from the forms one has, the sub-
|
||
ject one is, the organs one has, or the functions one fulfills, becoming is to
|
||
extract particles between which one establishes the relations of movement
|
||
and rest, speed and slowness that are closest to what one is becoming, and
|
||
through which one becomes. This is the sense in which becoming is the
|
||
process of desire. This principle of proximity or approximation is entirely
|
||
particular and reintroduces no analogy whatsoever. It indicates as rigor-
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 273
|
||
|
||
ously as possible a zone ofproximity55 or copres23 46 59 95 131 155 157 166 187 203 205 212 228 238 371 434 444 494 507 521 ously as possible a zone ofproximity55 or copresence of a particle, the move- ence of a particle, the move-
|
||
ment into which any particle that enters the zone is drawn. Louis Wolfson
|
||
embarks upon a strange undertaking: a schizophrenic, he translates as
|
||
quickly as possible each phrase in his maternal language into foreign words
|
||
with similar sound and meaning; an anorexic, he rushes to the refrigerator,
|
||
tears open the packages and snatches their contents, stuffing himself as
|
||
quickly as possible.56 It would be false to believe that he needs to borrow
|
||
"disguised" words from foreign languages. Rather, he snatches from his
|
||
own language verbal particles that can no longer belong to the form of that
|
||
language, just as he snatches from food alimentary particles that no longer
|
||
act as formed nutritional substances; the two kinds of particles enter into
|
||
proximity. We could also put it this way: Becoming is to emit particles that
|
||
take on certain relations of movement and rest because they enter a partic-
|
||
ular zone of proximity. Or, it is to emit particles that enter that zone
|
||
because they take on those relations. A haecceity is inseparable from the
|
||
fog and mist that depend on a molecular zone, a corpuscular space. Prox-
|
||
imity is a notion, at once topological and quantal, that marks a belonging to
|
||
the same molecule, independently of the subjects considered and the forms
|
||
determined.
|
||
Scherer and Hocquenghem made this essential point in their reconsid-
|
||
eration of the problem of wolf-children. Of course, it is not a question of a
|
||
real production, as if the child "really" became an animal; nor is it a ques-
|
||
tion of a resemblance, as if the child imitated animals that really raised it;
|
||
nor is it a question of a symbolic metaphor, as if the autistic child that was
|
||
abandoned or lost merely became the "analogue" of an animal. Scherer
|
||
and Hocquenghem are right to expose this false reasoning, which is based
|
||
on a culturalism or moralism upholding the irreducibility of the human
|
||
order: Because the child has not been transformed into an animal, it must
|
||
only have a metaphorical relation to it, induced by the child's illness or
|
||
rejection. For their own part, they appeal to an objective zone of indetermi-
|
||
nation or uncertainty, "something shared or indiscernible," a proximity
|
||
"that makes it impossible to say where the boundary between the human
|
||
and animal lies," not only in the case of autistic children, but for all chil-
|
||
dren; it is as though, independent of the evolution carrying them toward
|
||
adulthood, there were room in the child for other becomings, "other con-
|
||
temporaneous possibilities" that are not regressions but creative involu-
|
||
tions bearing witness to "an inhumanity immediately experienced in the
|
||
body as such" unnatural nuptials "outside the programmed body." There
|
||
is a reality of becoming-animal, even though one does not in reality become
|
||
animal. It is useless, then, to raise the objection that the dog-child only
|
||
plays dog within the limits of his formal constitution, and does nothing
|
||
canine that another human being could not have done if he or she had so
|
||
274 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
desired. For what needs to be explained is precisely the fact that all chil-
|
||
dren, and even many adults, do it to a greater or lesser degree, and in so
|
||
doing bear witness to an inhuman connivance with the animal, rather than
|
||
an Oedipal symbolic community.57 Neither should it be thought that chil-
|
||
dren who graze, or eat dirt or raw flesh, are merely getting the vitamins and
|
||
minerals they need. It is a question of composing a body with the animal, a
|
||
body without organs defined by zones of intensity or proximity. Where
|
||
does this objective indetermination or indiscernibility of which Scherer
|
||
and Hocquenghem speak come from?
|
||
An example: Do not imitate a dog, but make your organism enter into
|
||
composition with something else in such a way that the particles emitted
|
||
from the aggregate thus composed will be canine as a function of the rela-
|
||
tion of movement and rest, or of molecular proximity, into which they
|
||
enter. Clearly, this something else can be quite varied, and be more or less
|
||
directly related to the animal in question: it can be the animal's natural
|
||
food (dirt and worm), or its exterior relations with other animals (you can
|
||
become-dog with cats, or become-monkey with a horse), or an apparatus or
|
||
prosthesis to which a person subjects the animal (muzzle and reindeer,
|
||
etc.), or something that does not even have a localizable relation to the ani-
|
||
mal in question. For this last case, we have seen how Slepian bases his
|
||
attempt to become-dog on the idea of tying shoes to his hands using his
|
||
mouth-muzzle. Philippe Gavi cites the performances of Lolito, an eater of
|
||
bottles, earthenware, porcelains, iron, and even bicycles, who declares: "I
|
||
consider myself half-animal, half-man. More animal than man. I love ani-
|
||
mals, dogs especially, I feel a bond with them. My teeth have adapted; in
|
||
fact, when I don't eat glass or iron, my jaw aches like a young dog's that
|
||
craves to chew a bone."58 If we interpret the word "like" as a metaphor, or
|
||
propose a structural analogy of relations (man-iron = dog-bone), we under-
|
||
stand nothing of becoming. The word "like" is one of those words that
|
||
change drastically in meaning and function when they are used in connec-
|
||
tion with haecceities, when they are made into expressions of becomings
|
||
instead of signified states or signifying relations. A dog may exercise its jaw
|
||
on iron, but when it does it is using its jaw as a molar organ. When Lolito
|
||
eats iron, it is totally different: he makes his jaw enter into composition
|
||
with the iron in such a way that he himself becomes the jaw of a molecular
|
||
dog. The actor Robert De Niro walks "like" a crab in a certain film
|
||
sequence; but, he says, it is not a question of his imitating a crab; it is a ques-
|
||
tion of making something that has to do with the crab enter into composi-
|
||
tion with the image, with the speed of the image.59 That is the essential
|
||
point for us: you become-animal only if, by whatever means or elements,
|
||
you emit corpuscles that enter the relation of movement and rest of the ani-
|
||
mal particles, or what amounts to the same thing, that enter the zone of
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 275
|
||
|
||
proximity of the animal molecule. You become animal only molecularly.
|
||
You do not become a barking molar dog, but by barking, if it is done with
|
||
enough feeling, with enough necessity and composition, you emit a molec-
|
||
ular dog. Man does not become wolf, or vampire, as if he changed molar
|
||
species; the vampire and werewolf are becomings of man, in other words,
|
||
proximities between molecules in composition, relations of movement
|
||
and rest, speed and slowness between emitted particles. Of course there are
|
||
werewolves and vampires, we say this with all our heart; but do not look for
|
||
a resemblance or analogy to the animal, for this is becoming-animal in
|
||
action, the production of the molecular animal (whereas the "real" animal
|
||
is trapped in its molar form and subjectivity). It is within us that the animal
|
||
bares its teeth like Hofmannsthal's rat, or the flower opens its petals; but
|
||
this is done by corpuscular emission, by molecular proximity, and not by
|
||
the imitation of a subject or a proportionality of form. Albertine can always
|
||
imitate a flower, but it is when she is sleeping and enters into composition
|
||
with the particles of sleep that her beauty spot and the texture of her skin
|
||
enter a relation of rest and movement that place her in the zone of a molec-
|
||
ular vegetable: the becoming-plant of Albertine. And it is when she is held
|
||
prisoner that she emits the particles of a bird. And it is when she flees,
|
||
launches down a line of flight, that she becomes-horse, even if it is the horse
|
||
of death.
|
||
Yes, all becomings are molecular: the animal, flower, or stone one
|
||
becomes are molecular collectivities, haecceities, not molar subjects,
|
||
objects, or form that we know from the outside and recognize from experi-
|
||
ence, through science, or by habit. If this is true, then we must say the same
|
||
of things human: there is a becoming-woman, a becoming-child, that do
|
||
not resemble the woman or the child as clearly distinct molar entities (al-
|
||
though it is possible—only possible—for the woman or child to occupy
|
||
privileged positions in relation to these becomings). What we term a molar
|
||
entity is, for example, the woman as defined by her form, endowed with
|
||
organs and functions and assigned as a subject. Becoming-woman is not
|
||
imitating this entity or even transforming oneself into it. We are not, how-
|
||
ever, overlooking the importance of imitation, or moments of imitation,
|
||
among certain homosexual males, much less the prodigious attempt at a
|
||
real transformation on the part of certain transvestites. All we are saying is
|
||
that these indissociable aspects of becoming-woman must first be under-
|
||
stood as a function of something else: not imitating or assuming the female
|
||
form, but emitting particles that enter the relation of movement and rest,
|
||
or the zone of proximity, of a microfemininity, in other words, that produce
|
||
in us a molecular woman, create the molecular woman. We do not mean to
|
||
say that a creation of this kind is the prerogative of the man, but on the con-
|
||
trary that the woman as a molar entity has to become-woman in order that
|
||
276 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
the man also becomes- or can become-woman. It is, of course, indispensa-
|
||
ble for women to conduct a molar politics, with a view to winning back
|
||
their own organism, their own history, their own subjectivity: "we as
|
||
women .. ." makes its appearance as a subject of enunciation. But it is dan-
|
||
gerous to confine oneself to such a subject, which does not function with-
|
||
out drying up a spring or stopping a flow. The song of life is often intoned
|
||
by the driest of women, moved by ressentiment, the will to power and cold
|
||
mothering. Just as a dessicated child makes a much better child, there
|
||
being no childhood flow emanating from it any longer. It is no more ade-
|
||
quate to say that each sex contains the other and must develop the opposite
|
||
pole in itself. Bisexuality is no better a concept than the separateness of the
|
||
sexes. It is as deplorable to miniaturize, internalize the binary machine as
|
||
it is to exacerbate it; it does not extricate us from it. It is thus necessary to
|
||
conceive of a molecular women's politics that slips into molar confronta-
|
||
tions, and passes under or through them.
|
||
When Virginia Woolf was questioned about a specifically women's writ-
|
||
ing, she was appalled at the idea of writing "as a woman." Rather, writing
|
||
should produce a becoming-woman as atoms of womanhood capable of
|
||
crossing and impregnating an entire social field, and of contaminating
|
||
men, of sweeping them up in that becoming. Very soft particles—but also
|
||
very hard and obstinate, irreducible, indomitable. The rise of women in
|
||
English novel writing has spared no man: even those who pass for the most
|
||
virile, the most phallocratic, such as Lawrence and Miller, in their turn
|
||
continually tap into and emit particles that enter the proximity or zone of
|
||
indiscernibility of women. In writing, they become-women. The question
|
||
is not, or not only, that of the organism, history, and subject of enunciation
|
||
that oppose masculine to feminine in the great dualism machines. The
|
||
question is fundamentally that of the body—the body they steal from us in
|
||
order to fabricate opposable organisms. This body is stolen first from the
|
||
girl: Stop behaving like that, you're not a little girl anymore, you're not a
|
||
tomboy, etc. The girl's becoming is stolen first, in order to impose a history,
|
||
or prehistory, upon her. The boy's turn comes next, but it is by using the girl
|
||
as an example, by pointing to the girl as the object of his desire, that an
|
||
opposed organism, a dominant history is fabricated for him too. The girl is
|
||
the first victim, but she must also serve as an example and a trap. That is
|
||
why, conversely, the reconstruction of the body as a Body without Organs,
|
||
the anorganism of the body, is inseparable from a becoming-woman, or the
|
||
production of a molecular woman. Doubtless, the girl becomes a woman in
|
||
the molar or organic sense. But conversely, becoming-woman or the molec-
|
||
ular woman is the girl herself. The girl is certainly not defined by virginity;
|
||
she is defined by a relation of movement and rest, speed and slowness, by a
|
||
combination of atoms, an emission of particles: haecceity. She never ceases
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 277
|
||
|
||
to roam upon a body without organs. She is an abstract line, or a line of
|
||
flight. Thus girls do not belong to an age group, sex, order, or kingdom: they
|
||
slip in everywhere, between orders, acts, ages, sexes; they produce n molec-
|
||
ular sexes on the line of flight in relation to the dualism machines they cross
|
||
right through. The only way to get outside the dualisms is to be-between, to
|
||
pass between, the intermezzo—that is what Virginia Woolf lived with all
|
||
her energies, in all of her work, never ceasing to become. The girl is like the
|
||
block of becoming that remains contemporaneous to each opposable term,
|
||
man, woman, child, adult. It is not the girl who becomes a woman; it is
|
||
becoming-woman that produces the universal girl. Trost, a mysterious
|
||
author, painted a portrait of the girl, to whom he linked the fate of the revo-
|
||
lution: her speed, her freely machinic body, her intensities, her abstract
|
||
line or line of flight, her molecular production, her indifference to mem-
|
||
ory, her nonfigurative character—"the nonfigurative of desire."60 Joan of
|
||
Arc? The special role of the girl in Russian terrorism: the girl with the
|
||
bomb, guardian of dynamite? It is certain that molecular politics proceeds
|
||
via the girl and the child. But it is also certain that girls and children draw
|
||
their strength neither from the molar status that subdues them nor from
|
||
the organism and subjectivity they receive; they draw their strength from
|
||
the becoming-molecular they cause to pass between sexes and ages, the
|
||
becoming-child of the adult as well as of the child, the becoming-woman of
|
||
the man as well as of the woman. The girl and the child do not become; it is
|
||
becoming itself that is a child or a girl. The child does not become an adult
|
||
any more than the girl becomes a woman; the girl is the becoming-woman
|
||
of each sex, just as the child is the becoming-young of every age. Knowing
|
||
how to age does not mean remaining young; it means extracting from one's
|
||
age the particles, the speeds and slownesses, the flows that constitute the
|
||
youth of that age. Knowing how to love does not mean remaining a man or a
|
||
woman; it means extracting from one's sex the particles, the speeds and
|
||
slownesses, the flows, the n sexes that constitute the girl of that sexuality. It
|
||
is Age itself that is a becoming-child, just as Sexuality, any sexuality, is a
|
||
becoming-woman, in other words, a girl. This by way of response to the stu-
|
||
pid question, Why did Proust make Albert Albertine?
|
||
Although all becomings are already molecular, including becoming-
|
||
woman, it must be said that all becomings begin with and pass through
|
||
becoming-woman. It is the key to all the other becomings. When the man of
|
||
war disguises himself as a woman, flees disguised as a girl, hides as a girl, it
|
||
is not a shameful, transitory incident in his life. To hide, to camouflage
|
||
oneself, is a warrior function, and the line of flight attracts the enemy, tra-
|
||
verses something and puts what it traverses to flight; the warrior arises in
|
||
the infinity of a line of flight. Although the femininity of the man of war is
|
||
not accidental, it should not be thought of as structural, or regulated by a
|
||
278 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
correspondence of relations. It is difficult to see how the correspondence
|
||
between the two relations "man-war" and "woman-marriage" could entail
|
||
an equivalence between the warrior and the girl as a woman who refuses to
|
||
marry.61 It is just as difficult to see how the general bisexuality, or even
|
||
homosexuality, of military societies could explain this phenomenon,
|
||
which is no more imitative than it is structural, representing instead an
|
||
essential anomie of the man of war. This phenomenon can only be under-
|
||
stood in terms of becoming. We have seen how the man of war, by virtue of
|
||
his furor and celerity, was swept up in irresistible becomings-animal. These
|
||
are becomings that have as their necessary condition the becoming-woman
|
||
of the warrior, or his alliance with the girl, his contagion with her. The man
|
||
of war is inseparable from the Amazons. The union of the girl and the man
|
||
of war does not produce animals, but simultaneously produces the
|
||
becoming-woman of the latter and the becoming-animal of the former, in a
|
||
single "block" in which the warrior in turn becomes animal by contagion
|
||
with the girl at the same time as the girl becomes warrior by contagion with
|
||
the animal. Everything ties together in an asymmetrical block of becom-
|
||
ing, an instantaneous zigzag. It is in the vestiges of a double war machine—
|
||
that of the Greeks, soon to be supplanted by the State, and that of the
|
||
Amazons, soon to be dissolved—that Achilles and Penthesilea, the last
|
||
man of war and the last queen of the girls, choose one another, Achilles in a
|
||
becoming-woman, Penthesilea in a becoming-dog.
|
||
The rites of transvestism or female impersonation in primitive societies
|
||
in which a man becomes a woman are not explainable by a social organiza-
|
||
tion that places the given relations in correspondence, or by a psychic
|
||
organization that makes the woman desire to become a man just as the man
|
||
desires to become a woman.62 Social structure and psychic identification
|
||
leave too many special factors unaccounted for: the linkage, unleashing,
|
||
and communication of the becomings triggered by the transvestite; the
|
||
power (puissance) of the resultant becoming-animal; and above all the par-
|
||
ticipation of these becomings in a specific war machine. The same applies
|
||
for sexuality: it is badly explained by the binary organization of the sexes,
|
||
and just as badly by a bisexual organization within each sex. Sexuality
|
||
brings into play too great a diversity of conjugated becomings; these are
|
||
like n sexes, an entire war machine through which love passes. This is not a
|
||
return to those appalling metaphors of love and war, seduction and con-
|
||
quest, the battle of the sexes and the domestic squabble, or even the
|
||
Strindberg-war: it is only after love is done with and sexuality has dried up
|
||
that things appear this way. What counts is that love itself is a war machine
|
||
endowed with strange and somewhat terrifying powers. Sexuality is the
|
||
production of a thousand sexes, which are so many uncontrollable becom-
|
||
ings. Sexuality proceeds by way of the becoming-woman of the man and the
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 279
|
||
|
||
becoming-animal of the human: an emission of particles. There is no need
|
||
for bestialism in this, although it may arise, and many psychiatric anec-
|
||
dotes document it in ways that are interesting, if oversimplified and conse-
|
||
quently off the track, too beastly. It is not a question of "playing" the dog,
|
||
like an elderly gentleman on a postcard; it is not so much a question of mak-
|
||
ing love with animals. Becomings-animal are basically of another power,
|
||
since their reality resides not in an animal one imitates or to which one cor-
|
||
responds but in themselves, in that which suddenly sweeps us up and
|
||
makes us become—a proximity, an indiscernibility that extracts a shared
|
||
element from the animal far more effectively than any domestication, uti-
|
||
lization, or imitation could: "the Beast."
|
||
If becoming-woman is the first quantum, or molecular segment, with
|
||
the becomings-animal that link up with it coming next, what are they all
|
||
rushing toward? Without a doubt, toward becoming-imperceptible. The
|
||
imperceptible is the immanent end of becoming, its cosmic formula. For
|
||
example, Matheson's Shrinking Man passes through the kingdoms of
|
||
nature, slips between molecules, to become an unfindable particle in infi-
|
||
nite meditation on the infinite. Paul Morand's Monsieur Zero flees the
|
||
larger countries, crosses the smallest ones, descends the scale of States,
|
||
establishes an anonymous society in Lichtenstein of which he is the only
|
||
member, and dies imperceptible, forming the particle 0 with his fingers: "I
|
||
am a man who flees by swimming under water, and at whom all the world's
|
||
rifles fire. . . . I must no longer offer a target." But what does becoming-
|
||
imperceptible signify, coming at the end of all the molecular becomings
|
||
that begin with becoming-woman? Becoming-imperceptible means many
|
||
things. What is the relation between the (anorganic) imperceptible, the
|
||
(asignifying) indiscernible, and the (asubjective) impersonal?
|
||
A first response would be: to be like everybody else. That is what
|
||
Kierkegaard relates in his story about the "knight of the faith," the man of
|
||
becoming: to look at him, one would notice nothing, a bourgeois, nothing
|
||
but a bourgeois. That is how Fitzgerald lived: after a real rupture, one suc-
|
||
ceeds . . . in being just like everybody else. To go unnoticed is by no means
|
||
easy. To be a stranger, even to one's doorman or neighbors. If it is so diffi-
|
||
cult to be "like" everybody else, it is because it is an affair of becoming. Not
|
||
everybody becomes everybody [and everything: tout le monde—Trans.],
|
||
makes a becoming of everybody/everything. This requires much asceti-
|
||
cism, much sobriety, much creative involution: an English elegance, an
|
||
English fabric, blend in with the walls, eliminate the too-perceived, the too-
|
||
much-to-be-perceived. "Eliminate all that is waste, death, and superflu-
|
||
ity," complaint and grievance, unsatisfied desire, defense or pleading,
|
||
everything that roots each of us (everybody) in ourselves, in our molarity.
|
||
For everybody/everything is the molar aggregate, but becoming everybody/
|
||
280 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
everything is another affair, one that brings into play the cosmos with its
|
||
molecular components. Becoming everybody/everything (tout le monde) is
|
||
to world (faire monde), to make a world (faire un monde). By process of
|
||
elimination, one is no longer anything more than an abstract line, or a piece
|
||
in a puzzle that is itself abstract. It is by conjugating, by continuing with
|
||
other lines, other pieces, that one makes a world that can overlay the first
|
||
one, like a transparency. Animal elegance, the camouflage fish, the clan-
|
||
destine: this fish is crisscrossed by abstract lines that resemble nothing,
|
||
that do not even follow its organic divisions; but thus disorganized,
|
||
disarticulated, it worlds with the lines of a rock, sand, and plants, becoming
|
||
imperceptible. The fish is like the Chinese poet: not imitative or structural,
|
||
but cosmic. Francois Cheng shows that poets do not pursue resemblance,
|
||
any more than they calculate "geometric proportions." They retain, extract
|
||
only the essential lines and movements of nature; they proceed only by
|
||
continued or superposed "traits," or strokes.63 It is in this sense that
|
||
becoming-everybody/everything, making the world a becoming, is to
|
||
world, to make a world or worlds, in other words, to find one's proximities
|
||
and zones of indiscernibility. The Cosmos as an abstract machine, and
|
||
each world as an assemblage effectuating it. If one reduces oneself to one or
|
||
several abstract lines that will prolong itself in and conjugate with others,
|
||
producing immediately, directly a world in which it is the world that
|
||
becomes, then one becomes-everybody/everything. Kerouac's dream, and
|
||
already Virginia Woolf s, was for the writing to be like the line of a Chinese
|
||
poem-drawing. She says that it is necessary to "saturate every atom," and
|
||
to do that it is necessary to eliminate, to eliminate all that is resemblance
|
||
and analogy, but also "to put everything into it": eliminate everything that
|
||
exceeds the moment, but put in everything that it includes—and the
|
||
moment is not the instantaneous, it is the haecceity into which one slips
|
||
and that slips into other haecceities by transparency.64 To be present at the
|
||
dawn of the world. Such is the link between imperceptibility, indis-
|
||
cernibility, and impersonality—the three virtues. To reduce oneself to an
|
||
abstract line, a trait, in order to find one's zone of indiscernibility with
|
||
other traits, and in this way enter the haecceity and impersonality of the
|
||
creator. One is then like grass: one has made the world, everybody/
|
||
everything, into a becoming, because one has made a necessarily commu-
|
||
nicating world, because one has suppressed in oneself everything that
|
||
prevents us from slipping between things and growing in the midst of
|
||
things. One has combined "everything" (le "tout"): the indefinite article,
|
||
the infinitive-becoming, and the proper name to which one is reduced. Sat-
|
||
urate, eliminate, put everything in.
|
||
Movement has an essential relation to the imperceptible; it is by nature
|
||
imperceptible. Perception can grasp movement only as the displacement
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 281
|
||
|
||
of a moving body or the development of a form. Movements, becomings, in
|
||
other words, pure relations of speed and slowness, pure affects, are below
|
||
and above the threshold of perception. Doubtless, thresholds of perception
|
||
are relative; there is always a threshold capable of grasping what eludes
|
||
another: the eagle's eye... But the adequate threshold can in turn operate
|
||
only as a function of a perceptible form and a perceived, discerned subject.
|
||
So that movement in itself continues to occur elsewhere: if we serialize per-
|
||
ception, the movement always takes place above the maximum threshold
|
||
and below the minimum threshold, in expanding or contracting intervals
|
||
(microintervals). Like huge Japanese wrestlers whose advance is too slow
|
||
and whose holds are too fast to see, so that what embraces are less the
|
||
wrestlers than the infinite slowness of the wait (what is going to happen?)
|
||
and the infinite speed of the result (what happened?). What we must do is
|
||
reach the photographic or cinematic threshold; but in relation to the
|
||
photograph, movement and affect once again took refuge above and below.
|
||
When Kierkegaard adopts the marvelous motto, "I look only at the move-
|
||
ments,"65 he is acting astonishingly like a precursor of the cinema, multi-
|
||
plying versions of a love scenario (between Agnes and the merman)
|
||
according to variable speeds and slownesses. He has all the more reason to
|
||
say that there is no movement that is not infinite; that the movement of the
|
||
infinite can occur only by means of affect, passion, love, in a becoming that
|
||
is the girl, but without reference to any kind of "mediation"; and that this
|
||
movement as such eludes any mediating perception because it is already
|
||
effectuated at every moment, and the dancer or lover finds him- or herself
|
||
already "awake and walking" the second he or she falls down, and even the
|
||
instant he or she leaps.66 Movement, like the girl as a fugitive being, cannot
|
||
be perceived.
|
||
However, we are obliged to make an immediate correction: movement
|
||
also "must" be perceived, it cannot but be perceived, the imperceptible is
|
||
also the percipiendum. There is no contradiction in this. If movement is
|
||
imperceptible by nature, it is so always in relation to a given threshold of
|
||
perception, which is by nature relative and thus plays the role of a media-
|
||
tion on the plane that effects the distribution of thresholds and percepts
|
||
and makes forms perceivable to perceiving subjects. It is the plane of
|
||
organization and development, the plane of transcendence, that renders
|
||
perceptible without itself being perceived, without being capable of being
|
||
perceived. But on the other plane, the plane of immanence or consistency,
|
||
the principle of composition itself must be perceived, cannot but be per-
|
||
ceived at the same time as that which it composes or renders. In this case,
|
||
movement is no longer tied to the mediation of a relative threshold that it
|
||
eludes ad infinitum; it has reached, regardless of its speed or slowness, an
|
||
absolute but differentiated threshold that is one with the construction of
|
||
282 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL ...
|
||
|
||
this or that region of the continued plane. It could also be said that move-
|
||
ment ceases to be the procedure of an always relative deterritorialization,
|
||
becoming the process of absolute deterritorialization. The difference
|
||
between the two planes accounts for the fact that what cannot be perceived
|
||
on one cannot but be perceived on the other. It is in jumping from one plane
|
||
to the other, or from the relative thresholds to the absolute threshold that
|
||
coexists with them, that the imperceptible becomes necessarily perceived.
|
||
Kierkegaard shows that the plane of the infinite, which he calls the plane of
|
||
faith, must become a pure plane of immanence that continually and imme-
|
||
diately imparts, reimparts, and regathers the finite: unlike the man of infi-
|
||
nite resignation, the knight of the faith or man of becoming will get the girl,
|
||
he will have all of the finite and perceive the imperceptible, as "heir appar-
|
||
ent to the finite."67 Perception will no longer reside in the relation between
|
||
a subject and an object, but rather in the movement serving as the limit of
|
||
that relation, in the period associated with the subject and object. Percep-
|
||
tion will confront its own limit; it will be in the midst of things, throughout
|
||
its own proximity, as the presence of one haecceity in another, the
|
||
prehension of one by the other or the passage from one to the other: Look
|
||
only at the movements.
|
||
It is odd that the word "faith" should be used to designate a plane that
|
||
works by immanence. But if the knight is the man of becoming, then there
|
||
are all kinds of knights. Are there not even knights of narcotics, in the sense
|
||
that faith is a drug (in a way very different from the sense in which religion
|
||
is an opiate)? These knights claim that drugs, under necessary conditions
|
||
of caution and experimentation, are inseparable from the deployment of a
|
||
plane. And on this plane not only are becomings-woman, becomings-
|
||
animal, becomings-molecular, becomings-imperceptible conjugated, but
|
||
the imperceptible itself becomes necessarily perceived at the same time as
|
||
perception becomes necessarily molecular: arrive at holes, microintervals
|
||
between matters, colors and sounds engulfing lines of flight, world lines,
|
||
lines of transparency and intersection.68 Change perception; the problem
|
||
has been formulated correctly because it presents "drugs" as a pregnant
|
||
whole free of secondary distinctions (hallucinatory or nonhallucinatory,
|
||
hard or soft, etc.). All drugs fundamentally concern speeds, and modifica-
|
||
tions of speed. What allows us to describe an overall Drug assemblage in
|
||
spite of the differences between drugs is a line of perceptive causality that
|
||
makes it so that (1) the imperceptible is perceived; (2) perception is molec-
|
||
ular; (3) desire directly invests the perception and the perceived. The
|
||
Americans of the beat generation had already embarked on this path, and
|
||
spoke of a molecular revolution specific to drugs. Then came Castaneda's
|
||
broad synthesis. Leslie Fiedler set forth the poles of the American Dream:
|
||
cornered between two nightmares, the genocide of the Indians and the slav-
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 283
|
||
|
||
ery of the blacks, Americans constructed a psychically repressed image of
|
||
the black as the force of affect, of the multiplication of affects, but a socially
|
||
repressed image of the Indian as subtlety of perception, perception made
|
||
increasingly keen and more finely divided, infinitely slowed or acceler-
|
||
ated.69 In Europe, Henri Michaux tended to be more willing to free himself
|
||
of rites and civilizations, establishing admirable and minute protocols of
|
||
experience, doing away with the question of causality with respect to drugs,
|
||
delimiting drugs as well as possible, separating them from delirium and
|
||
hallucination. But at this point everything reconnects: again, the problem
|
||
is well formulated if we say that drugs eliminate forms and persons, if we
|
||
bring into play the mad speeds of drugs and the extraordinary posthigh
|
||
slownesses, if we clasp one to the other like wrestlers, if we confer upon per-
|
||
ception the molecular power to grasp microperceptions, microoperations,
|
||
and upon the perceived the force to emit accelerated or decelerated parti-
|
||
cles in a floating time that is no longer our time, and to emit haecceities that
|
||
are no longer of this world: deterritorialization, "I was disoriented . . ." (a
|
||
perception of things, thoughts, desires in which desire, thought, and the
|
||
thing have invaded all of perception: the imperceptible finally perceived).
|
||
Nothing left but the world of speeds and slownesses without form, without
|
||
subject, without a face. Nothing left but the zigzag of a line, like "the lash of
|
||
the whip of an enraged cart driver" shredding faces and landscapes.70 A
|
||
whole rhizomatic labor of perception, the moment when desire and per-
|
||
ception meld.
|
||
This problem of specific causality is an important one. Invoking causali-
|
||
ties that are too general or are extrinsic (psychological or sociological) is as
|
||
good as saying nothing. There is a discourse on drugs current today that
|
||
does no more than dredge up generalities on pleasure and misfortune, on
|
||
difficulties in communication, on causes that always come from some-
|
||
where else. The more incapable people are of grasping a specific causality
|
||
in extension, the more they pretend to understand the phenomenon in
|
||
question. There is no doubt that an assemblage never contains a causal
|
||
infrastructure. It does have, however, and to the highest degree, an abstract
|
||
line of creative or specific causality, its line of flight or of deterritorializa-
|
||
tion; this line can be effectuated only in connection with general causalities
|
||
of another nature, but is in no way explained by them. It is our belief that
|
||
the issue of drugs can be understood only at the level where desire directly
|
||
invests perception, and perception becomes molecular at the same time as
|
||
the imperceptible is perceived. Drugs then appear as the agent of this
|
||
becoming. This is where pharmacoanalysis would come in, which must be
|
||
both compared and contrasted to psychoanalysis. For psychoanalysis must
|
||
be taken simultaneously as a model, a contrasting approach, and a betrayal.
|
||
Psychoanalysis can be taken as a model of reference because it was able,
|
||
284 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
with respect to essentially affective phenomena, to construct the schema of
|
||
a specific causality divorced from ordinary social or psychological general-
|
||
ities. But this schema still relies on a plane of organization that can never be
|
||
apprehended in itself, that is always concluded from something else, that is
|
||
always inferred, concealed from the system of perception: it is called the
|
||
Unconscious. Thus the plane of the Unconscious remains a plane of tran-
|
||
scendence guaranteeing, justifying, the existence of psychoanalysis and the
|
||
necessity of its interpretations. This plane of the Unconscious stands in
|
||
molar opposition to the perception-consciousness system, and because
|
||
desire must be translated onto this plane, it is itself linked to gross
|
||
molarities, like the submerged part of an iceberg (the Oedipal structure, or
|
||
the rock of castration). The imperceptible thus remains all the more imper-
|
||
ceptible because it is opposed to the perceived in a dualism machine.
|
||
Everything is different on the plane of consistency or immanence, which is
|
||
necessarily perceived in its own right in the course of its construction:
|
||
experimentation replaces interpretation, now molecular, nonfigurative,
|
||
and nonsymbolic, the unconscious as such is given in microperceptions;
|
||
desire directly invests the field of perception, where the imperceptible
|
||
appears as the perceived object of desire itself, "the nonfigurative of
|
||
desire." The unconscious no longer designates the hidden principle of the
|
||
transcendent plane of organization, but the process of the immanent plane
|
||
of consistency as it appears on itself in the course of its construction. For
|
||
the unconscious must be constructed, not rediscovered. There is no longer
|
||
a conscious-unconscious dualism machine, because the unconscious is, or
|
||
rather is produced, there where consciousness goes, carried by the plane.71
|
||
Drugs give the unconscious the immanence and plane that psychoanalysis
|
||
has consistently botched (perhaps the famous cocaine episode marked a
|
||
turning point that forced Freud to renounce a direct approach to the
|
||
unconscious).
|
||
But if it is true that drugs are linked to this immanent, molecular percep-
|
||
tive causality, we are still faced with the question of whether they actually
|
||
succeed in drawing the plane necessary for their action. The causal line, or
|
||
the line of flight, of drugs is constantly being segmentarized under the most
|
||
rigid of forms, that of dependency, the hit and the dose, the dealer. Even in
|
||
its supple form, it can mobilize gradients and thresholds of perception
|
||
toward becomings-animal, becomings-molecular, but even this is done in
|
||
the context of a relativity of thresholds that restrict themselves to imitating
|
||
a plane of consistency rather than drawing it on an absolute threshold.
|
||
What good does it do to perceive as fast as a quick-flying bird if speed and
|
||
movement continue to escape somewhere else? The deterritorializations
|
||
remain relative, compensated for by the most abject reterritorializations,
|
||
so that the imperceptible and perception continually pursue or run after
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 285
|
||
|
||
each other without ever truly coupling. Instead of holes in the world allow-
|
||
ing the world lines themselves to run off, the lines of flight coil and start to
|
||
swirl in black holes; to each addict a hole, group or individual, like a snail.
|
||
Down, instead of high. The molecular microperceptions are overlaid in
|
||
advance, depending on the drug, by hallucinations, delusions, false percep-
|
||
tions, phantasies, or paranoid outbursts; they restore forms and subjects
|
||
every instant, like so many phantoms or doubles continually blocking con-
|
||
struction of the plane. Moreover, as we saw in our enumeration of the dan-
|
||
gers, not only is the plane of consistency in danger of being betrayed or
|
||
thrown offtrack through the influence of other causalities that intervene in
|
||
an assemblage of this kind, but the plane itself engenders dangers of its
|
||
own, by which it is dismantled at the same time as it is constructed. We are
|
||
no longer, it itself is no longer master of speeds. Instead of making a body
|
||
without organs sufficiently rich or full for the passage of intensities, drug
|
||
addicts erect a vitrified or emptied body, or a cancerous one: the causal
|
||
line, creative line, or line of flight immediately turns into a line of death
|
||
and abolition. The abominable vitrification of the veins, or the purulence
|
||
of the nose—the glassy body of the addict. Black holes and lines of death,
|
||
Artaud's and Michaux's warnings converge (they are more technical, more
|
||
consistent than the informational, psychoanalytic, or sociopsychological
|
||
discourse of treatment and assistance centers). Artaud: You will not avoid
|
||
hallucinations, erroneous perceptions, shameless phantasies, or bad feel-
|
||
ings, like so many black holes on the plane of consistency, because your
|
||
conscious will also go in that booby-trapped direction.72 Michaux: You will
|
||
no longer be master of your speeds, you will get stuck in a mad race between
|
||
the imperceptible and perception, a race all the more circular now that
|
||
everything is relative.73 You will be full of yourself, you will lose control,
|
||
you will be on a plane of consistency, in a body without organs, but at a
|
||
place where you will always botch them, empty them, undo what you do,
|
||
motionless rags. These words are so much simpler than "erroneous percep-
|
||
tions" (Artaud) or "bad feelings" (Michaux), but say the most technical of
|
||
things: that the immanent molecular and perceptive causality of desire
|
||
fails in the drug-assemblage. Drug addicts continually fall back into what
|
||
they wanted to escape: a segmentarity all the more rigid for being marginal,
|
||
a territorialization all the more artificial for being based on chemical sub-
|
||
stances, hallucinatory forms, and phantasy subjectifications. Drug addicts
|
||
may be considered as precursors or experimenters who tirelessly blaze new
|
||
paths of life, but their cautiousness lacks the foundation for caution. So
|
||
they either join the legion of false heroes who follow the conformist path of
|
||
a little death and a long fatigue. Or, what is worse, all they will have done is
|
||
make an attempt only nonusers or former users can resume and benefit
|
||
from, secondarily rectifying the always aborted plane of drugs, discovering
|
||
286 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . ..
|
||
|
||
through drugs what drugs lack for the construction of a plane of consis-
|
||
tency. Is the mistake drug users make always to start over again from
|
||
ground zero, either going on the drug again or quitting, when what they
|
||
should do is make it a stopover, to start from the "middle," bifurcate from
|
||
the middle? To succeed in getting drunk, but on pure water (Henry Miller).
|
||
To succeed in getting high, but by abstention, "to take and abstain, espe-
|
||
cially abstain," I am a drinker of water (Michaux). To reach the point where
|
||
"to get high or not to get high" is no longer the question, but rather whether
|
||
drugs have sufficiently changed the general conditions of space and time
|
||
perception so that nonusers can succeed in passing through the holes in the
|
||
world and following the lines of flight at the very place where means other
|
||
than drugs become necessary. Drugs do not guarantee immanence; rather,
|
||
the immanence of drugs allows one to forgo them. Is it cowardice or exploi-
|
||
tation to wait until others have taken the risks? No, it is joining an under-
|
||
taking in the middle, while changing the means. It is necessary to choose
|
||
the right molecule, the water, hydrogen, or helium molecule. This has noth-
|
||
ing to do with models, all models are molar: it is necessary to determine the
|
||
molecules and particles in relation to which "proximities" (indiscern-
|
||
ibilities, becomings) are engendered and defined. The vital assemblage,
|
||
the life-assemblage, is theoretically or logically possible with all kinds of
|
||
molecules, silicon, for example. But it so happens that this assemblage is
|
||
not machinically possible with silicon: the abstract machine does not let it
|
||
pass because it does not distribute zones of proximity that construct the
|
||
plane of consistency.74 We shall see that machinic reasons are entirely dif-
|
||
ferent from logical reasons or possibilities. One does not conform to a
|
||
model, one straddles the right horse. Drug users have not chosen the right
|
||
molecule or the right horse. Drugs are too unwieldy to grasp the impercep-
|
||
tible and becomings-imperceptible; drug users believed that drugs would
|
||
grant them the plane, when in fact the plane must distill its own drugs,
|
||
remaining master of speeds and proximities.
|
||
|
||
Memories of the Secret. The secret has a privileged, but quite variable,
|
||
relation to perception and the imperceptible. The secret relates first of all
|
||
to certain contents. The content is too big for its form . . . or else the con-
|
||
tents themselves have a form, but that form is covered, doubled, or
|
||
replaced by a simple container, envelope, or box whose role it is to suppress
|
||
formal relations. These are contents it has been judged fitting to isolate or
|
||
disguise for various reasons. Drawing up a list of these reasons (shame,
|
||
treasure, divinity, etc.) has limited value as long as the secret is opposed to
|
||
its discovery as in a binary machine having only two terms, the secret and
|
||
disclosure, the secret and desecration. For on the one hand, the secret as
|
||
content is superseded by a perception of the secret, which is no less secret
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 287
|
||
|
||
than the secret. It matters little what the goal is, and whether the aim of the
|
||
perception is a denunciation, final divulging, or disclosure. From an anec-
|
||
dotal standpoint, the perception of the secret is the opposite of the secret,
|
||
but from the standpoint of the concept, it is a part of it. What counts is that
|
||
the perception of the secret must necessarily be secret itself: the spy, the
|
||
voyeur, the blackmailer, the author of anonymous letters are no less secre-
|
||
tive than what they are in a position to disclose, regardless of their ulterior
|
||
motives. There is always a woman, a child, a bird to secretly perceive the
|
||
secret. There is always a perception finer than yours, a perception of your
|
||
imperceptible, of what is in your box. We can even envision a profession of
|
||
secrecy for those who are in a position to perceive the secret. The protector
|
||
of the secret is not necessarily in on it, but is also tied to a perception, since
|
||
he or she must perceive and detect those who wish to discover the secret
|
||
(counterespionage). There is thus a first direction, in which the secret
|
||
moves toward an equally secretive perception, a perception that seeks to be
|
||
imperceptible itself. A wide variety of very different figures may revolve
|
||
around this first point. And then there is a second point, just as inseparable
|
||
from the secret as its content: the way in which it imposes itself and
|
||
spreads. Once again, whatever the finalities or results, the secret has a way
|
||
of spreading that is in turn shrouded in secrecy. The secret as secretion. The
|
||
secret must sneak, insert, or introduce itself into the arena of public forms;
|
||
it must pressure them and prod known subjects into action (we are refer-
|
||
ring to influence of the "lobby" type, even if the lobby is not in itself a secret
|
||
society).
|
||
In short, the secret, defined as a content that has hidden its form in favor
|
||
of a simple container, is inseparable from two movements that can acci-
|
||
dentally interrupt its course or betray it, but are nonetheless an essential
|
||
part of it: something must ooze from the box, something will be perceived
|
||
through the box or in the half-opened box. The secret was invented by soci-
|
||
ety; it is a sociological or social notion. Every secret is a collective assem-
|
||
blage. The secret is not at all an immobilized or static notion. Only
|
||
becomings are secrets; the secret has a becoming. The secret has its origin
|
||
in the war machine; it is the war machine and its becomings-woman,
|
||
becomings-child, becomings-animal that bring the secret.75 A secret soci-
|
||
ety always acts in society as a war machine. Sociologists who have studied
|
||
secret societies have determined many of their laws: protection,
|
||
equalization and hierarchy, silence, ritual, deindividuation, centraliza-
|
||
tion, autonomy, compartmentalization, etc.76 But perhaps they have not
|
||
given enough weight to the principal laws governing the movement of con-
|
||
tent: (1) every secret society has a still more secret hindsociety, which either
|
||
perceives the secret, protects it, or metes out the punishment for its disclo-
|
||
sure (it is not at all begging the question to define the secret society by the
|
||
288 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
presence of a secret hindsociety: a society is secret when it exhibits this
|
||
doubling, has this special section); (2) every secret society has its own mode
|
||
of action, which is in turn secret; the secret society may act by influence,
|
||
creeping, insinuation, oozing, pressure, or invisible rays; "passwords" and
|
||
secret languages (there is no contradiction here; the secret society cannot
|
||
live without the universal project of permeating all of society, of creeping
|
||
into all of the forms of society, disrupting its hierarchy and segmentation;
|
||
the secret hierarchy conjugates with a conspiracy of equals, it commands
|
||
its members to swim in society as fish in water, but conversely society must
|
||
be like water around fish; it needs the complicity of the entire surrounding
|
||
society). This is evident in cases as diverse as the mob groups of the United
|
||
States and the animal-men of Africa: on the one hand, there is the mode of
|
||
influence of the secret society and its leaders on the political or public fig-
|
||
ures of its surroundings; and on the other hand, there is the secret society's
|
||
mode of doubling itself with a hindsociety, which may constitute a special
|
||
section of killers or guards.77 Influence and doubling, secretion and concre-
|
||
tion, every secret operates between two "discreets" [discrets: also "discrete
|
||
(terms)"—Trans.] that can, moreover, link or meld in certain cases. The
|
||
child's secret combines these elements to marvelous effect: the secret as a
|
||
content in a box, the secret influence and propagation of the secret, the
|
||
secret perception of the secret (the child's secret is not composed of minia-
|
||
turized adult secrets but is necessarily accompanied by a secret perception
|
||
of the adult secret). A child discovers a secret...
|
||
But the becoming of the secret compels it not to content itself with con-
|
||
cealing its form in a simple container, or with swapping it for a container.
|
||
The secret, as secret, must now acquire its own form. The secret is elevated
|
||
from a finite content to the infinite form of secrecy. This is the point at
|
||
which the secret attains absolute imperceptibility, instead of being linked
|
||
to a whole interplay of relative perceptions and reactions. We go from a
|
||
content that is well defined, localized, and belongs to the past, to the a pri-
|
||
ori general form of a nonlocalizable something that has happened. We go
|
||
from the secret defined as a hysterical childhood content to secrecy
|
||
defined as an eminently virile paranoid form. And this form displays the
|
||
same two concomitants of the secret, the secret perception and the mode of
|
||
action by secret influence; but these concomitants have become "traits" of
|
||
a form they ceaselessly reconstitute, reform, recharge. On the one hand,
|
||
paranoiacs denounce the international plot of those who steal their secrets,
|
||
their most intimate thoughts; or they declare that they have the gift of per-
|
||
ceiving the secrets of others before they have formed (someone with para-
|
||
noid jealousy does not apprehend the other in the act of escaping; they
|
||
divine or foresee the slightest intention of it). On the other hand, paranoi-
|
||
acs act by means of, or else suffer from, rays they emit or receive (Raymond
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 289
|
||
|
||
Roussel and Schreber). Influence by rays, and doubling by flight or echo,
|
||
are what now give the secret its infinite form, in which perceptions as well
|
||
as actions pass into imperceptibility. Paranoid judgment is like an antici-
|
||
pation of perception replacing empirical research into boxes and their con-
|
||
tents: guilty a priori, and in any event! (for example, the evolution of the
|
||
narrator of the Recherche in relation to Albertine). We can say, in summary
|
||
fashion, that psychoanalysis has gone from a hysterical to an increasingly
|
||
paranoid conception of the secret.78 Interminable analysis: the Uncon-
|
||
scious has been assigned the increasingly difficult task of itself being the
|
||
infinite form of secrecy, instead of a simple box containing secrets. You will
|
||
tell all, but in saying everything you will say nothing because all the "art" of
|
||
psychoanalysis is required in order to measure your contents against the
|
||
pure form. At this point, however, after the secret has been raised to the
|
||
level of a form in this way, an inevitable adventure befalls it. When the
|
||
question "What happened?" attains this infinite virile form, the answer is
|
||
necessarily that nothing happened, and both form and content are
|
||
destroyed. The news travels fast that the secret of men is nothing, in truth
|
||
nothing at all. Oedipus, the phallus, castration, "the splinter in the flesh"—
|
||
that was the secret? It is enough to make women, children, lunatics, and
|
||
molecules laugh.
|
||
The more the secret is made into a structuring, organizing form, the
|
||
thinner and more ubiquitous it becomes, the more its content becomes
|
||
molecular, at the same time as its form dissolves. It really wasn't much, as
|
||
Jocasta says. The secret does not as a result disappear, but it does take on a
|
||
more feminine status. What was behind President Schreber's paranoid
|
||
secret all along, if not a becoming-feminine, a becoming-woman? For
|
||
women do not handle the secret in at all the same way as men (except when
|
||
they reconstitute an inverted image of virile secrecy, a kind of secrecy of the
|
||
gyneceum). Men alternately fault them for their indiscretion, their gossip-
|
||
ing, and for their solidarity, their betrayal. Yet it is curious how a woman
|
||
can be secretive while at the same time hiding nothing, by virtue of trans-
|
||
parency, innocence, and speed. The complex assemblage of secrecy in
|
||
courtly love is properly feminine and operates in the most complete trans-
|
||
parency. Celerity against gravity. The celerity of a war machine against the
|
||
gravity of a State apparatus. Men adopt a grave attitude, knights of the
|
||
secret: "You see what burden I bear: my seriousness, my discretion." But
|
||
they end up telling everything—and it turns out to be nothing. There are
|
||
women, on the other hand, who tell everything, sometimes in appalling
|
||
technical detail, but one knows no more at the end than at the beginning;
|
||
they have hidden everything by celerity, by limpidity. They have no secret
|
||
because they have become a secret themselves. Are they more politic than
|
||
we? Iphigenia. Innocent a priori. That is the girl's defense against the
|
||
290 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
judgment preferred by men: "guilty a priori" . . . This is where the secret
|
||
reaches its ultimate state: its content is molecularized, it has become
|
||
molecular, at the same time as its form has been dismantled, becoming a
|
||
pure moving line—in the sense in which it can be said a given line is the
|
||
"secret" of a painter, or a given rhythmic cell, a given sound molecule
|
||
(which does not constitute a theme or form) the "secret" of a musician.
|
||
If ever there was a writer who dealt with the secret, it was Henry James.
|
||
In this respect, he went through an entire evolution, like a perfecting of his
|
||
art. For he began by looking for the secret in contents, even insignificant,
|
||
half-opened ones, contents briefly glimpsed. Then he raised the possibility
|
||
of there being an infinite form of secrecy that no longer even requires a con-
|
||
tent and that has conquered the imperceptible. But he raises this possi-
|
||
bility only in order to ask the question, Is the secret in the content or in the
|
||
form? And the answer is already apparent: neither.19 James is one of those
|
||
writers who is swept up in an irresistible becoming-woman. He never
|
||
stopped pursuing his goal, inventing the necessary technical means. Mo-
|
||
lecularize the content of the secret and linearize its form. James explored it
|
||
all, from the becoming-child of the secret (there is always a child who dis-
|
||
covers secrets: What Maisie Knew) to the becoming-woman of the secret
|
||
(secrecy by a transparency that is no longer anything more than a pure line
|
||
that scarcely leaves any traces of its own passage; the admirable Daisy
|
||
Miller). James is not as close to Proust as people say; it is he who raises the
|
||
cry, "Innocent a priori!" (all Daisy asked for was a little respect, she would
|
||
have given her love for that. . .) in opposition to the "Guilty a priori" that
|
||
condemns Albertine. What counts in the secret is less its three states
|
||
(child's content, virile infinite form, pure feminine line) than the becom-
|
||
ings attached to them, the becoming-child of the secret, its becoming-
|
||
feminine, its becoming-molecular—which occur precisely at the point
|
||
where the secret has lost both its content and its form, where the impercep-
|
||
tible, the clandestine with nothing left to hide, has finally been perceived.
|
||
From the gray eminence to the gray immanence. Oedipus passes through all
|
||
three secrets: the secret of the sphinx whose box he penetrates; the secret
|
||
that weighs upon him as the infinite form of his own guilt; and finally, the
|
||
secret at Colonus that makes him inaccessible and melds with the pure line
|
||
of his flight and exile, he who has nothing left to hide, or, like an old No
|
||
actor, has only a girl's mask with which to cover his lack of a face. Some
|
||
people can talk, hide nothing, not lie: they are secret by transparency, as
|
||
impenetrable as water, in truth incomprehensible. Whereas the others have
|
||
a secret that is always breached, even though they surround it with a thick
|
||
wall or elevate it to an infinite form.
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL ... D 291
|
||
|
||
Memories and Becomings, Points and Blocks. Why are there so many
|
||
becomings of man, but no becoming-man? First because man is major-
|
||
itarian par excellence, whereas becomings are minoritarian; all becoming
|
||
is a becoming-minoritarian. When we say majority, we are referring not to
|
||
a greater relative quantity but to the determination of a state or standard
|
||
in relation to which larger quantities, as well as the smallest, can be said to
|
||
be minoritarian: white-man, adult-male, etc. Majority implies a state of
|
||
domination, not the reverse. It is not a question of knowing whether there
|
||
are more mosquitoes or flies than men, but of knowing how "man" consti-
|
||
tuted a standard in the universe in relation to which men necessarily (ana-
|
||
lytically) form a majority. The majority in a government presupposes the
|
||
right to vote, and not only is established among those who possess that
|
||
right but is exercised over those who do not, however great their numbers;
|
||
similarly, the majority in the universe assumes as pregiven the right and
|
||
power of man.80 In this sense women, children, but also animals, plants,
|
||
and molecules, are minoritarian. It is perhaps the special situation of
|
||
women in relation to the man-standard that accounts for the fact that
|
||
becomings, being minoritarian, always pass through a becoming-woman.
|
||
It is important not to confuse "minoritarian," as a becoming or process,
|
||
with a "minority", as an aggregate or a state. Jews, Gypsies, etc., may con-
|
||
stitute minorities under certain conditions, but that in itself does not
|
||
make them becomings. One reterritorializes, or allows oneself to be
|
||
reterritorialized, on a minority as a state; but in a becoming, one is
|
||
deterritorialized. Even blacks, as the Black Panthers said, must become-
|
||
black. Even women must become-woman. Even Jews must become-
|
||
Jewish (it certainly takes more than a state). But if this is the case, then
|
||
becoming-Jewish necessarily affects the non-Jew as much as the Jew.
|
||
Becoming-woman necessary affects men as much as women. In a way, the
|
||
subject in a becoming is always "man," but only when he enters a
|
||
becoming-minoritarian that rends him from his major identity. As in
|
||
Arthur Miller's novel, Focus, or Losey's film, Mr. Klein: it is the non-Jew
|
||
who becomes Jewish, who is swept up in, carried off by, this becoming
|
||
after being rent from his standard of measure. Conversely, if Jews them-
|
||
selves must become-Jewish, if women must become-woman, if children
|
||
must become-child, if blacks must become-black, it is because only a
|
||
minority is capable of serving as the active medium of becoming, but
|
||
under such conditions that it ceases to be a definable aggregate in relation
|
||
to the majority. Becoming-Jewish, becoming-woman, etc., therefore
|
||
imply two simultaneous movements, one by which a term (the subject) is
|
||
withdrawn from the majority, and another by which a term (the medium
|
||
or agent) rises up from the minority. There is an asymmetrical and
|
||
indissociable block of becoming, a block of alliance: the two "Mr. Kleins,"
|
||
292 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
the Jew and the non-Jew, enter into a becoming-Jewish (the same thing
|
||
happens in Focus).
|
||
A woman has to become-woman, but in a becoming-woman of all man.
|
||
A Jew becomes Jewish, but in a becoming-Jewish of the non-Jew. A
|
||
becoming-minoritarian exists only by virtue of a deterritorialized medium
|
||
and subject that are like its elements. There is no subject of the becoming
|
||
except as a deterritorialized variable of the majority; there is no medium of
|
||
becoming except as a deterritorialized variable of a minority. We can be
|
||
thrown into a becoming by anything at all, by the most unexpected, most
|
||
insignificant of things. You don't deviate from the majority unless there is
|
||
a little detail that starts to swell and carries you off. It is because the hero of
|
||
Focus, the average American, needs glasses that give his nose a vaguely
|
||
Semitic air, it is "because of the glasses" that he is thrown into this strange
|
||
adventure of the becoming-Jewish of the non-Jew. Anything at all can do
|
||
the job, but it always turns out to be a political affair. Becoming-minori-
|
||
tarian is a political affair and necessitates a labor of power (puissance), an
|
||
active micropolitics. This is the opposite of macropolitics, and even of His-
|
||
tory, in which it is a question of knowing how to win or obtain a majority.
|
||
As Faulkner said, to avoid ending up a fascist there was no other choice but
|
||
to become-black.81 Unlike history, becoming cannot be conceptualized in
|
||
terms of past and future. Becoming-revolutionary remains indifferent to
|
||
questions of a future and a past of the revolution; it passes between the two.
|
||
Every becoming is a block of coexistence. The so-called ahistorical socie-
|
||
ties set themselves outside history, not because they are content to repro-
|
||
duce immutable models or are governed by a fixed structure, but because
|
||
they are societies of becoming (war societies, secret societies, etc.). There is
|
||
no history but of the majority, or of minorities as defined in relation to the
|
||
majority. And yet "how to win the majority" is a totally secondary problem
|
||
in relation to the advances of the imperceptible.
|
||
Let us try to say it another way: There is no becoming-man because man
|
||
is the molar entity par excellence, whereas becomings are molecular. The
|
||
faciality function showed us the form under which man constitutes the
|
||
majority, or rather the standard upon which the majority is based: white,
|
||
male, adult, "rational," etc., in short, the average European, the subject of
|
||
enunciation. Following the law of arborescence, it is this central Point that
|
||
moves across all of space or the entire screen, and at every turn nourishes a
|
||
certain distinctive opposition, depending on which faciality trait is
|
||
retained: male-(female), adult-(child), white-(black, yellow, or red);
|
||
rational-(animal). The central point, or third eye, thus has the property of
|
||
organizing binary distributions within the dualism machines, and of
|
||
reproducing itself in the principal term of the opposition; the entire oppo-
|
||
sition at the same time resonates in the central point. The constitution of a
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 293
|
||
|
||
"majority" as redundancy. Man constitutes himself as a gigantic memory,
|
||
through the position of the central point, its frequency (insofar as it is nec-
|
||
essarily reproduced by each dominant point), and its resonance (insofar as
|
||
all of the points tie in with it). Any line that goes from one point to another
|
||
in the aggregate of the molar system, and is thus defined by points answer-
|
||
ing to these mnemonic conditions of frequency and resonance, is a part of
|
||
the arborescent system.82
|
||
What constitutes arborescence is the submission of the line to the point.
|
||
Of course, the child, the woman, the black have memories; but the Memory
|
||
that collects those memories is still a virile majoritarian agency treating
|
||
them as "childhood memories," as conjugal, or colonial memories. It is
|
||
possible to operate by establishing a conjunction or collocation of contigu-
|
||
ous points rather than a relation between distant points: you would then
|
||
have phantasies rather than memories. For example, a woman can have a
|
||
female point alongside a male point, and a man a male point alongside a
|
||
female one. The constitution of these hybrids, however, does not take us
|
||
very far in the direction of a true becoming (for example, bisexuality, as the
|
||
psychoanalysts note, in no way precludes the prevalence of the masculine
|
||
or the majority of the "phallus"). One does not break with the arborescent
|
||
schema, one does not reach becoming or the molecular, as long as a line is
|
||
connected to two distant points, or is composed of two contiguous points.
|
||
A line of becoming is not defined by points that it connects, or by points
|
||
that compose it; on the contrary, it passes between points, it comes up
|
||
through the middle, it runs perpendicular to the points first perceived,
|
||
transversally to the localizable relation to distant or contiguous points.83 A
|
||
point is always a point of origin. But a line of becoming has neither begin-
|
||
ning nor end, departure nor arrival, origin nor destination; to speak of the
|
||
absence of an origin, to make the absence of an origin the origin, is a bad
|
||
play on words. A line of becoming has only a middle. The middle is not an
|
||
average; it is fast motion, it is the absolute speed of movement. A becoming
|
||
is always in the middle; one can only get it by the middle. A becoming is nei-
|
||
ther one nor two, nor the relation of the two; it is the in-between, the border
|
||
or line of flight or descent running perpendicular to both. If becoming is a
|
||
block (a line-block), it is because it constitutes a zone of proximity and
|
||
indiscernibility, a no-man's-land, a nonlocalizable relation sweeping up
|
||
the two distant or contiguous points, carrying one into the proximity of the
|
||
other—and the border-proximity is indifferent to both contiguity and to
|
||
distance. The line or block of becoming that unites the wasp and the orchid
|
||
produces a shared deterritorialization: of the wasp, in that it becomes a lib-
|
||
erated piece of the orchid's reproductive system, but also of the orchid, in
|
||
that it becomes the object of an orgasm in the wasp, also liberated from its
|
||
own reproduction. A coexistence of two asymmetrical movements that
|
||
294 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL ...
|
||
|
||
combine to form a block, down a line of flight that sweeps away selective
|
||
pressures. The line, or the block, does not link the wasp to the orchid, any
|
||
more than it conjugates or mixes them: it passes between them, carrying
|
||
them away in a shared proximity in which the discernibility of points dis-
|
||
appears. The line-system (or block-system) of becoming is opposed to the
|
||
point-system of memory. Becoming is the movement by which the line
|
||
frees itself from the point, and renders points indiscernible: the rhizome,
|
||
the opposite of arborescence; break away from arborescence. Becoming is
|
||
an antimemory. Doubtless, there exists a molecular memory, but as a fac-
|
||
tor of integration into a majoritarian or molar system. Memories always
|
||
have a reterritorialization function. On the other hand, a vector of
|
||
deterritorialization is in no way indeterminate; it is directly plugged into
|
||
the molecular levels, and the more deterritorialized it is, the stronger is the
|
||
contact: it is deterritorialization that makes the aggregate of the molecular
|
||
components "hold together." From this point of view, one may contrast a
|
||
childhood block, or a becoming-child, with the childhood memory: "a"
|
||
molecular child is produced. . . "a" child coexists with us, in a zone of prox-
|
||
imity or a block of becoming, on a line of deterritorialization that carries us
|
||
both off—as opposed to the child we once were, whom we remember or
|
||
phantasize, the molar child whose future is the adult. "This will be child-
|
||
hood, but it must not be my childhood," writes Virginia Woolf. (Orlando
|
||
already does not operate by memories, but by blocks, blocks of ages, block
|
||
of epochs, blocks of the kingdoms of nature, blocks of sexes, forming so
|
||
many becomings between things, or so many lines of deterritoriali-
|
||
zation.)84 Wherever we used the word "memories" in the preceding pages,
|
||
we were wrong to do so; we meant to say "becoming," we were saying
|
||
becoming.
|
||
If the line is opposed to the point (or blocks to memories, becoming to
|
||
the faculty of memory), it is not in an absolute way: a punctual system
|
||
includes a certain utilization of lines, and the block itself assigns the point
|
||
new functions. In a punctual system, a point basically refers to linear coor-
|
||
dinates. Not only are a horizontal line and a vertical line represented, but
|
||
the vertical moves parallel to itself, and the horizontal superposes other
|
||
horizontals upon itself; every point is assigned in relation to the two base
|
||
coordinates, but is also marked on a horizontal line of superposition and
|
||
on a vertical line or plane of displacement. Finally, two points are con-
|
||
nected when any line is drawn from one to the other. A system is termed
|
||
punctual when its lines are taken as coordinates in this way, or as localizable
|
||
connections; for example, systems of arborescence, or molar and mne-
|
||
monic systems in general, are punctual. Memory has a punctual organiza-
|
||
tion because every present refers simultaneously to the horizontal line of
|
||
the flow of time (kinematics), which goes from an old present to the actual
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 295
|
||
|
||
present, and the vertical line of the order of time (stratigraphy), which goes
|
||
from the present to the past, or to the representation of the old present.
|
||
This is, of course, a basic schema that cannot be developed further without
|
||
running into major complications, but it is the one found in representa-
|
||
tions of art forming a "didactic" system, in other words, a mnemotechnics.
|
||
Musical representation, on the one hand, draws a horizontal, melodic line,
|
||
the bass line, upon which other melodic lines are superposed; points are
|
||
assigned that enter into relations of counterpoint between lines. On the
|
||
other hand, it draws a vertical, harmonic line or plane, which moves along
|
||
the horizontals but is no longer dependent upon them; it runs from high to
|
||
low and defines a chord capable of linking up with the following chords.
|
||
Pictorial representation has an analogous form, with means of its own: this
|
||
is not only because the painting has a vertical and a horizontal, but because
|
||
the traits and colors, each on its own account, relate to verticals of displace-
|
||
ment and horizontals of superposition (for example, the vertical cold form,
|
||
or white, light and tonality; the horizontal warm form, or black, chromatics
|
||
and modality, etc.). To cite only relatively recent examples, this is evident
|
||
in the didactic systems of Kandinsky, Klee, and Mondrian, which neces-
|
||
sarily imply an encounter with music.
|
||
Let us summarize the principal characteristics of a punctual system: (1)
|
||
Systems of this kind comprise two base lines, horizontal and vertical; they
|
||
serve as coordinates for assigning points. (2) The horizontal line can be
|
||
superposed vertically and the vertical line can be moved horizontally, in
|
||
such a way that new points are produced or reproduced, under conditions
|
||
of horizontal frequency and vertical resonance. (3) From one point to
|
||
another, a line can (or cannot) be drawn, but if it can it takes the form of a
|
||
localizable connection; diagonals thus play the role of connectors between
|
||
points of different levels or moments, instituting in their turn frequencies
|
||
and resonances on the basis of these points of variable horizon or verticon,
|
||
contiguous or distant.85 These systems are arborescent, mnemonic, molar,
|
||
structural; they are systems ofterritorialization or reterritorialization. The
|
||
line and the diagonal remain totally subordinated to the point because they
|
||
serve as coordinates for a point or as localizable connections for two
|
||
points, running from one point to another.
|
||
Opposed to the punctual system are linear, or rather multilinear, sys-
|
||
tems. Free the line, free the diagonal: every musician or painter has this
|
||
intention. One elaborates a punctual system or a didactic representation,
|
||
but with the aim of making it snap, of sending a tremor through it. A punc-
|
||
tual system is most interesting when there is a musician, painter, writer,
|
||
philosopher to oppose it, who even fabricates it in order to oppose it, like a
|
||
springboard to jump from. History is made only by those who oppose his-
|
||
tory (not by those who insert themselves into it, or even reshape it). This is
|
||
296 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
not done for provocation but happens because the punctual system they
|
||
found ready-made, or themselves invented, must have allowed this opera-
|
||
tion: free the line and the diagonal, draw the line instead of plotting a point,
|
||
produce an imperceptible diagonal instead of clinging to an even elabo-
|
||
rated or reformed vertical or horizontal. When this is done it always goes
|
||
down in History but never comes from it. History may try to break its ties
|
||
to memory; it may make the schemas of memory more elaborate, super-
|
||
pose and shift coordinates, emphasize connections, or deepen breaks. The
|
||
dividing line, however, is not there. The dividing line passes not between
|
||
history and memory but between punctual "history-memory" systems and
|
||
diagonal or multilinear assemblages, which are in no way eternal: they have
|
||
to do with becoming; they are a bit of becoming in the pure state; they are
|
||
transhistorical. There is no act of creation that is not transhistorical and
|
||
does not come up from behind or proceed by way of a liberated line.
|
||
Nietzsche opposes history not to the eternal but to the subhistorical or
|
||
superhistorical: the Untimely, which is another name for haecceity,
|
||
becoming, the innocence of becoming (in other words, forgetting as
|
||
opposed to memory, geography as opposed to history, the map as opposed
|
||
to the tracing, the rhizome as opposed to arborescence). "The unhistorical
|
||
is like an atmosphere within which alone life can germinate and with the
|
||
destruction of which it must vanish. . . . What deed would man be capable
|
||
of if he had not first entered into that vaporous region of the unhis-
|
||
torical?"86 Creations are like mutant abstract lines that have detached
|
||
themselves from the task of representing a world, precisely because they
|
||
assemble a new type of reality that history can only recontain or relocate in
|
||
punctual systems.
|
||
When Boulez casts himself in the role of historian of music, he does so in
|
||
order to show how a great musician, in a very different manner in each case,
|
||
invents a kind of diagonal running between the harmonic vertical and the
|
||
melodic horizon. And in each case it is a different diagonal, a different
|
||
technique, a creation. Moving along this transversal line, which is really a
|
||
line of deterritorialization, there is a sound block that no longer has a point
|
||
of origin, since it is always and already in the middle of the line; and no
|
||
longer has horizontal and vertical coordinates, since it creates its own coor-
|
||
dinates; and no longer forms a localizable connection from one point to
|
||
another, since it is in "nonpulsed time": a deterritorialized rhythmic block
|
||
that has abandoned points, coordinates, and measure, like a drunken boat
|
||
that melds with the line or draws a plane of consistency. Speeds and
|
||
slownesses inject themselves into musical form, sometimes impelling it to
|
||
proliferation, linear microproliferations, and sometimes to extinction,
|
||
sonorous abolition, involution, or both at once. The musician is in the best
|
||
position to say: "I hate the faculty of memory, I hate memories." And that is
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 297
|
||
|
||
because he or she affirms the power of becoming. The Viennese school is
|
||
exemplary of this kind of diagonal, this kind of line-block. But it can
|
||
equally be said that the Viennese school found a new system of territo-
|
||
rialization, of points, verticals, and horizontals that position it in History.
|
||
Another attempt, another creative act, came after it. The important thing
|
||
is that all musicians have always proceeded in this way: drawing their own
|
||
diagonal, however fragile, outside points, outside coordinates and
|
||
localizable connections, in order to float a sound block down a created, lib-
|
||
erated line, in order to unleash in space this mobile and mutant sound
|
||
block, a haecceity (for example, chromaticism, aggregates, and complex
|
||
notes, but already the resources and possibilities of polyphony, etc.).87
|
||
Some have spoken of "oblique vectors" with respect to the organ. The diag-
|
||
onal is often composed of extremely complex lines and spaces of sound. Is
|
||
that the secret of a little phrase or a rhythmic block? Undoubtedly, the
|
||
point now assumes a new and essential creative function. It is no longer
|
||
simply a question of an inevitable destiny reconstituting a punctual sys-
|
||
tem; on the contrary, it is now the point that is subordinated to the line, the
|
||
point now marks the proliferation of the line, or its sudden deviation, its
|
||
acceleration, its slowdown, its furor or agony. Mozart's "microblocks."
|
||
The block may even be reduced to a point, as though to a single note (point-
|
||
block): Berg's B in Wozzeck, Schumann's A. Homage to Schumann, the
|
||
madness of Schumann: the cello wanders across the grid of the orchestra-
|
||
tion, drawing its diagonal, along which the deterritorialized sound block
|
||
moves; or an extremely sober kind of refrain is "treated" by a very elabo-
|
||
rate melodic line and polyphonic architecture.
|
||
In a multilinear system, everything happens at once: the line breaks free
|
||
of the point as origin; the diagonal breaks free of the vertical and the hori-
|
||
zontal as coordinates; and the transversal breaks free of the diagonal as a
|
||
localizable connection between two points. In short, a block-line passes
|
||
amid (au milieu des) sounds and propels itself by its own nonlocalizable
|
||
middle {milieu). The sound block is the intermezzo. It is a body without
|
||
organs, an antimemory pervading musical organization, and is all the
|
||
more sonorous: "The Schumannian body does not stay in place. . . . The
|
||
intermezzo [is] consubstantial with the entire Schumannian oeuvre.... At
|
||
the limit, there are only intermezzi. ... The Schumannian body knows
|
||
only bifurcations; it does not construct itself, it keeps diverging according
|
||
to an accumulation of interludes.... Schumannian beating is panic, but it
|
||
is also coded ... and it is because the panic of the blows apparently keeps
|
||
within the limits of a docile language that it is ordinarily not perceived.. . .
|
||
Let us imagine for tonality two contradictory (and yet concomitant) sta-
|
||
tuses. On the one hand . . . a screen, a language intended to articulate the
|
||
body.. .according to a known organization... .On the other hand, contra-
|
||
298 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
dictorily... tonality becomes the ready servant of the beats within another
|
||
level it claims to domesticate."88
|
||
Does the same thing, strictly the same thing, apply to painting? In effect,
|
||
the point does not make the line; the line sweeps away the deterritorialized
|
||
point, carries it off under its outside influence; the line does not go from
|
||
one point to another, but runs between points in a different direction that
|
||
renders them indiscernible. The line has become the diagonal, which has
|
||
broken free from the vertical and the horizontal. But the diagonal has
|
||
already become the transversal, the semidiagonal or free straight line, the
|
||
broken or angular line, or the curve—always in the midst of themselves.
|
||
Between the white vertical and the black horizontal lie Klee's gray,
|
||
Kandinsky's red, Monet's purple; each forms a block of color. This line is
|
||
without origin, since it always begins off the painting, which only holds it
|
||
by the middle; it is without coordinates, because it melds with a plane of
|
||
consistency upon which it floats and that it creates; it is without localizable
|
||
connection, because it has lost not only its representative function but any
|
||
function of outlining a form of any kind—by this token, the line has
|
||
become abstract, truly abstract and mutant, a visual block; and under these
|
||
conditions the point assumes creative functions again, as a color-point or
|
||
line-point.89 The line is between points, in their midst, and no longer goes
|
||
from one point to another. It does not outline a shape. "He did not paint
|
||
things, he painted between things." There is no falser problem in painting
|
||
than depth and, in particular, perspective. For perspective is only a histori-
|
||
cal manner of occupying diagonals or transversals, lines of flight [lignes de
|
||
fuite: here, the lines in a painting moving toward the vanishing point, or
|
||
point de fuite—Trans.], in other words, of reterritorializing the moving vis-
|
||
ual block. We use the word "occupy" in the sense of "giving an occupation
|
||
to," fixing a memory and a code, assigning a function. But the lines of
|
||
flight, the transversals, are suitable for many other functions besides this
|
||
molar function. Lines of flight as perspective lines, far from being made to
|
||
represent depth, themselves invent the possibility of such a representation,
|
||
which occupies them only for an instant, at a given moment. Perspective,
|
||
and even depth, are the reterritorialization of lines of flight, which alone
|
||
created painting by carrying it farther. What is called central perspective in
|
||
particular plunged the multiplicity of escapes and the dynamism of lines
|
||
into a punctual black hole. Conversely, it is true that problems of perspec-
|
||
tive triggered a whole profusion of creative lines, a mass release of visual
|
||
blocks, at the very moment they claimed to have gained mastery over them.
|
||
Is painting, in each of its acts of creation, engaged in a becoming as intense
|
||
as that of music?
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 299
|
||
|
||
Becoming-Music. We have tried to define in the case of Western music
|
||
(although the other musical traditions confront an analogous problem,
|
||
under different conditions, to which they find different solutions) a block
|
||
of becoming at the level of expression, or a block of expression: this block of
|
||
becoming rests on transversals that continually escape from the coordi-
|
||
nates or punctual systems functioning as musical codes at a given moment.
|
||
It is obvious that there is a block of content corresponding to this block of
|
||
expression. It is not really a correspondence; there would be no mobile
|
||
"block" if a content, itself musical (and not a subject or a theme), were not
|
||
always interfering with the expression. What does music deal with, what is
|
||
the content indissociable from sound expression? It is hard to say, but it is
|
||
something: a child dies, a child plays, a woman is born, a woman dies, a
|
||
bird arrives, a bird flies off. We wish to say that these are not accidental
|
||
themes in music (even if it is possible to multiply examples), much less imi-
|
||
tative exercises; they are something essential. Why a child, a woman, a
|
||
bird? It is because musical expression is inseparable from a becoming-
|
||
woman, a becoming-child, a becoming-animal that constitute its content.
|
||
Why does the child die, or the bird fall as though pierced by an arrow?
|
||
Because of the "danger" inherent in any line that escapes, in any line of
|
||
flight or creative deterritorialization: the danger of veering toward de-
|
||
struction, toward abolition. Melisande [in Debussy's opera, Pelleas et
|
||
Melisande—Trans.], a child-woman, a secret, dies twice ("it's the poor lit-
|
||
tle dear's turn now"). Music is never tragic, music is joy. But there are times
|
||
it necessarily gives us a taste for death; not so much happiness as dying hap-
|
||
pily, being extinguished. Not as a function of a death instinct it allegedly
|
||
awakens in us, but of a dimension proper to its sound assemblage, to its
|
||
sound machine, the moment that must be confronted, the moment the
|
||
transversal turns into a line of abolition. Peace and exasperation.90 Music
|
||
has a thirst for destruction, every kind of destruction, extinction, breakage,
|
||
dislocation. Is that not its potential "fascism"? Whenever a musician
|
||
writes In Memoriam, it is not so much a question of an inspirational motif
|
||
or a memory, but on the contrary of a becoming that is only confronting its
|
||
own danger, even taking a fall in order to rise again: a becoming-child, a
|
||
becoming-woman, a becoming-animal, insofar as they are the content of
|
||
music itself and continue to the point of death.
|
||
We would say that the refrain is properly musical content, the block of
|
||
content proper to music. A child comforts itself in the dark or claps its
|
||
hands or invents a way of walking, adapting it to the cracks in the sidewalk,
|
||
or chants "Fort-Da" (psychoanalysts deal with the Fort-Da very poorly
|
||
when they treat it as a phonological opposition or a symbolic component of
|
||
the language-unconscious, when it is in fact a refrain). Tra la la. A woman
|
||
sings to herself, "I heard her softly singing a tune to herself under her
|
||
300 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
breath." A bird launches into its refrain. All of music is pervaded by bird
|
||
songs, in a thousand different ways, from Jannequin to Messiaen. Frr, Frr.
|
||
Music is pervaded by childhood blocks, by blocks of femininity. Music is
|
||
pervaded by every minority, and yet composes an immense power. Chil-
|
||
dren's, women's, ethnic, and territorial refrains, refrains of love and
|
||
destruction: the birth of rhythm. Schumann's work is made of refrains, of
|
||
childhood blocks, which he treats in a very special way: his own kind of
|
||
becoming-child, his own kind of becoming-woman, Clara. It would be pos-
|
||
sible to catalogue the transversal or diagonal utilizations of the refrain in
|
||
the history of music, all of the children's Games and Kinderszenen, all of
|
||
the bird songs. But such a catalogue would be useless because it would seem
|
||
like a multiplication of examples of themes, subjects, and motifs, when it is
|
||
in fact a question of the most essential and necessary content of music. The
|
||
motif of the refrain may be anxiety, fear, joy, love, work, walking, territory
|
||
. . . but the refrain itself is the content of music.
|
||
We are not at all saying that the refrain is the origin of music, or that
|
||
music begins with it. It is not really known when music begins. The refrain
|
||
is rather a means of preventing music, warding it off, or forgoing it. But
|
||
music exists because the refrain exists also, because music takes up the
|
||
refrain, lays hold of it as a content in a form of expression, because it forms
|
||
a block with it in order to take it somewhere else. The child's refrain, which
|
||
is not music, forms a block with the becoming-child of music: once again,
|
||
this asymmetrical composition is necessary. "Ah, vous dirai-je maman"
|
||
("Ah, mamma, now you shall know") in Mozart, Mozart's refrains. A
|
||
theme in C, followed by twelve variations; not only is each note of the
|
||
theme doubled, but the theme is doubled internally. Music submits the
|
||
refrain to this very special treatment of the diagonal or transversal, it
|
||
uproots the refrain from its territoriality. Music is a creative, active opera-
|
||
tion that consists in deterritorializing the refrain. Whereas the refrain is
|
||
essentially territorial, territorializing, or reterritorializing, music makes it
|
||
a deterritorialized content for a deterritorializing form of expression. Par-
|
||
don that sentence: what musicians do should be musical, it should be writ-
|
||
ten in music. Instead, we will give a figurative example: Mussorgsky's
|
||
"Lullaby," in Songs and Dances of Death, presents an exhausted mother sit-
|
||
ting up with her sick child; she is relieved by a visitor, Death, who sings a
|
||
lullaby in which each couplet ends with an obsessive, sober refrain, a repet-
|
||
itive rhythm with only one note, a point-block: "Shush, little child, sleep
|
||
my little child" (not only does the child die, but the deterritorialization of
|
||
the refrain is doubled by Death in person, who replaces the mother).
|
||
Is the situation similar for painting, and if so, how? In no way do we
|
||
believe in a fine-arts system; we believe in very diverse problems whose
|
||
solutions are found in heterogeneous arts. To us, Art is a false concept, a
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 301
|
||
|
||
solely nominal concept; this does not, however, preclude the possibility of a
|
||
simultaneous usage of the various arts within a determinable multiplicity.
|
||
The "problem" within which painting is inscribed is that of the face-
|
||
landscape. That of music is entirely different: it is the problem of the
|
||
refrain. Each arises at a certain moment, under certain conditions, on the
|
||
line of its problem; but there is no possible structural or symbolic corre-
|
||
spondence between the two, unless one translates them into punctual sys-
|
||
tems. We have distinguished the following three states of the landscape
|
||
problem: (1) semiotic systems of corporeality, silhouettes, postures, colors,
|
||
and lines (these semiotic systems are already present in profusion among
|
||
animals; the head is part of the body, and the body has the milieu, the
|
||
biotope as its correlate; these systems already display very pure lines as, for
|
||
example, in the "grass stem" behavior); (2) an organization of the face,
|
||
white wall/black holes, face/eyes, or facial profile/sideview of the eyes (this
|
||
semiotic system of faciality has the landscape as its correlate: facialization
|
||
of the entire body and landscapification of all the milieus, Christ as the
|
||
European central point); (3) a deterritorialization effaces and landscapes,
|
||
in favor of probe-heads whose lines no longer outline a form or form a con-
|
||
tour, and whose colors no longer lay out a landscape (this is the pictorial
|
||
semiotic system: Put the face and the landscape to flight. For example,
|
||
what Mondrian correctly calls a "landscape": a pure, absolutely deterrito-
|
||
rialized landscape).
|
||
For convenience, we presented three successive and distinct states, but
|
||
only provisionally. We cannot decide whether animals have painting, even
|
||
though they do not paint on canvas, and even when hormones induce their
|
||
colors and lines; even here, there is little foundation for a clear-cut distinc-
|
||
tion between animals and human beings. Conversely, we must say that
|
||
painting does not begin with so-called abstract art but recreates the silhou-
|
||
ettes and postures of corporeality, and is already fully in operation in the
|
||
face-landscape organization (the way in which painters "work" the face of
|
||
Christ, and make it leak from the religious code in all directions). The aim
|
||
of painting has always been the deterritorialization of faces and land-
|
||
scapes, either by a reactivation of corporeality, or by a liberation of lines or
|
||
colors, or both at the same time. There are many becomings-animal,
|
||
becomings-woman, and becomings-child in painting.
|
||
The problem of music is different, if it is true that its problem is the
|
||
refrain. Deterritorializing the refrain, inventing lines of deterritorializa-
|
||
tion for the refrain, implies procedures and constructions that have noth-
|
||
ing to do with those of painting (outside of vague analogies of the sort
|
||
painters have often tried to establish). Again, it is not certain whether we
|
||
can draw a dividing line between animals and human beings: Are there not,
|
||
as Messiaen believes, musician birds and nonmusician birds? Is the bird's
|
||
302 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . .
|
||
|
||
refrain necessarily territorial, or is it not already used for very subtle
|
||
deterritorializations, for selective lines of flight? The difference between
|
||
noise and sound is definitely not a basis for a definition of music, or even
|
||
for the distinction between musician birds and nonmusician birds. Rather,
|
||
it is the labor of the refrain: Does it remain territorial and territorializing,
|
||
or is it carried away in a moving block that draws a transversal across all
|
||
coordinates—and all of the intermediaries between the two? Music is pre-
|
||
cisely the adventure of the refrain: the way music lapses back into a refrain
|
||
(in our head, in Swann's head, in the pseudo-probe-heads on TV and radio,
|
||
the music of a great musician used as a signature tune, a ditty); the way it
|
||
lays hold of the refrain, makes it more and more sober, reduced to a few
|
||
notes, then takes it down a creative line that is so much richer, no origin or
|
||
end of which is in sight. ..
|
||
Leroi-Gourhan established a distinction and correlation between two
|
||
poles, "hand-tool" and "face-language." But there it was a question of dis-
|
||
tinguishing a form of content and a form of expression. Here we are consid-
|
||
ering expressions that hold their content within themselves, so we must
|
||
make a different distinction: the face with its visual correlates (eyes) con-
|
||
cerns painting; the voice with its auditory correlates (the ear is itself a
|
||
refrain, it is shaped like one) concerns music. Music is a deterrito-
|
||
rialization of the voice, which becomes less and less tied to language, just as
|
||
painting is a deterritorialization of the face. Traits of vocability can indeed
|
||
be indexed to traits of faciality, as in lipreading; they are not, however, in
|
||
correspondence, especially when they are carried off by the respective
|
||
movements of music and painting. The voice is far ahead of the face, very
|
||
far ahead. Entitling a musical work Visage (Face) thus seems to be the
|
||
greatest of sound paradoxes.91 The only way to "line up" the two problems
|
||
of painting and music is to take a criterion extrinsic to the fiction of the fine
|
||
arts, to compare the forces of deterritorialization in each case. Music seems
|
||
to have a much stronger deterritorializing force, at once more intense and
|
||
much more collective, and the voice seems to have a much greater power of
|
||
deterritorialization. Perhaps this trait explains the collective fascination
|
||
exerted by music, and even the potentiality of the "fascist" danger we men-
|
||
tioned a little earlier: music (drums, trumpets) draws people and armies
|
||
into a race that can go all the way to the abyss (much more so than banners
|
||
and flags, which are paintings, means of classification and rallying). It may
|
||
be that musicians are individually more reactionary than painters, more
|
||
religious, less "social"; they nevertheless wield a collective force infinitely
|
||
greater than that of painting: "The chorus formed by the assembly of the
|
||
people is a very powerful bond..." It is always possible to explain this
|
||
force by the material conditions of musical emission and reception, but it
|
||
is preferable to take the reverse approach; these conditions are explained
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 303
|
||
|
||
by the force of deterritorialization of music. It could be said that from the
|
||
standpoint of the mutant abstract machine painting and music do not cor-
|
||
respond to the same thresholds, or that the pictorial machine and the musi-
|
||
cal machine do not have the same index. There is a "backwardness" of
|
||
painting in relation to music, as Klee, the most musicianly of painters,
|
||
observed.92 Maybe that is why many people prefer painting, or why aes-
|
||
thetics took painting as its privileged model: there is no question that it
|
||
"scares" people less. Even its relations to capitalism and social formations
|
||
are not at all of the same type.
|
||
Doubtless, in each case we must simultaneously consider factors of
|
||
territoriality, deterritorialization, and reterritorialization. Animal and
|
||
child refrains seem to be territorial: therefore they are not "music." But
|
||
when music lays hold of the refrain and deterritorializes it, and deterrito-
|
||
rializes the voice, when it lays hold of the refrain and sends it racing off in
|
||
a rhythmic sound block, when the refrain "becomes" Schumann or
|
||
Debussy, it is through a system of melodic and harmonic coordinates by
|
||
means of which music reterritorializes upon itself, qua music. Con-
|
||
versely, we shall see that in certain cases even the animal refrain possesses
|
||
forces of deterritorialization much more intense than animal silhouettes,
|
||
postures, and colors. We must therefore take a number of factors into con-
|
||
sideration: relative territorialities, their respective deterritorializations,
|
||
and their correlative reterritorializations, several types of them (for
|
||
example, intrinsic reterritorializations such as musical coordinates, and
|
||
extrinsic ones such as the deterioration of the refrain into a hackneyed
|
||
formula, or music into a ditty). The fact that there is no deterrito-
|
||
rialization without a special reterritorialization should prompt us to
|
||
rethink the abiding correlation between the molar and the molecular: no
|
||
flow, no becoming-molecular escapes from a molar formation without
|
||
molar components accompanying it, forming passages or perceptible
|
||
landmarks for the imperceptible processes.
|
||
The becoming-woman, the becoming-child of music are present in the
|
||
problem of the machining of the voice. Machining the voice was the first
|
||
musical operation. As we know, the problem was resolved in Western
|
||
music in two different ways, in Italy and in England: the head voice of the
|
||
countertenor, who sings "above his voice," or whose voice operates inside
|
||
the sinuses and at the back of the throat and the palate without relying on
|
||
the diaphragm or passing through the bronchial tubes; and the stomach
|
||
voice of the castrati, "stronger, more voluminous, more languid," as if
|
||
they gave carnal matter to the imperceptible, impalpable, and aerial.
|
||
Dominique Fernandez wrote a fine book on this subject; he shows, fortu-
|
||
nately refraining from any psychoanalytic discussion of a link between
|
||
music and castration, that the musical problem of the machinery of the
|
||
304 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
voice necessarily implies the abolition of the overall dualism machine, in
|
||
other words, the molar formation assigning voices to the "man or
|
||
woman."93 Being a man or a woman no longer exists in music. It is not cer-
|
||
tain, however, that the myth of the androgyne Fernandez invokes is ade-
|
||
quate. It is a question not of myth but of real becoming. The voice itself
|
||
must attain a becoming-woman or a becoming-child. That is the prodi-
|
||
gious content of music. It is no longer a question, as Fernandez observes, of
|
||
imitating a woman or a child, even if it is a child who is singing. The musi-
|
||
cal voice itself becomes-child at the same time as the child becomes-
|
||
sonorous, purely sonorous. No child could ever have done that, or if one
|
||
did, it would be by becoming in addition something other than a child, a
|
||
child belonging to a different, strangely sensual and celestial, world. In
|
||
short, the deterritorialization is double: the voice is deterritorialized in a
|
||
becoming-child, but the child it becomes is itself deterritorialized, unen-
|
||
gendered, becoming. "The child grew wings," said Schumann. We find the
|
||
same zigzag movement in the becomings-animal of music: Marcel More
|
||
shows that the music of Mozart is permeated by a becoming-horse, or
|
||
becomings-bird. But no musician amuses himself by "playing" horse or
|
||
bird. If the sound block has a becoming-animal as its content, then the ani-
|
||
mal simultaneously becomes, in sonority, something else, something abso-
|
||
lute, night, death, joy—certainly not a generality or a simplification, but a
|
||
haecceity, this death, that night. Music takes as its content a becoming-
|
||
animal; but in that becoming-animal the horse, for example, takes as its
|
||
expression soft kettledrum beats, winged like hooves from heaven or hell;
|
||
and the birds find expression in gruppeti, appoggiaturas, staccato notes
|
||
that transform them into so many souls.94 It is the accents that form the
|
||
diagonal in Mozart, the accents above all. If one does not follow the
|
||
accents, if one does not observe them, one falls back into a relatively
|
||
impoverished punctual system. The human musician is deterritorialized
|
||
in the bird, but it is a bird that is itself deterritorialized, "transfigured," a
|
||
celestial bird that has just as much of a becoming as that which becomes
|
||
with it. Captain Ahab is engaged in an irresistible becoming-whale with
|
||
Moby-Dick; but the animal, Moby-Dick, must simultaneously become an
|
||
unbearable pure whiteness, a shimmering pure white wall, a silver thread
|
||
that stretches out and supples up "like" a girl, or twists like a whip, or stands
|
||
like a rampart. Can it be that literature sometimes catches up with paint-
|
||
ing, and even music? And that painting catches up with music? (More cites
|
||
Klee's birds but on the other hand fails to understand what Messiaen says
|
||
about bird song.) No art is imitative, no art can be imitative or figurative.
|
||
Suppose a painter "represents" a bird; this is in fact a becoming-bird that
|
||
can occur only to the extent that the bird itself is in the process of becoming
|
||
something else, a pure line and pure color. Thus imitation self-destructs,
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 305
|
||
|
||
since the imitator unknowingly enters into a becoming that conjugates
|
||
with the unknowing becoming of that which he or she imitates. One imi-
|
||
tates only if one fails, when one fails. The painter and musician do not imi-
|
||
tate the animal, they become-animal at the same time as the animal
|
||
becomes what they willed, at the deepest level of their concord with
|
||
Nature.95 Becoming is always double, that which one becomes becomes no
|
||
less than the one that becomes—block is formed, essentially mobile, never
|
||
in equilibrium. Mondrian's is the perfect square. It balances on one corner
|
||
and produces a diagonal that half-opens its closure, carrying away both
|
||
sides.
|
||
Becoming is never imitating. When Hitchcock does birds, he does not
|
||
reproduce bird calls, he produces an electronic sound like a field of intensi-
|
||
ties or a wave of vibrations, a continuous variation, like a terrible threat
|
||
welling up inside us.96 And this applies not only to the "arts": Moby-Dick's
|
||
effect also hinges the pure lived experience of double becoming, and the
|
||
book would not have the same beauty otherwise. The tarantella is a strange
|
||
dance that magically cures or exorcises the supposed victims of a tarantula
|
||
bite. But when the victim does this dance, can he or she be said to be imitat-
|
||
ing the spider, to be identifying with it, even in an identification through an
|
||
"archetypal" or "agonistic" struggle? No, because the victim, the patient,
|
||
the person who is sick, becomes a dancing spider only to the extent that the
|
||
spider itself is supposed to become a pure silhouette, pure color and pure
|
||
sound to which the person dances.97 One does not imitate; one constitutes
|
||
a block of becoming. Imitation enters in only as an adjustment of the block,
|
||
like a finishing touch, a wink, a signature. But everything of importance
|
||
happens elsewhere: in the becoming-spider of the dance, which occurs on
|
||
the condition that the spider itself becomes sound and color, orchestra and
|
||
painting. Take the case of the local folk hero, Alexis the Trotter, who ran
|
||
"like" a horse at extraordinary speed, whipped himself with a short switch,
|
||
whinnied, reared, kicked, knelt, lay down on the ground in the manner of a
|
||
horse, competed against them in races, and against bicycles and trains. He
|
||
imitated a horse to make people laugh. But he had a deeper zone of proxim-
|
||
ity or indiscernibility. Sources tell us that he was never as much of a horse
|
||
as when he played the harmonica: precisely because he no longer needed a
|
||
regulating or secondary imitation. It is said that he called his harmonica his
|
||
"chops-destroyer" and played the instrument twice as fast as anyone else,
|
||
doubled the beat, imposed a nonhuman tempo.98 Alexis became all the
|
||
more horse when the horse's bit became a harmonica, and the horse's trot
|
||
went into double time. As always, the same must be said of the animals
|
||
themselves. For not only do animals have colors and sounds, but they do
|
||
not wait for the painter or musician to use those colors and sounds in a
|
||
painting or music, in other words, to enter into determinate becomings-
|
||
306 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
color and becomings-sounds by means of components of deterrito-
|
||
rialization (we will return to this point later). Ethology is advanced enough
|
||
to have entered this realm.
|
||
We are not at all arguing for an aesthetics of qualities, as if the pure
|
||
quality (color, sound, etc.) held the secret of a becoming without measure,
|
||
as in Philebus. Pure qualities still seem to us to be punctual systems: They
|
||
are reminiscences, they are either transcendent or floating memories or
|
||
seeds of phantasy. A functionalist conception, on the other hand, only
|
||
considers the function a quality fulfills in a specific assemblage, or in
|
||
passing from one assemblage to another. The quality must be considered
|
||
from the standpoint of the becoming that grasps it, instead of becoming
|
||
being considered from the standpoint of intrinsic qualities having the
|
||
value of archetypes or phylogenetic memories. For example, whiteness,
|
||
color, is gripped in a becoming-animal that can be that of the painter or of
|
||
Captain Ahab, and at the same time in a becoming-color, a becoming-
|
||
whiteness, that can be that of the animal itself. Moby-Dick's whiteness is
|
||
the special index of his becoming-solitary. Colors, silhouettes, and ani-
|
||
mal refrains are indexes of becoming-conjugal or becoming-social that
|
||
also imply components of deterritorialization. A quality functions only
|
||
as a line of deterritorialization of an assemblage, or in going from one
|
||
assemblage to another. This is why an animal-block is something other
|
||
than a phylogenetic memory, and a childhood block something other
|
||
than a childhood memory. In Kafka, a quality never functions for itself or
|
||
as a memory, but rather rectifies an assemblage in which it is deterritori-
|
||
alized, and, conversely, for which it provides a line of deterritori-
|
||
alization; for example, the childhood steeple passes into the castle tower,
|
||
takes it at the level of its zone of indiscernibility ("battlements that were
|
||
irregular, broken, fumbling"), and launches down a line of flight (as if one
|
||
of the tenants "had burst through the roof').99 If things are more compli-
|
||
cated and less sober for Proust, it is because for him qualities retain an air
|
||
of reminiscence or phantasy, and yet with Proust as well these are func-
|
||
tional blocks acting not as memories or phantasies but as a becoming-
|
||
child, a becoming-woman, as components of deterritorialization passing
|
||
from one assemblage to another.
|
||
To the theorems of simple deterritorialization we encountered earlier
|
||
(in our discussion of the face),100 we can now add others on generalized
|
||
double deterritorialization. Theorem Five: deterritorialization is always
|
||
double, because it implies the coexistence of a major variable and a minor
|
||
variable in simultaneous becoming (the two terms of a becoming do not
|
||
exchange places, there is no identification between them, they are instead
|
||
drawn into an asymmetrical block in which both change to the same extent,
|
||
and which constitutes their zone of proximity). Theorem Six: in non-
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL . . . D 307
|
||
|
||
symmetrical double deterritorialization it is possible to assign a deter-
|
||
ritorializing force and a deterritorialized force, even if the same force
|
||
switches from one value to the other depending on the "moment" or aspect
|
||
considered; furthermore, it is the least deterritorialized element that
|
||
always triggers the deterritorialization of the most deterritorializing ele-
|
||
ment, which then reacts back upon it in full force. Theorem Seven: the
|
||
deterritorializing element has the relative role of expression, and the
|
||
deterritorialized element the relative role of content (as evident in the
|
||
arts); but not only does the content have nothing to do with an external sub-
|
||
ject or object, since it forms an asymmetrical block with the expression, but
|
||
the deterritorialization carries the expression and the content to a proxim-
|
||
ity where the distinction between them ceases to be relevant, or where the
|
||
deterritorialization creates their indiscernibility (example: the sound diag-
|
||
onal as the musical form of expression, and becomings-woman, -child,
|
||
-animal as the contents proper to music, as refrains). Theorem Eight: one
|
||
assemblage does not have the same forces or even speeds of deterrito-
|
||
rialization as another; in each instance, the indices and coefficients must
|
||
be calculated according to the block of becoming under consideration, and
|
||
in relation to the mutations of an abstract machine (for example, there is a
|
||
certain slowness, a certain viscosity, of painting in relation to music; but
|
||
one cannot draw a symbolic boundary between the human being and ani-
|
||
mal. One can only calculate and compare powers of deterritorialization).
|
||
Fernandez demonstrates the presence of becomings-woman, becom-
|
||
ings-child in vocal music. Then he decries the rise of instrumental and
|
||
orchestral music; he is particularly critical of Verdi and Wagner for having
|
||
resexualized the voice, for having restored the binary machine in response
|
||
to the requirements of capitalism, which wants a man to be a man and a
|
||
woman a woman, each with his or her own voice: Verdi-voices, Wagner-
|
||
voices, are reterritorialized upon man and woman. He explains the prema-
|
||
ture disappearance of Rossini and Bellini (the retirement of the first and
|
||
death of the second) by their hopeless feeling that the vocal becomings of
|
||
the opera were no longer possible. However, Fernandez does not ask under
|
||
what auspices, and with what new types of diagonals, this occurs. To begin
|
||
with, it is true that the voice ceases to be machined for itself, with simple
|
||
instrumental accompaniment; it ceases to be a stratum or a line of expres-
|
||
sion that stands on its own. But why? Music crossed a new threshold of
|
||
deterritorialization, beyond which it is the instrument that machines the
|
||
voice, and the voice and instrument are carried on the same plane in a rela-
|
||
tion that is sometimes one of confrontation, sometimes one of compensa-
|
||
tion, sometimes one of exchange and complementarity. The lied, in
|
||
particular Schumann's lieder, perhaps marks the first appearance of this
|
||
pure movement that places the voice and the piano on the same plane of
|
||
308 D 1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL...
|
||
|
||
consistency, makes the piano an instrument of delirium, and prepares the
|
||
way for Wagnerian opera. Even a case like Verdi's: it has often been said
|
||
that his opera remains lyrical and vocal in spite of its destruction of the bel
|
||
canto, and in spite of the importance of orchestration in the final works;
|
||
still, voices are instrumentalized and make extraordinary gains in tessitura
|
||
or extension (the production of the Verdi-baritone, of the Verdi-soprano).
|
||
At any rate, the issue is not a given composer, especially not Verdi, or a
|
||
given genre, but the more general movement affecting music, the slow
|
||
mutation of the musical machine. If the voice returns to a binary distribu-
|
||
tion of the sexes, this occurs in relation to binary groupings of instruments
|
||
in orchestration. There are always molar systems in music that serve as
|
||
coordinates; this dualist system of the sexes that reappears on the level of
|
||
the voice, this molar and punctual distribution, serves as a foundation for
|
||
new molecular flows that then intersect, conjugate, are swept up in a kind
|
||
of instrumentation and orchestration that tend to be part of the creation
|
||
itself. Voices may be reterritorialized on the distribution of the two sexes,
|
||
but the continuous sound flow still passes between them as in a difference
|
||
of potential.
|
||
This brings us to the second point: the principal problem concerning
|
||
this new threshold of deterritorialization of the voice is no longer that of a
|
||
properly vocal becoming-woman or becoming-child, but that of a
|
||
becoming-molecular in which the voice itself is instrumentalized. Of
|
||
course, becomings-woman and -child remain just as important, even take
|
||
on new importance, but only to the extent that they convey another truth:
|
||
what was produced was already a molecular child, a molecular woman .. .
|
||
We need only think of Debussy: the becoming-child and the becoming-
|
||
woman in his works are intense but are now inseparable from a molecu-
|
||
larization of the motif, a veritable "chemistry" achieved through orches-
|
||
tration. The child and the woman are now inseparable from the sea and the
|
||
water molecule (Sirens, precisely, represents one of the first complete
|
||
attempts to integrate the voice with the orchestra). Already Wagner was
|
||
reproached for the "elementary" character of his music, for its aquaticism,
|
||
or its "atomization" of the motif, "a subdivision into infinitely small
|
||
units." This becomes even clearer if we think of becoming-animal: birds
|
||
are still just as important, yet the reign of birds seems to have been replaced
|
||
by the age of insects, with its much more molecular vibrations, chirring,
|
||
rustling, buzzing, clicking, scratching, and scraping. Birds are vocal, but
|
||
insects are instrumental: drums and violins, guitars and cymbals.101 A
|
||
becoming-insect has replaced becoming-bird, or forms a block with it. The
|
||
insect is closer, better able to make audible the truth that all becomings are
|
||
molecular (cf. Martenot's waves, electronic music). The molecular has the
|
||
capacity to make the elementary communicate with the cosmic: precisely
|
||
1730: BECOMING-INTENSE, BECOMING-ANIMAL... D 309
|
||
|
||
because it effects a dissolution of form that connects the most diverse lon-
|
||
gitudes and latitudes, the most varied speeds and slownesses, which guar-
|
||
antees a continuum by stretching variation far beyond its formal limits.
|
||
Rediscover Mozart, and that the "theme" was a variation from the start.
|
||
Varese explains that the sound molecule (the block) separates into ele-
|
||
ments arranged in different ways according to variable relations of speed,
|
||
but also into so many waves or flows of a sonic energy irradiating the entire
|
||
universe, a headlong line of flight. That is how he populated the Gobi
|
||
desert with insects and stars constituting a becoming-music of the world, or
|
||
a diagonal for a cosmos. Messiaen presents multiple chromatic durations
|
||
in coalescence, "alternating between the longest and the shortest, in order
|
||
to suggest the idea of the relations between the infinitely long durations of
|
||
the stars and mountains and the infinitely short ones of the insects and
|
||
atoms: a cosmic, elementary power that... derives above all from the labor
|
||
of rhythm."102 The same thing that leads a musician to discover the birds
|
||
also leads him to discover the elementary and the cosmic. Both combine to
|
||
form a block, a universe fiber, a diagonal or complex space. Music dis-
|
||
patches molecular flows. Of course, as Messiaen says, music is not the priv-
|
||
ilege of human beings: the universe, the cosmos, is made of refrains; the
|
||
question in music is that of a power of deterritorialization permeating
|
||
nature, animals, the elements, and deserts as much as human beings. The
|
||
question is more what is not musical in human beings, and what already is
|
||
musical in nature. Moreover, what Messiaen discovered in music is the
|
||
same thing the ethologists discovered in animals: human beings are hardly
|
||
at an advantage, except in the means of overcoding, of making punctual
|
||
systems. That is even the opposite of having an advantage; through
|
||
becomings-woman, -child, -animal, or -molecular, nature opposes its
|
||
power, and the power of music, to the machines of human beings, the roar
|
||
of factories and bombers. And it is necessary to reach that point, it is neces-
|
||
sary for the nonmusical sound of the human being to form a block with the
|
||
becoming-music of sound, for them to confront and embrace each other
|
||
like two wrestlers who can no longer break free from each other's grasp, and
|
||
slide down a sloping line: "Let the choirs represent the survivors. . . Faintly
|
||
one hears the sound of cicadas. Then the notes of a lark, followed by the
|
||
mockingbird. Someone laughs . . . A woman sobs . . . From a male a great
|
||
shout: WE ARE LOST! A woman's voice: WE ARE SAVED! Staccato cries: Lost!
|
||
Saved! Lost! Saved!"103
|
||
11. 1837: Of the Refrain
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Paul Klee, Twittering Machine, 1922
|
||
Copyright © 1987 by Cosmopress, Geneva
|
||
Watercolor, pen and ink, 161A x 12" (without margins)
|
||
Collection, The Museum of Modern Art, New York
|
||
Purchase
|
||
|
||
|
||
310
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 311
|
||
|
||
I. A child in the dark, gripped with fear, comforts himself by singing under
|
||
his breath. He walks and halts to his song. Lost, he takes shelter, or orients
|
||
himself with his little song as best he can. The song is like a rough sketch of a
|
||
calming and stabilizing, calm and stable, center in the heart of chaos. Per-
|
||
haps the child skips as he sings, hastens or slows his pace. But the song itself
|
||
is already a skip: it jumps from chaos to the beginnings of order in chaos
|
||
and is in danger of breaking apart at any moment. There is always sonority
|
||
in Ariadne's thread. Or the song of Orpheus.
|
||
II. Now we are at home. But home does not preexist: it was necessary to
|
||
draw a circle around that uncertain and fragile center, to organize a limited
|
||
space. Many, very diverse, components have a part in this, landmarks and
|
||
marks of all kinds. This was already true of the previous case. But now the
|
||
components are used for organizing a space, not for the momentary deter-
|
||
mination of a center. The forces of chaos are kept outside as much as possi-
|
||
ble, and the interior space protects the germinal forces of a task to fulfill or
|
||
a deed to do. This involves an activity of selection, elimination and extrac-
|
||
tion, in order to prevent the interior forces of the earth from being sub-
|
||
merged, to enable them to resist, or even to take something from chaos
|
||
across the filter or sieve of the space that has been drawn. Sonorous or vocal
|
||
components are very important: a wall of sound, or at least a wall with
|
||
some sonic bricks in it. A child hums to summon the strength for the
|
||
schoolwork she has to hand in. A housewife sings to herself, or listens to the
|
||
radio, as she marshals the antichaos forces of her work. Radios and televi-
|
||
sion sets are like sound walls around every household and mark territories
|
||
(the neighbor complains when it gets too loud). For sublime deeds like the
|
||
foundation of a city or the fabrication of a golem, one draws a circle, or bet-
|
||
ter yet walks in a circle as in a children's dance, combining rhythmic vowels
|
||
and consonants that correspond to the interior forces of creation as to the
|
||
differentiated parts of an organism. A mistake in speed, rhythm, or har-
|
||
mony would be catastrophic because it would bring back the forces of
|
||
chaos, destroying both creator and creation.
|
||
III. Finally, one opens the circle a crack, opens it all the way, lets some-
|
||
one in, calls someone, or else goes out oneself, launches forth. One opens
|
||
the circle not on the side where the old forces of chaos press against it but in
|
||
another region, one created by the circle itself. As though the circle tended
|
||
on its own to open onto a future, as a function of the working forces it shel-
|
||
ters. This time, it is in order to join with the forces of the future, cosmic
|
||
forces. One launches forth, hazards an improvisation. But to improvise is
|
||
to join with the World, or meld with it. One ventures from home on the
|
||
thread of a tune. Along sonorous, gestural, motor lines that mark the
|
||
customary path of a child and graft themselves onto or begin to bud "lines
|
||
312 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
of drift" with different loops, knots, speeds, movements, gestures, and
|
||
sonorities.1
|
||
These are not three successive moments in an evolution. They are three
|
||
aspects of a single thing, the Refrain (ritournelle). They are found in tales
|
||
(both horror stories and fairy tales), and in lieder as well. The refrain has
|
||
all three aspects, it makes them simultaneous or mixes them: sometimes,
|
||
sometimes, sometimes. Sometimes chaos is an immense black hole in
|
||
which one endeavors to fix a fragile point as a center. Sometimes one
|
||
organizes around that point a calm and stable "pace" (rather than a form):
|
||
the black hole has become a home. Sometimes one grafts onto that pace a
|
||
breakaway from the black hole. Paul Klee presented these three aspects,
|
||
and their interlinkage, in a most profound way. He calls the black hole a
|
||
"gray point" for pictorial reasons. The gray point starts out as nonlocal-
|
||
izable, nondimensional chaos, the force of chaos, a tangled bundle of
|
||
aberrant lines. Then the point "jumps over itself and radiates a dimen-
|
||
sional space with horizontal layers, vertical cross sections, unwritten cus-
|
||
tomary lines, a whole terrestrial interior force (this force also appears, at a
|
||
more relaxed pace, in the atmosphere and in water). The gray point (black
|
||
hole) has thus jumped from one state to another, and no longer represents
|
||
chaos but the abode or home. Finally, the point launches out of itself,
|
||
impelled by wandering centrifugal forces that fan out to the sphere of the
|
||
cosmos: one "tries convulsively to fly from the earth, but at the following
|
||
level one actually rises above i t . . . powered by centrifugal forces that tri-
|
||
umph over gravity."2
|
||
The role of the refrain has often been emphasized: it is territorial, a terri-
|
||
torial assemblage. Bird songs: the bird sings to mark its territory. The
|
||
Greek modes and Hindu rhythms are themselves territorial, provincial,
|
||
regional. The refrain may assume other functions, amorous, professional
|
||
or social, liturgical or cosmic: it always carries earth with it; it has a land
|
||
(sometimes a spiritual land) as its concomitant; it has an essential relation
|
||
to a Natal, a Native. A musical "nome" is a little tune, a melodic formula
|
||
that seeks recognition and remains the bedrock or ground of polyphony
|
||
(cantus firmus). The nomos as customary, unwritten law is inseparable
|
||
from a distribution of space, a distribution in space. By that token, it is
|
||
ethos, but the ethos is also the Abode.3 Sometimes one goes from chaos to
|
||
the threshold of a territorial assemblage: directional components, infra-
|
||
assemblage. Sometimes one organizes the assemblage: dimensional com-
|
||
ponents, intra-assemblage. Sometimes one leaves the territorial assem-
|
||
blage for other assemblages, or for somewhere else entirely: interassem-
|
||
blage, components of passage or even escape. And all three at once. Forces
|
||
of chaos, terrestrial forces, cosmic forces: all of these confront each other
|
||
and converge in the territorial refrain.
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 313
|
||
|
||
From chaos, Milieus and Rhythms are born. This is the concern of very
|
||
ancient cosmogonies. Chaos is not without its own directional compo-
|
||
nents, which are its own ecstasies. We have seen elsewhere how all kinds of
|
||
milieus, each defined by a component, slide in relation to one another, over
|
||
one another. Every milieu is vibratory, in other words, a block of space-
|
||
time constituted by the periodic repetition of the component. Thus the
|
||
living thing has an exterior milieu of materials, an interior milieu of com-
|
||
posing elements and composed substances, an intermediary milieu of
|
||
membranes and limits, and an annexed milieu of energy sources and
|
||
actions-perceptions. Every milieu is coded, a code being defined by peri-
|
||
odic repetition; but each code is in a perpetual state of transcoding or
|
||
transduction. Transcoding or transduction is the manner in which one
|
||
milieu serves as the basis for another, or conversely is established atop
|
||
another milieu, dissipates in it or is constituted in it. The notion of the
|
||
milieu is not unitary: not only does the living thing continually pass from
|
||
one milieu to another, but the milieus pass into one another, they are essen-
|
||
tially communicating. The milieus are open to chaos, which threatens
|
||
them with exhaustion or intrusion. Rhythm is the milieus' answer to chaos.
|
||
What chaos and rhythm have in common is the in-between—between two
|
||
milieus, rhythm-chaos or the chaosmos: "Between night and day, between
|
||
that which is constructed and that which grows naturally, between muta-
|
||
tions from the inorganic to the organic, from plant to animal, from animal
|
||
to humankind, yet without this series constituting a progression ..." In
|
||
this in-between, chaos becomes rhythm, not inexorably, but it has a chance
|
||
to. Chaos is not the opposite of rhythm, but the milieu of all milieus. There
|
||
is rhythm whenever there is a transcoded passage from one milieu to
|
||
another, a communication of milieus, coordination between heterogene-
|
||
ous space-times. Drying up, death, intrusion have rhythm. It is well known
|
||
that rhythm is not meter or cadence, even irregular meter or cadence: there
|
||
is nothing less rhythmic than a military march. The tom-tom is not 1 -2, the
|
||
waltz is not 1, 2, 3, music is not binary or ternary, but rather forty-seven
|
||
basic meters, as in Turkish music. Meter, whether regular or not, assumes a
|
||
coded form whose unit of measure may vary, but in a noncommunicating
|
||
milieu, whereas rhythm is the Unequal or the Incommensurable that is
|
||
always undergoing transcoding. Meter is dogmatic, but rhythm is critical;
|
||
it ties together critical moments, or ties itself together in passing from one
|
||
milieu to another. It does not operate in a homogeneous space-time, but by
|
||
heterogeneous blocks. It changes direction. Bachelard is right to say that
|
||
"the link between truly active moments (rhythm) is always effected on a dif-
|
||
ferent plane from the one upon which the action is carried out."4 Rhythm is
|
||
never on the same plane as that which has rhythm. Action occurs in a
|
||
milieu, whereas rhythm is located between two milieus, or between two
|
||
314 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
intermilieus, on the fence, between night and day, at dusk, twilight or
|
||
Zwielicht, Haecceity. To change milieus, taking them as you find them:
|
||
Such is rhythm. Landing, splashdown, takeoff.. . This easily avoids an
|
||
aporia that threatened to introduce meter into rhythm, despite all the dec-
|
||
larations of intent to the contrary: How can one proclaim the constituent
|
||
inequality of rhythm while at the same time admitting implied vibrations,
|
||
periodic repetitions of components? A milieu does in fact exist by virtue of
|
||
a periodic repetition, but one whose only effect is to produce a difference
|
||
by which the milieu passes into another milieu. It is the difference that is
|
||
rhythmic, not the repetition, which nevertheless produces it: productive
|
||
repetition has nothing to do with reproductive meter. This is the "critical
|
||
solution of the antinomy."
|
||
One case of transcoding is particularly important: when a code is not
|
||
content to take or receive components that are coded differently, and
|
||
instead takes or receives fragments of a different code as such. The first
|
||
case pertains to the leaf-water relation, the second to the spider-fly rela-
|
||
tion. It has often been noted that the spider web implies that there are
|
||
sequences of the fly's own code in the spider's code; it is as though the spi-
|
||
der had a fly in its head, a fly "motif," a fly "refrain." The implication may
|
||
be reciprocal, as with the wasp and the orchid, or the snapdragon and the
|
||
bumblebee. Jakob von Uexkull has elaborated an admirable theory of
|
||
transcodings. He sees the components as melodies in counterpoint, each of
|
||
which serves as a motif for another: Nature as music.5 Whenever there is
|
||
transcoding, we can be sure that there is not a simple addition, but the con-
|
||
stitution of a new plane, as of a surplus value. A melodic or rhythmic plane,
|
||
surplus value of passage or bridging. The two cases, however, are never
|
||
pure; they are in reality mixed (for example, the relation of the leaf, this
|
||
time not to water in general but to rain).
|
||
Still, we do not yet have a Territory, which is not a milieu, not even an
|
||
additional milieu, nor a rhythm or passage between milieus. The territory
|
||
is in fact an act that affects milieus and rhythms, that "territorializes"
|
||
them. The territory is the product of a territorialization of milieus and
|
||
rhythms. It amounts to the same thing to ask when milieus and rhythms
|
||
become territorialized, and what the difference is between a nonterritorial
|
||
animal and a territorial animal. A territory borrows from all the milieus; it
|
||
bites into them, seizes them bodily (although it remains vulnerable to
|
||
intrusions). It is built from aspects or portions of milieus. It itself has an
|
||
exterior milieu, an interior milieu, an intermediary milieu, and an
|
||
annexed milieu. It has the interior zone of a residence or shelter, the exte-
|
||
rior zone of its domain, more or less retractable limits or membranes,
|
||
intermediary or even neutralized zones, and energy reserves or annexes. It
|
||
is by essence marked by "indexes," which may be components taken from
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 315
|
||
|
||
any of the milieus: materials, organic products, skin or membrane states,
|
||
energy sources, action-perception condensates. There is a territory pre-
|
||
cisely when milieu components cease to be directional, becoming dimen-
|
||
sional instead, when they cease to be functional to become expressive.
|
||
There is a territory when the rhythm has expressiveness. What defines the
|
||
territory is the emergence of matters of expression (qualities). Take the
|
||
example of color in birds or fish: color is a membrane state associated with
|
||
interior hormonal states, but it remains functional and transitory as long as
|
||
it is tied to a type of action (sexuality, aggressiveness, flight). It becomes
|
||
expressive, on the other hand, when it acquires a temporal constancy and a
|
||
spatial range that make it a territorial, or rather territorializing, mark: a sig-
|
||
nature.6 The question is not whether color resumes its functions or fulfills
|
||
new ones in the territory. It is clear that it does, but this reorganization of
|
||
functions implies first of all that the component under consideration has
|
||
become expressive and that its meaning, from this standpoint, is to mark a
|
||
territory. The same species of birds may have colored and uncolored repre-
|
||
sentatives; the colored birds have a territory, whereas the all-white ones are
|
||
gregarious. We know what role urine and excrement play in marking, but
|
||
territorial excrement, for example, in the rabbit, has a particular odor
|
||
owing to specialized anal glands. Many monkeys, when serving as guards,
|
||
expose their brightly colored sexual organs: the penis becomes a rhythmic
|
||
and expressive color-carrier that marks the limits of the territory.7 A milieu
|
||
component becomes both a quality and a property, quale and proprium. It
|
||
has been remarked how quick this becoming is in many cases, the rapidity
|
||
with which a territory is constituted at the same time as expressive quali-
|
||
ties are selected or produced. The brown stagemaker (Scenopoeetes
|
||
dentirostris) lays down landmarks each morning by dropping leaves it picks
|
||
from its tree, and then turning them upside down so the paler underside
|
||
stands out against the dirt: inversion produces a matter of expression.8
|
||
The territory is not primary in relation to the qualitative mark; it is the
|
||
mark that makes the territory. Functions in a territory are not primary;
|
||
they presuppose a territory-producing expressiveness. In this sense, the
|
||
territory, and the functions performed within it, are products of
|
||
territorialization. Territorialization is an act of rhythm that has become
|
||
expressive, or of milieu components that have become qualitative. The
|
||
marking of a territory is dimensional, but it is not a meter, it is a rhythm. It
|
||
retains the most general characteristic of rhythm, which is to be inscribed
|
||
on a different plane than that of its actions. But now the distinction
|
||
between the two planes is between territorializing expressions and
|
||
territorialized functions. That is why we cannot accept a thesis like
|
||
Lorenz's, which tends to make aggressiveness the basis of the territory: the
|
||
territory would then be the product of the phylogenetic evolution of an
|
||
316 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
instinct of aggression, starting at the point where that instinct became
|
||
intraspecific, was turned against the animal's own kind. A territorial ani-
|
||
mal would direct its aggressiveness against members of its own species; the
|
||
species would gain the selective advantage of distributing its members
|
||
throughout a space where each would have its own place.9 This ambiguous
|
||
thesis, which has dangerous political overtones, seems to us to have little
|
||
foundation. It is obvious that the function of aggression changes pace when
|
||
it becomes intraspecific. but this reorganization of the function, rather
|
||
than explaining the territory, presupposes it. there are numerous reorgani-
|
||
zations within the territory, which also affect sexuality, hunting, etc.; there
|
||
are even new functions, such as building a place to live. These functions are
|
||
organized or created only because they are territorialized, and not the other
|
||
way around. The T factor, the territorializing factor, must be sought
|
||
elsewhere: precisely in the becoming-expressive of rhythm or melody, in
|
||
other words, in the emergence or proper qualities (color, odor, sound,
|
||
silhouette...).
|
||
Can this becoming, this emergence, be called Art? That would make the
|
||
territory a result of art. The artist: the first person to set out a boundary
|
||
stone, or to make a mark. Property, collective or individual, is derived from
|
||
that even when it is in the service of war and oppression. Property is funda-
|
||
mentally artistic because art is fundamentally poster, placard. As Lorenz
|
||
says, coral fish are posters. The expressive is primary in relation to the pos-
|
||
sessive; expressive qualities, or matters of expression, are necessarily
|
||
appropriative and constitute a having more profound than being.10 Not in
|
||
the sense that these qualities belong to a subject, but in the sense that they
|
||
delineate a territory that will belong to the subject that carries or produces
|
||
them. These qualities are signatures, but the signature, the proper name, is
|
||
not the constituted mark of a subject, but the constituting mark of a
|
||
domain, an abode. The signature is not the indication of a person; it is the
|
||
chancy formation of a domain. Abodes have proper names, and are
|
||
inspired. "The inspired and their abodes . . ."; it is with the abode that
|
||
inspiration arises. No sooner do I like a color that I make it my standard or
|
||
placard. One puts one's signature on something just as one plants one's flag
|
||
on a piece of land. A high school supervisor stamped all the leaves strewn
|
||
about the school yard and then put them back in their places. He had
|
||
signed. Territorial marks are readymades. And what is called art brut in not
|
||
at all pathological or primitive; it is merely this constitution, this freeing, of
|
||
matters of expression in the movement of territoriality: the base or ground
|
||
of art. Take anything and make it a matter of expression. The stagemaker
|
||
practices art brut. Artists are stagemakers, even when they tear up their
|
||
own posters. Of course, from this standpoint art is not the privilege of
|
||
human beings. Messiaen is right in saying that many birds are not only vir-
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 317
|
||
|
||
tuosos but artists, above all in their territorial songs (if a robber "improp-
|
||
erly wishes to occupy a spot which doesn't belong to it, the true owner sings
|
||
and sings so well that the predator goes away.... If the robber sings better
|
||
than the true proprietor, the proprietor yields his place").11 The refrain is
|
||
rhythm and melody that have been territorialized because they have
|
||
become expressive—and have become expressive because they are
|
||
territorializing. We are not going in circles. What we wish to say is that
|
||
there is a self-movement of expressive qualities. Expressiveness is not
|
||
reducible to the immediate effects of an impulse triggering an action in a
|
||
milieu: effects of that kind are subjective impressions or emotions rather
|
||
than expressions (as, for example, the temporary color a freshwater fish
|
||
takes on under a given impulse). On the other hand, expressive qualities,
|
||
the colors of the coral fish, for example, are auto-objective, in other words,
|
||
find an objectivity in the territory they draw.
|
||
What is this objective movement? What does a matter do as a matter of
|
||
expression? It is first of all a poster or placard, but that is not all it is. It
|
||
merely takes that route. The signature becomes style. In effect, expressive
|
||
qualities or matters of expression enter shifting relations with one another
|
||
that "express" the relation of the territory they draw to the interior milieu of
|
||
impulses and exterior milieu of circumstances. To express is not to depend
|
||
upon; there is an autonomy of expression. On the one hand, expressive
|
||
qualities entertain internal relations with one another that constitute terri-
|
||
torial motifs; sometimes these motifs loom above the internal impulses,
|
||
sometimes they are superposed upon them, sometimes they ground one
|
||
impulse in another, sometimes they pass and cause a passage from one
|
||
impulse to another, sometimes they insert themselves between them—but
|
||
they are not themselves "pulsed." Sometimes these nonpulsed motifs arise
|
||
in a fixed form, or seem to arise that way, but at other times the same ones,
|
||
or others, take on variable speed and articulation; it is as much their varia-
|
||
bility as their fixity that makes them independent of the drives they com-
|
||
bine or neutralize. "We know that our dogs go through motions of smelling,
|
||
seeking, chasing, biting, and shaking to death with equal enthusiasm
|
||
whether they are hungry or not."12 Another example is the dance of the
|
||
stickleback. Its zigzag is a motif in which the zig is tied to an aggressive
|
||
drive toward the partner, and the zag to a sexual drive toward the nest; yet
|
||
the zig and the zag are accented, or even oriented, differently. On the other
|
||
hand, expressive qualities also entertain other internal relations that pro-
|
||
duce territorial counterpoints: this refers to the manner in which they con-
|
||
stitute points in the territory that place the circumstances of the external
|
||
milieu in counterpoint. For example, an enemy approaches or suddenly
|
||
appears, or rain starts to fall, the sun rises, the sun sets... Here again, the
|
||
points or counterpoints are autonomous in their fixity or variability in
|
||
318 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
relation to the circumstances of the exterior milieu whose relation to the
|
||
territory they express. For this relation can be given without the circum-
|
||
stances being given, just as the relation to the impulses can be given with-
|
||
out the impulse being given. And even when the impulses and circum-
|
||
stances are given, the relation is prior to what it places in relation.
|
||
Relations between matters of expression express relations of the territory
|
||
to internal impulses and external circumstances: they have an autonomy
|
||
within this very expression. In truth, territorial motifs and counterpoints
|
||
explore potentialities of the interior or exterior milieu. Ethologists have
|
||
grouped these phenomena under the concept of "ritualization" and have
|
||
demonstrated the link between animal rituals and territory. But this word
|
||
is not necessarily appropriate for these nonpulsed motifs and nonlocalized
|
||
counterpoints, since it accounts for neither their variability nor their fixity.
|
||
It is not one or the other, fixity or variability; certain motifs or points are
|
||
fixed only if others are variable, or else they are fixed on one occasion and
|
||
variable on another.
|
||
We should say, rather, that territorial motifs form rhythmic faces or char-
|
||
acters, and that territorial counterpoints form melodic landscapes. There is
|
||
a rhythmic character when we find that we no longer have the simple situa-
|
||
tion of a rhythm associated with a character, subject, or impulse. The
|
||
rhythm itself is now the character in its entirety; as such, it may remain con-
|
||
stant, or it may be augmented or diminished by the addition or subtraction
|
||
of sounds or always increasing or decreasing durations, and by an amplifi-
|
||
cation or elimination bringing death or resuscitation, appearance or disap-
|
||
pearance. Similarly, the melodic landscape is no longer a melody associ-
|
||
ated with a landscape; the melody itself is a sonorous landscape in
|
||
counterpoint to a virtual landscape. That is how we get beyond the placard
|
||
stage: although each expressive quality, each matter of expression consid-
|
||
ered in itself, is a placard or poster, the analysis of them is nevertheless
|
||
abstract. Expressive qualities entertain variable or constant relations with
|
||
one another (that is what matters of expression do); they no longer consti-
|
||
tute placards that mark a territory, but motifs and counterpoints that
|
||
express the relation of the territory to interior impulses or exterior circum-
|
||
stances, whether or not they are given. No longer signatures, but a style.
|
||
What objectively distinguishes a musician bird from a nonmusician bird is
|
||
precisely this aptitude for motifs and counterpoints that, if they are varia-
|
||
ble, or even when they are constant, make matters of expression something
|
||
other than a poster—a style—since they articulate rhythm and harmonize
|
||
melody. We can then say that the musician bird goes from sadness to joy or
|
||
that it greets the rising sun or endangers itself in order to sing or sings better
|
||
than another, etc. None of these formulations carries the slightest risk of
|
||
anthropomorphism, or implies the slightest interpretation. It is instead a
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 319
|
||
|
||
kind of geomorphism. The relation to joy and sadness, the sun, danger, per-
|
||
fection, is given in the motif and counterpoint, even if the term of each of
|
||
these relations is not given. In the motif and the counterpoint, the sun, joy
|
||
or sadness, danger, become sonorous, rhythmic, or melodic.13
|
||
Human music also goes this route. For Swann, the art lover, Vinteuil's
|
||
little phrase often acts as a placard associated with the Bois de Boulogne
|
||
and the face and character of Odette: as if it reassured Swann that the Bois
|
||
de Boulogne was indeed his territory, and Odette his possession. There is
|
||
already something quite artistic in this way of hearing music. Debussy crit-
|
||
icized Wagner, comparing his leitmotifs to signposts signaling the hidden
|
||
circumstances of a situation, the secret impulses of a character. The criti-
|
||
cism is accurate, on one level or at certain moments. But as the work devel-
|
||
ops, the motifs increasingly enter into conjunction, conquer their own
|
||
plane, become autonomous from the dramatic action, impulses, and situa-
|
||
tions, and independent of characters and landscapes; they themselves
|
||
become melodic landscapes and rhythmic characters continually enrich-
|
||
ing their internal relations. They may then remain relatively constant, or
|
||
on the contrary grow or diminish, expand or contract, vary in the speed at
|
||
which they unfold: in both cases, they are no longer pulsed and localized,
|
||
and even the constants are in the service of variation; the more provisory
|
||
they are, the more they display the continuous variation they resist, the
|
||
more rigid they become.14 Proust was among the first to underscore this life
|
||
of the Wagnerian motif. Instead of the motif being tied to a character who
|
||
appears, the appearance of the motif itself constitutes a rhythmic character
|
||
in "the plenitude of a music that is indeed filled with so many strains, each
|
||
of which is a being."15 It is not by chance that the apprenticeship of the
|
||
Recherche pursues an analogous discovery in relation to Vinteuil's little
|
||
phrases: they do not refer to a landscape; they carry and develop within
|
||
themselves landscapes that do not exist on the outside (the white sonata
|
||
and red septet. ..). The discovery of the properly melodic landscape and
|
||
the properly rhythmic character marks the moment of art when it ceases to
|
||
be a silent painting on a signboard. This may not be art's last word, but art
|
||
went that route, as did the bird: motifs and counterpoints that form an
|
||
autodevelopment, in other words, a style. The interiorization of the
|
||
melodic or sonorous landscape finds its exemplary form in Liszt and that
|
||
of the rhythmic character in Wagner. More generally, the lied is the musical
|
||
art of the landscape, the most pictorial, impressionist form of music. But
|
||
the two poles are so closely bound that in the lied as well Nature appears as
|
||
a rhythmic character with infinite transformations.
|
||
The territory is first of all the critical distance between two beings of the
|
||
same species: Mark your distance. What is mine is first of all my distance; I
|
||
possess only distances. Don't anybody touch me, I growl if anyone enters
|
||
320 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
my territory, I put up placards. Critical distance is a relation based on mat-
|
||
ters of expression. It is a question of keeping at a distance the forces of
|
||
chaos knocking at the door. Mannerism: the ethos is both abode and man-
|
||
ner, homeland and style. This is evident in territorial dances termed
|
||
baroque or mannerist, in which each pose, each movement, establishes a
|
||
distance of this kind (sarabands, allemandes, bourrees, gavottes.. .).16
|
||
There is a whole art of poses, postures, silhouettes, steps, and voices. Two
|
||
schizophrenics converse or stroll according to laws of boundary and terri-
|
||
tory that may escape us. How very important it is, when chaos threatens, to
|
||
draw an inflatable, portable territory. If need be, I'll put my territory on my
|
||
own body, I'll territorialize my body: the house of the tortoise, the hermit-
|
||
age of the crab, but also tattoos that make the body a territory. Critical dis-
|
||
tance is not a meter, it is a rhythm. But the rhythm, precisely, is caught up in
|
||
a becoming that sweeps up the distances between characters, making them
|
||
rhythmic characters that are themselves more or less distant, more or less
|
||
combinable (intervals). Two animals of the same sex and species confront
|
||
each other: the rhythm of the first one "expands" when it approaches its
|
||
territory or the center of its territory; the rhythm of the second contracts
|
||
when it moves away from its territory. Between the two, at the boundaries,
|
||
an oscillational constant is established: an active rhythm, a passively
|
||
endured rhythm, and a witness rhythm?17 Or else the animal opens its terri-
|
||
tory a crack for a partner of the opposite sex: a complex rhythmic character
|
||
forms through duets, antiphonal or alternating singing, as in the case of
|
||
African shrikes. Furthermore, we must simultaneously take into account
|
||
two aspects of the territory: it not only ensures and regulates the coexis-
|
||
tence of members of the same species by keeping them apart, but makes
|
||
possible the coexistence of a maximum number of different species in the
|
||
same milieu by specializing them. Members of the same species enter into
|
||
rhythmic characters at the same time as different species enter into
|
||
melodic landscapes; for the landscapes are peopled by characters and the
|
||
characters belong to landscapes. An example is Messiaen's Chrono-
|
||
chromie, with its eighteen bird songs forming autonomous rhythmic char-
|
||
acters and simultaneously realizing an extraordinary landscape in com-
|
||
plex counterpoint, with invented or implicit chords.
|
||
Not only does art not wait for human beings to begin, but we may ask if
|
||
art ever appears among human beings, except under artificial and belated
|
||
conditions. It has often been noted that human art was for a long time
|
||
bound up with work and rites of a different nature. Saying this, however,
|
||
perhaps has no more weight than saying that art begins with human beings.
|
||
For it is true that a territory has two notable effects: a reorganization of
|
||
functions and a regrouping offerees. On the one hand, when functional
|
||
activities are territorialized they necessarily change pace (the creation of
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 321
|
||
|
||
new functions such as building a dwelling, or the transformation of old
|
||
functions, as when aggressiveness changes nature and becomes intra-
|
||
specific). This is like a nascent theme of specialization or professionalism:
|
||
if the territorial refrain so often passes into professional refrains, it is
|
||
because professions assume that various activities are performed in the
|
||
same milieu, and that the same activity has no other agents in the same ter-
|
||
ritory. Professional refrains intersect in the milieu, like merchants' cries,
|
||
but each marks a territory within which the same activity cannot be per-
|
||
formed, nor the same cry ring out. In animals as in human beings, there are
|
||
rules of critical distance for competition: my stretch of sidewalk. In short, a
|
||
territorialization of functions is the condition for their emergence as
|
||
"occupations" or "trades." Thus intraspecific or specialized aggressive-
|
||
ness is necessarily a territorialized aggressiveness; it does not explain the
|
||
territory since it itself derives from it. It is immediately apparent that all
|
||
activities within the territory adopt a new practical pace. But that is no rea-
|
||
son to conclude that art in itself does not exist here, for it is present in the
|
||
territorializing factor that is the necessary condition for the emergence of
|
||
the work-function.
|
||
The situation is the same if we consider the other effect of territori-
|
||
alization. That other effect, which relates not to occupations but to rites
|
||
and religions, consists in this: the territory groups all the forces of the dif-
|
||
ferent milieus together in a single sheaf constituted by the forces of the
|
||
earth. The attribution of all the diffuse forces to the earth as receptacle or
|
||
base takes place only at the deepest level of each territory. "The surround-
|
||
ing milieu was experienced as a unity; it is very hard to distinguish in these
|
||
primal intuitions what belongs properly to the earth from what is merely
|
||
manifested through the earth: mountains, forests, water, vegetation."18
|
||
The forces of air and water, bird and fish, thus become forces of the earth.
|
||
Moreover, although in extension the territory separates the interior forces
|
||
of the earth from the exterior forces of chaos, the same does not occur in
|
||
"intension," in the dimension of depth, where the two types of force clasp
|
||
and are wed in a battle whose only criterion and stakes is the earth. There is
|
||
always a place, a tree or grove, in the territory where all the forces come
|
||
together in a hand-to-hand combat of energies. The earth is this close
|
||
embrace.19 This intense center is simultaneously inside the territory, and
|
||
outside several territories that converge on it at the end of an immense pil-
|
||
grimage (hence the ambiguities of the "natal"). Inside or out, the territory
|
||
is linked to this intense center, which is like the unknown homeland, terres-
|
||
trial source of all forces friendly and hostile, where everything is decided.20
|
||
So we must once again acknowledge that religion, which is common to
|
||
human beings and animals, occupies territory only because it depends on
|
||
the raw aesthetic and territorializing factor as its necessary condition. It is
|
||
322 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
this factor that at the same time organizes the functions of the milieu into
|
||
occupations and binds the forces of chaos in rites and religions, which are
|
||
forces of the earth. Territorializing marks simultaneously develop into
|
||
motifs and counterpoints, and reorganize functions and regroup forces. But
|
||
by virtue of this, the territory already unleashes something that will surpass
|
||
it.
|
||
We always come back to this "moment": the becoming-expressive of
|
||
rhythm, the emergence of expressive proper qualities, the formation of
|
||
matters of expression that develop into motifs and counterpoints. We
|
||
therefore need a notion, even an apparently negative one, that can grasp
|
||
this fictional or raw moment. The essential thing is the disjunction notice-
|
||
able between the code and the territory. The territory arises in a free margin
|
||
of the code, one that is not indeterminate but rather is determined differ-
|
||
ently. Each milieu has its own code, and there is perpetual transcoding
|
||
between milieus; the territory, on the other hand, seems to form at the level
|
||
of a certain decoding. Biologists have stressed the importance of these
|
||
determined margins, which are not to be confused with mutations, in other
|
||
words, changes internal to the code: here, it is a question of duplicated
|
||
genes or extra chromosomes that are not inside the genetic code, are free of
|
||
function, and offer a free matter for variation.21 But it is very unlikely that
|
||
this kind of matter could create new species independently of mutations,
|
||
unless it were accompanied by events of another order capable of multiply-
|
||
ing the interactions of the organism with its milieus. Territorialization is
|
||
precisely such a factor that lodges on the margins of the code of a single spe-
|
||
cies and gives the separate representatives of that species the possibility of
|
||
differentiating. It is because there is a disjunction between the territory
|
||
and the code that the territory can indirectly induce new species. Wherever
|
||
territoriality appears, it establishes an intraspecific critical distance
|
||
between members of the same species; it is by virtue of its own disjunction
|
||
in relation to specific differences that it becomes an oblique, indirect means
|
||
of differentiation. From all of these standpoints, decoding appears as the
|
||
"negative" of the territory, and the most obvious distinction between terri-
|
||
torial animals and nonterritorial animals is that the former are much less
|
||
coded than the latter. We have said enough bad things about the territory
|
||
that we can now evaluate all the creations that tend toward it, occur within
|
||
it, and result or will result from it.
|
||
We have gone from forces of chaos to forces of the earth. From milieus to
|
||
territory. From functional rhythms to the becoming-expressive of rhythm.
|
||
From phenomena of transcoding to phenomena of decoding. From milieu
|
||
functions to territorialized functions. It is less a question of evolution than
|
||
of passage, bridges and tunnels. We saw that milieus continually pass into
|
||
one another. Now we see that the milieus pass into the territory. The
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 323
|
||
|
||
expressive qualities we term aesthetic are certainly not "pure" or symbolic
|
||
qualities but proper qualities, in other words, appropriative qualities, pas-
|
||
sages from milieu components to territory components. The territory itself
|
||
is a place of passage. The territory is the first assemblage, the first thing to
|
||
constitute an assemblage; the assemblage is fundamentally territorial. But
|
||
how could it not already be in the process of passing into something else,
|
||
into other assemblages? That is why we could not talk about the constitu-
|
||
tion of the territory without also talking about its internal organization.
|
||
We could not describe the infra-assemblage (posters or placards) without
|
||
also discussing the intra-assemblage (motifs and counterpoints). Nor can
|
||
we say anything about the intra-assemblage without already being on the
|
||
path to other assemblages, or elsewhere. The passage of the Refrain. The
|
||
refrain moves in the direction of the territorial assemblage and lodges itself
|
||
there or leaves. In a general sense, we call a refrain any aggregate of matters
|
||
of expression that draws a territory and develops into territorial motifs and
|
||
landscapes (there are optical, gestural, motor, etc., refrains). In the narrow
|
||
sense, we speak of a refrain when an assemblage is sonorous or "domi-
|
||
nated" by sound—but why do we assign this apparent privilege to sound?
|
||
|
||
We are now in the intra-assemblage. Its organization is very rich and
|
||
complex. It includes not only the territorial assemblage but also assem-
|
||
bled, territorialized functions. Take the Troglodytidae, the wren family:
|
||
the male takes possession of his territory and produces a "music box
|
||
refrain" as a warning to possible intruders; he builds his own nests in his
|
||
territory, sometimes as many as a dozen; when a female arrives, he sits in
|
||
front of a nest, invites her to visit, hangs his wings, and lowers the inten-
|
||
sity of his song, reduced to a mere trill.22 It seems that the nesting function
|
||
is highly territorialized, since the nests are prepared by the male alone
|
||
before the arrival of the female, who only visits and completes them; the
|
||
"courtship" function is also territorialized, but to a lesser degree, since
|
||
the territorial refrain becomes seductive by changing in intensity. All
|
||
kinds of heterogeneous elements show up in the intra-assemblage: not
|
||
only the assemblage marks that group materials, colors, odors, sounds,
|
||
postures, etc., but also the various elements of given assembled behaviors
|
||
that enter into a motif. For example, a display behavior is composed of a
|
||
dance, clicking of the beak, an exhibition of colors, a posture with neck
|
||
outstretched, cries, smoothing of the feathers, bows, a refrain. .. The first
|
||
question to be asked is what holds these territorializing marks, territorial
|
||
motifs, and territorialized functions together in the same intra-assem-
|
||
blage. This is a question of consistency: the "holding together" of hetero-
|
||
geneous elements. At first, they constitute no more than a fuzzy set, a
|
||
discrete set that later takes on consistency.
|
||
324 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
But another question seems to interrupt or cut across the first one. For
|
||
in many cases, a territorialized, assembled function acquires enough
|
||
independence to constitute a new assemblage, one that is more or less
|
||
deterritorialized, en route to deterritorialization. There is no need to
|
||
effectively leave the territory to go this route; but what just a minute ago
|
||
was a constituted function in the territorial assemblage has become the
|
||
constituting element of another assemblage, the element of passage to
|
||
another assemblage. As in courtly love, a color ceases to be territorial and
|
||
enters a "courtship" assemblage. The territorial assemblage opens onto
|
||
the courtship assemblage, which is a social assemblage that has gained
|
||
autonomy. That is what happens when it is specifically the sexual partner
|
||
or the members of a group that are recognized, rather than the territory:
|
||
The partner is then said to be a Tier mil der Heimvalenz, "an animal with
|
||
home value." There is therefore a distinction to be made between milieu
|
||
groups and couples (without individual recognition), territorial groups
|
||
and couples (in which there is only recognition inside the territory), and
|
||
finally social groups and love couples (when there is recognition indepen-
|
||
dent of place).23 Courtship, or the group, is no longer a part of the territor-
|
||
ial assemblage; a courtship or group assemblage takes on autonomy—
|
||
even though it may stay inside the territory. Conversely, in the new
|
||
assemblage there is a reterritorialization on the member of the couple or
|
||
members of the group that have-the-value-of (valence). This opening of
|
||
the assemblage onto other assemblages can be analyzed in detail, and var-
|
||
ies widely. For example, when the male does not make the nest and con-
|
||
fines himself to transporting materials or mimicking the construction of
|
||
a nest (as in Australian grass finches), he either courts the female holding
|
||
a piece of stubble in his beak (genus Bathildd), uses the grass stem only in
|
||
the initial stages of courtship or even beforehand (genera Aidemosyne and
|
||
Lonchura), or pecks at the grass without offering it (genus Emblema).24
|
||
It could always be said that these "grass stem" behaviors are merely archa-
|
||
isms, or vestiges of nesting behavior. But the notion of behavior itself
|
||
proves inadequate to this assemblage. For when the nest is no longer made
|
||
by the male, nesting ceases to be a component of the territorial
|
||
assemblage—it takes wing, so to speak, from the territory; furthermore,
|
||
courtship, which now precedes nesting, itself becomes a relatively autono-
|
||
mous assemblage. In addition, the matter of expression, "grass stem," acts
|
||
as a component of passage between the territorial assemblage and the
|
||
courtship assemblage. The fact that the grass stem has an increasingly
|
||
rudimentary function in certain species, the fact that it tends to cancel
|
||
out in the series under consideration, is not enough to make it a vestige,
|
||
much less a symbol. A matter of expression is never a vestige or a symbol.
|
||
The grass stem is a deterritorialized component, or one en route to
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 325
|
||
|
||
deterritorialization. It is neither an archaism nor a transitional or part-
|
||
object. It is an operator, a vector. It is an assemblage converter. The stem
|
||
cancels out precisely because it is a component of passage from one assem-
|
||
blage to another. This viewpoint is confirmed by the fact that if the stem
|
||
cancels out, another relay component replaces it or assumes greater impor-
|
||
tance, namely, the refrain, which is not only territorial but becomes amo-
|
||
rous and social, and changes accordingly.25 The question of why, in the
|
||
constitution of new assemblages, the sound component "refrain" has a
|
||
stronger valence than the gestural component "grass stem" can be consid-
|
||
ered only later on. The important thing for now is to note this formation of
|
||
new assemblages within the territorial assemblage, and this movement
|
||
from the intra-assemblage to interassemblages by means of components of
|
||
passage and relay: An innovative opening of the territory onto the female,
|
||
or the group. Selective pressure proceeds by way of interassemblages. It is
|
||
as though forces of deterritorialization affected the territory itself, causing
|
||
us to pass from the territorial assemblage to other types of assemblages
|
||
(courtship or sexuality assemblages, group or social assemblages). The
|
||
grass stem and the refrain are two agents of these forces, two agents of
|
||
deterritorialization.
|
||
The territorial assemblage continually passes into other assemblages.
|
||
Likewise, the infra-assemblage is inseparable from the intra-assemblage,
|
||
as is the intra-assemblage from interassemblages; yet these passages are
|
||
not necessary but rather take place "on a case-by-case basis." The reason
|
||
is simple: the intra-assemblage, the territorial assemblage, territorializes func-
|
||
tions and forces (sexuality, aggressiveness, gregariousness, etc.), and
|
||
in the process of territorializing them, transforms them. But these
|
||
territorialized functions and forces can suddenly take on an autonomy
|
||
that makes them swing over into other assemblages, compose other
|
||
deterritorialized assemblages. In the intra-assemblage, sexuality may
|
||
appear as a territorialized function, but it can just as easily draw a line of
|
||
deterritorialization that describes another assemblage; there are there-
|
||
fore quite variable relations between sexuality and the territory, as if sex-
|
||
uality were keeping "its distance." Profession, trade, and specialty imply
|
||
territorialized activities, but they can also take wing from the territory,
|
||
building a new assemblage around themselves, and between professions.
|
||
A territorial or territorialized component may set about budding, pro-
|
||
ducing: this is the case for the refrain, so much so that we should perhaps
|
||
call all cases of this kind refrains. This ambiguity between the territory
|
||
and deterritorialization is the ambiguity of the Natal. It is understood
|
||
much more clearly if it is borne in mind that the territory has an intense
|
||
center at its profoundest depths; but as we have seen, this intense center
|
||
can be located outside the territory, at the point of convergence of very
|
||
326 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
different and very distant territories. The Natal is outside. We may cite a
|
||
certain number of troubling and well-known, more or less mysterious,
|
||
cases illustrating prodigious takeoffs from the territory, displaying a vast
|
||
movement of deterritorialization directly plugged into the territories and
|
||
permeating them through and through: (1) pilgrimages to the source, as
|
||
among salmon; (2) supernumerary assemblies, such as those of locusts or
|
||
chaffinches, etc. (tens of millions of chaffinches near Thoune in 1950-
|
||
1951); (3) magnetic or solar-guided migrations; (4) long marches, such as
|
||
those of the lobsters.26
|
||
Whatever the causes of each of these movements, it is clear that the
|
||
nature of the movement is different. It is no longer adequate to say that
|
||
there is interassemblage, passage from a territorial assemblage to another
|
||
type of assemblage; rather, we should say that one leaves all assemblages
|
||
behind, that one exceeds the capacities of any possible assemblage, enter-
|
||
ing another plane. In effect, there is no longer a milieu movement or
|
||
rhythm, nor a territorialized or territorializing movement or rhythm; there
|
||
is something of the Cosmos in these more ample movements. The localiza-
|
||
tion mechanisms are still extremely precise, but the localization has
|
||
become cosmic. These are no longer territorialized forces bundled together
|
||
as forces of the earth; they are the liberated or regained forces of a
|
||
deterritorialized Cosmos. In migration, the sun is no longer the terrestrial
|
||
sun reigning over a territory, even an aerial one; it is the celestial sun of the
|
||
Cosmos, as in the two Jerusalems, the Apocalypse. Leaving aside these two
|
||
grandiose cases where deterritorialization becomes absolute while losing
|
||
nothing of its precision (because it weds cosmic variables), we must remark
|
||
that the territory is constantly traversed by movements of deterrito-
|
||
rialization that are relative and may even occur in place, by which one
|
||
passes from the intra-assemblage to interassemblages, without, however,
|
||
leaving the territory or issuing from the assemblages in order to wed the
|
||
Cosmos. A territory is always en route to an at least potential deterrito-
|
||
rialization, even though the new assemblage may operate a reterritoriali-
|
||
zation (something that "has-the-value-of' home). We saw that the territory
|
||
constituted itself on a margin of decoding affecting the milieu; we now see
|
||
that there is a margin of deterritorialization affecting the territory itself.
|
||
There is a series of unclaspings. The territory is inseparable from certain
|
||
coefficients of deterritorialization (which can be evaluated in each case)
|
||
that place the relations of each territorialized function to the territory in
|
||
variation, as well as the relations of the territory to each deterritorialized
|
||
assemblage. It is the same "thing" that appears first as a territorialized
|
||
function taken up in the intra-assemblage, and again as a deterritorialized
|
||
or autonomous assemblage, as an interassemblage.
|
||
Refrains could accordingly be classified as follows: (1) territorial
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 327
|
||
|
||
refrains that seek, mark, assemble a territory; (2) territorialized function
|
||
refrains that assume a special function in the assemblage (the Lullaby that
|
||
territorializes the child's slumber, the Lover's Refrain that territorializes
|
||
the sexuality of the loved one, the Professional Refrain that territorializes
|
||
trades and occupations, the Merchant Refrain that territorializes distribu-
|
||
tion and products); (3) the same, when they mark new assemblages, pass
|
||
into new assemblages by means of deterritorialization-reterritorialization
|
||
(nursery rhymes are a very complicated example: they are territorial
|
||
refrains that are sung differently from neighborhood to neighborhood,
|
||
sometimes from one street to the next; they distribute game roles and func-
|
||
tions within the territorial assemblage; but they also cause the territory to
|
||
pass into the game assemblage, which tends to become autonomous);27 (4)
|
||
refrains that collect or gather forces, either at the heart of the territory, or in
|
||
order to go outside it (these are refrains of confrontation or departure that
|
||
sometimes bring on a movement of absolute deterritorialization:
|
||
"Goodbye, I'm leaving and I won't look back." At infinity, these refrains
|
||
must rejoin the songs of the Molecules, the newborn wailing of the funda-
|
||
mental Elements, as Millikan put it. They cease to be terrestrial, becoming
|
||
cosmic: when the religious Nome blooms and dissolves in a molecular pan-
|
||
theist Cosmos, when the singing of the birds is replaced by combinations of
|
||
water, wind, clouds, and fog. "Outside, the wind and the rain ..." The Cos-
|
||
mos as an immense deterritorialized refrain).
|
||
The problem of consistency concerns the manner in which the compo-
|
||
nents of a territorial assemblage hold together. But it also concerns the
|
||
manner in which different assemblages hold together, with components of
|
||
passage and relay. It may even be the case that consistency finds the totality
|
||
of its conditions only on a properly cosmic plane, where all the disparate
|
||
and heterogeneous elements are convoked. However, from the moment
|
||
heterogeneities hold together in an assemblage or interassemblages a prob-
|
||
lem of consistency is posed, in terms of coexistence or succession, and both
|
||
simultaneously. Even in a territorial assemblage, it may be the most deter-
|
||
ritorialized component, the deterritorializing vector, in other words, the
|
||
refrain, that assures the consistency of the territory. If we ask the general
|
||
question, "What holds things together?", the clearest, easiest answer seems
|
||
to be provided by a formalizing, linear, hierarchized, centralized
|
||
arborescent model. Take Tinbergen's schema, which presents a coded link-
|
||
age of spatiotemporal forms in the central nervous system: a higher func-
|
||
tional center goes automatically into operation and releases an appetitive
|
||
behavior in search of specific stimuli (the migrational center); through the
|
||
intermediary of the stimulus, a second center that had been inhibited up to
|
||
this point is freed and releases a new appetitive behavior (the territorial
|
||
center); then other subordinate centers are activated, centers of fighting,
|
||
328 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
nesting, courtship . . . until stimuli are found that release the correspond-
|
||
ing executive acts.28 This kind of representation, however, is constructed of
|
||
oversimplified binarities: inhibition-release, innate-acquired, etc. Etholo-
|
||
gists have a great advantage over ethnologists: they did not fall into the
|
||
structural danger of dividing an undivided "terrain" into forms of kinship,
|
||
politics, economics, myth, etc. The ethologists have retained the integrality
|
||
of a certain undivided "terrain." But by orienting it along the axes of
|
||
inhibition-release, innate-acquired, they risk reintroducing souls and cen-
|
||
ters at each locus and stage of linkage. That is why even the authors who
|
||
stress the role of the peripheral and the acquired at the level of releasing
|
||
stimuli do not truly overturn the linear aborescent schema, even if they
|
||
reverse the direction of the arrows.
|
||
It seems more important to us to underline a certain number of factors
|
||
liable to suggest an entirely different schema, one favoring rhizomatic,
|
||
rather than arborified, functioning, and no longer operating by these dual-
|
||
isms. First of all, what is called a functional center brings into play not only
|
||
a localization but also a distribution of an entire population of neurons
|
||
selected from throughout the central nervous system, as in a "cable net-
|
||
work." This being the case, in considering the system as a whole we should
|
||
speak less of automatism of a higher center than of coordination between
|
||
centers, and of the cellular groupings or molecular populations that per-
|
||
form these couplings: there is no form or correct structure imposed from
|
||
without or above but rather an articulation from within, as if oscillating
|
||
molecules, oscillators, passed from one heterogeneous center to another, if
|
||
only for the purpose of assuring the dominance of one among them.29 This
|
||
obviously excludes any linear relation from one center to another, in favor
|
||
of packets of relations steered by molecules: the interaction or coordina-
|
||
tion may be positive or negative (release or inhibition), but it is never
|
||
direct, as in a linear relation or chemical reaction; it always occurs between
|
||
molecules with at least two heads, and each center taken separately.30
|
||
This represents a whole behavioral-biological "machinics," a whole
|
||
molecular engineering that should help increase our understanding of the
|
||
nature of problems of consistency. The philosopher Eugene Dupreel pro-
|
||
posed a theory of consolidation; he demonstrated that life went not from a
|
||
center to an exteriority but from an exterior to an interior, or rather from a
|
||
discrete or fuzzy aggregate to its consolidation. This implies three things.
|
||
First, that there is no beginning from which a linear sequence would derive,
|
||
but rather densifications, intensifications, reinforcements, injections,
|
||
showerings, like so many intercalary events ("there is growth only by inter-
|
||
calation"). Second, and this is not a contradiction, there must be an
|
||
arrangement of intervals, a distribution of inequalities, such that it is
|
||
sometimes necessary to make a hole in order to consolidate. Third, there is
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 329
|
||
|
||
a superposition of disparate rhythms, an articulation from within of an
|
||
interrhythmicity, with no imposition of meter or cadence.31 Consolidation
|
||
is not content to come after; it is creative. The fact is that the beginning
|
||
always begins in-between, intermezzo. Consistency is the same as consoli-
|
||
dation, it is the act that produces consolidated aggregates, of succession as
|
||
well as of coexistence, by means of the three factors just mentioned: inter-
|
||
calated elements, intervals, and articulations of superposition. Architec-
|
||
ture, as the art of the abode and the territory, attests to this: there are
|
||
consolidations that are made afterward, and there are consolidations of the
|
||
keystone type that are constituent parts of the ensemble. More recently,
|
||
matters like reinforced concrete have made it possible for the architectural
|
||
ensemble to free itself from arborescent models employing tree-pillars,
|
||
branch-beams, foliage-vaults. Not only is concrete a heterogeneous matter
|
||
whose degree of consistency varies according to the elements in the mix,
|
||
but iron is intercalated following a rhythm; moreover, its self-supporting
|
||
surfaces form a complex rhythmic personage whose "stems" have different
|
||
sections and variable intervals depending on the intensity and direction of
|
||
the force to be tapped (armature instead of structure). In this sense, the lit-
|
||
erary or musical work has an architecture: "Saturate every atom," as Vir-
|
||
ginia Woolf said;32 or in the words of Henry James, it is necessary to "begin
|
||
far away, as far away as possible," and to proceed by "blocks of wrought
|
||
matter." It is no longer a question of imposing a form upon a matter but of
|
||
elaborating an increasingly rich and consistent material, the better to tap
|
||
increasingly intense forces. What makes a material increasingly rich is the
|
||
same as what holds heterogeneities together without their ceasing to be het-
|
||
erogeneous. What holds them together in this way are intercalary oscilla-
|
||
tors, synthesizers with at least two heads; these are interval analyzers,
|
||
rhythm synchronizers (the word "synchronizer" is ambiguous because
|
||
molecular synchronizers do not proceed by homogenizing and equalizing
|
||
measurement, but operate from within, between two rhythms). Is not con-
|
||
solidation the terrestrial name for consistency? The territorial assemblage
|
||
is a milieu consolidation, a space-time consolidation, of coexistence and
|
||
succession. And the refrain operates with these three factors.
|
||
The matters of expression themselves must present characteristics mak-
|
||
ing this taking on of consistency possible. We have seen that they have an
|
||
aptitude to enter into internal relations forming motifs and counterpoints:
|
||
the territorializing marks become territorial motifs or counterpoints, the
|
||
signatures and placards constitute a "style." These are the elements of a
|
||
discrete or fuzzy aggregate; but they become consolidated, take on consis-
|
||
tency. To this extent, they have effects, such as reorganizing functions and
|
||
gathering forces. To get a better grasp on the mechanism of this aptitude,
|
||
we may lay down certain conditions of homogeneity, beginning with marks
|
||
330 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
or matters of the same kind, for example, a set of sonorous marks, the song
|
||
of a bird. The song of the chaffinch normally has three distinct phases: the
|
||
first has from four to fourteen notes rising in crescendo but decreasing in
|
||
frequency; the second has from two to eight notes, lower than the first and
|
||
of constant frequency; the third ends with a complex "flourish" or "orna-
|
||
ment." From the standpoint of acquisition, this "full song" is preceded by a
|
||
"subsong" that under normal conditions already assumes possession of the
|
||
general tonal quality, overall duration and content of the stanzas, and even
|
||
a tendency to end on a higher note.33 But the organization into three stan-
|
||
zas, the order of the stanzas, the details and the ornament, are not pregiven;
|
||
it is precisely the articulations from within that are missing, the intervals,
|
||
the intercalary notes, everything making for motif and counterpoint. The
|
||
distinction between subsong and full song could thus be presented as fol-
|
||
lows: the subsong as mark or placard, the full song as style or motif, and the
|
||
aptitude to pass from one to the other, for one to consolidate itself in the
|
||
other. Clearly, artificial isolation will have very different effects depending
|
||
on whether it takes place before or after the acquisition of the components
|
||
ofthe subsong.
|
||
Our present concern, however, is to find out what happens when these
|
||
components effectively develop into the motifs and counterpoints of the
|
||
full song. We must leave behind the conditions of qualitative homogeneity
|
||
we set for ourselves. For as long as we confine ourselves to marks, marks of
|
||
one kind coexist with marks of another kind, period: the sounds of an ani-
|
||
mal coexist with its colors, gestures, silhouettes; or else the sounds of a
|
||
given species coexist with the sounds of other species, perhaps quite differ-
|
||
ent but close in space. The organization of qualified marks into motifs and
|
||
counterpoints necessarily entails a taking on of consistency, or a capture of
|
||
the marks of another quality, a mutual branching of sounds-colors-
|
||
gestures, or a capture of sounds from different animal species, etc. Consis-
|
||
tency necessarily occurs between heterogeneities, not because it is the birth
|
||
of a differentiation, but because heterogeneities that were formerly content
|
||
to coexist or succeed one another become bound up with one another
|
||
through the "consolidation" of their coexistence and succession. The inter-
|
||
vals, intercalations, and articulations constitutive of motifs and counter-
|
||
points in the order of an expressive quality also envelop other qualities of a
|
||
different order, or qualities of the same order but of another sex or even
|
||
another species of animal. A color will "answer to" a sound. If a quality has
|
||
motifs and counterpoints, if there are rhythmic characters and melodic
|
||
landscapes in a given order, then there is the constitution of a veritable
|
||
machinic opera tying together orders, species, and heterogeneous qualities.
|
||
What we term machinic is precisely this synthesis of heterogeneities as
|
||
such. Inasmuch as these heterogeneities are matters of expression, we say
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 331
|
||
|
||
that their synthesis itself, their consistency or capture, forms a properly
|
||
machinic "statement" or "enunciation." The varying relations into which
|
||
a color, sound, gesture, movement, or position enters in the same species,
|
||
and in different species, form so many machinic enunciations.
|
||
Let us return to the stagemaker, the magic bird or bird of the opera. He is
|
||
not brightly colored (as though there were an inhibition). But his song, his
|
||
refrain, can be heard from a great distance (is this a compensation, or on
|
||
the contrary the prime factor?). He sings perched on his singing stick, a
|
||
vine or branch located just above the display ground he has prepared by
|
||
marking it with cut leaves turned upside down to contrast with the color of
|
||
the earth. As he sings, he uncovers the yellow root of certain feathers under-
|
||
neath his beak: he makes himself visible at the same time as sonorous. His
|
||
song forms a varied and complex motif interweaving his own notes and
|
||
those of other birds that he imitates in the intervals.34 This produces a con-
|
||
solidation that "consists" in species-specific sounds, sounds of other spe-
|
||
cies, leaf hue, throat color: the stagemaker's machinic statement or
|
||
assemblage of enunciation. Many birds "imitate" the songs of other spe-
|
||
cies. But imitation may not be the best concept for these phenomena,
|
||
which vary according to the assemblage into which they enter. The subsong
|
||
contains elements that can enter into melodic and rhythmic organizations
|
||
distinct from those of the species under consideration, supplying the full
|
||
song with truly alien or added notes. If certain birds such as the chaffinch
|
||
seem impervious to imitation, it is because any alien sounds appearing in
|
||
their subsong are eliminated from the consistency of the full song. On the
|
||
other hand, in cases where added phrases do get included in the full song, it
|
||
may be because there is an interspecific assemblage of the parasitism type;
|
||
or it may be because the bird's assemblage itself effectuates the counter-
|
||
points to its melody. Thorpe is not wrong to say that the problem is one of
|
||
the occupation of frequency bands, as with radios (the sound aspect of ter-
|
||
ritoriality).35 It is less a question of imitating a song than of occupying cor-
|
||
responding frequencies; for there may be an advantage in being able to
|
||
restrict oneself to a very determinate zone in some circumstances, and in
|
||
others to widen or deepen the zone to assure oneself counterpoints and to
|
||
invent chords that would otherwise remain diffuse, as, for example, in the
|
||
rain forest, which is precisely where the greatest number of "imitative"
|
||
birds are found.
|
||
From the standpoint of consistency, matters of expression must be con-
|
||
sidered not only in relation to their aptitude to form motifs and counter-
|
||
points but also in relation to the inhibitors and releasers that act on them,
|
||
and the mechanisms of innateness or learning, heredity or acquisition, that
|
||
modulate them. Ethology's mistake is to restrict itself to a binary distri-
|
||
bution of these factors, even, and especially, when it is thought necessary to
|
||
332 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
take both into account simultaneously, to intermix them at every level of a
|
||
"tree of behaviors." Instead, what should be done is to start from a positive
|
||
notion capable of accounting for the very particular character the innate
|
||
and the acquired assume in the rhizome, and which is like the principle of
|
||
their mixture. Such a notion cannot be arrived at in terms of behavior but
|
||
rather only in terms of assemblage. Some authors emphasize autonomous
|
||
developments encoded in centers (innateness); others emphasize acquired
|
||
linkages regulated by peripheral sensations (learning). But Raymond
|
||
Ruyer has demonstrated that the animal is instead prey to "musical
|
||
rhythms" and "melodic and rhythmic themes" explainable neither as the
|
||
encoding of a recorded phonograph disk nor by the movements of per-
|
||
formance that effectuate them and adapt them to the circumstances.36 The
|
||
opposite is even true: the melodic or rhythmic themes precede their per-
|
||
formance and recording. What is primary is the consistency of a refrain, a
|
||
little tune, either in the form of a mnemic melody that has no need to be
|
||
inscribed locally in a center, or in the form of a vague motif with no need to
|
||
be pulsed or stimulated. There is perhaps more to be learned from a musi-
|
||
cal and poetic notion such as the Natal—in the lied, or in Holderlin or
|
||
Thomas Hardy—than from the slightly vapid and foggy categories of the
|
||
innate and the acquired. For from the moment there is a territorial assem-
|
||
blage, we can say that the innate assumes a very particular figure, since it is
|
||
inseparable from a movement of decoding and passes to the margins of the
|
||
code, unlike the innate of the interior milieu; acquisition also assumes a
|
||
very particular figure, since it is territorialized, in other words, regulated
|
||
by matters of expression rather than by stimuli in the exterior milieu. The
|
||
natal is the innate, but decoded; and it is the acquired, but territorialized.
|
||
The natal is the new figure assumed by the innate and the acquired in the
|
||
territorial assemblage. The affect proper to the natal, as heard in the lied: to
|
||
be forever lost, or refound, or aspiring to the unknown homeland. In the
|
||
natal, the innate tends to be displaced: as Ruyer says, it is in some way prior
|
||
to or downstream from the act; it concerns less the act or the behavior than
|
||
the matters of expression themselves, the perception that discerns and
|
||
selects them, and the gesture that erects them, or itself constitutes them
|
||
(that is why there are "critical periods" when the animal valorizes an object
|
||
or situation, "is impregnated" by a matter of expression, long before being
|
||
able to perform the corresponding act). This is not to say, however, that
|
||
behavior is at the mercy of chance learning; for it is predetermined by this
|
||
displacement, and finds rules of assemblage in its own territorialization.
|
||
The natal, then, consists in a decoding of innateness and a territo-
|
||
rialization of learning, one atop the other, one alongside the other. The
|
||
natal has a consistency that cannot be explained as a mixture of the innate
|
||
and the acquired, because it is instead what accounts for such mixtures in
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 333
|
||
|
||
territorial assemblage and interassemblages. In short, the notion of behav-
|
||
ior proves inadequate, too linear, in comparison with that of the assem-
|
||
blage. The natal stretches from what happens in the intra-assemblage all
|
||
the way to the center that has been projected outside; it cuts across all the
|
||
interassemblages and reaches all the way to the gates of the Cosmos.
|
||
The territorial assemblage is inseparable from lines or coefficients of
|
||
deterritorialization, passages, and relays toward other assemblages. There
|
||
have been many studies on the influence of artificial conditions on bird
|
||
song, but the results vary both by species and according to the kind and
|
||
timing of the artifice. Many birds are receptive to the songs of other spe-
|
||
cies, if they are exposed to them during the critical period, and will repro-
|
||
duce the alien songs later on. The chaffinch, however, seems much more
|
||
devoted to its own matters of expression and retains an innate sense of its
|
||
own tonal quality even if exposed to synthetic sounds. The outcome also
|
||
depends on whether the birds are isolated before or after the critical period.
|
||
In the first case, chaffinches develop a nearly normal song; in the second,
|
||
the subjects in the isolated group (who cannot hear each other) develop an
|
||
abnormal, nonspecies-specific song that is nevertheless common to the
|
||
group (see Thorpe). In any event, it is necessary to consider the effects of
|
||
deterritorialization or denatalization on a given species at a given moment.
|
||
Whenever a territorial assemblage is taken up by a movement that
|
||
deterritorializes it (whether under so-called natural or artificial condi-
|
||
tions), we say that a machine is released. That in fact is the distinction we
|
||
would like to propose between machine and assemblage: a machine is like a
|
||
set of cutting edges that insert themselves into the assemblage undergoing
|
||
deterritorialization, and draw variations and mutations of it. For there are
|
||
no mechanical effects; effects are always machinic, in other words, depend
|
||
on a machine that is plugged into an assemblage and has been freed
|
||
through deterritorialization. What we call machinic statements are
|
||
machine effects that define consistency or enter matters of expression.
|
||
Effects of this kind can be very diverse but are never symbolic or imagi-
|
||
nary; they always have a real value of passage or relay.
|
||
As a general rule, a machine plugs into the territorial assemblage of a
|
||
species and opens it to other assemblages, causes it to pass through the
|
||
interassemblages of that species; for example, the territorial assemblage of
|
||
a bird species opens onto interassemblages of courtship and gregar-
|
||
iousness, moving in the direction of the partner or "socius." But the
|
||
machine may also open the territorial assemblage to interspecific assem-
|
||
blages, as in the case of birds that adopt alien songs, and most especially in
|
||
the case of parasitism.37 Or it may go beyond all assemblages and produce
|
||
an opening onto the Cosmos. Or, conversely, instead of opening up the
|
||
deterritorialized assemblage onto something else, it may produce an effect
|
||
334 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
of closure, as if the aggregate had fallen into and continues to spin in a kind
|
||
of black hole. This is what happens under conditions of precocious or
|
||
extremely sudden deterritorialization, and when specific, interspecific,
|
||
and cosmic paths are blocked; the machine then produces "individual"
|
||
group effects spinning in circles, as in the case of chaffinches that have been
|
||
isolated too early, whose impoverished, simplified song expresses nothing
|
||
more than the resonance of the black hole in which they are trapped. It is
|
||
important to bring up this "black hole" function again because it can
|
||
increase our understanding of phenomena of inhibition, and is in turn
|
||
capable of breaking with the overnarrow inhibitor-releaser dualism. We
|
||
saw earlier that an interassemblage could include lines of impoverishment
|
||
and fixation leading to a black hole but could still perhaps lead into a richer
|
||
and more positive line of deterritorialization (for example, the "grass
|
||
stem" component among Australian grass finches falls into a black hole
|
||
and leads into the "refrain" component).38 Thus the black hole is a
|
||
machine effect in assemblages and has a complex relation to other effects.
|
||
It may be necessary for the release of innovative processes that they first
|
||
fall into a catastrophic black hole: stases of inhibition are associated with
|
||
the release of crossroads behaviors. On the other hand, when black holes
|
||
resonate together or inhibitions conjugate and echo each other, instead of
|
||
an opening onto consistency, we see a closure of the assemblage, as though
|
||
it were deterritorialized in the void: young chaffinches. Machines are
|
||
always singular keys that open or close an assemblage, a territory. More-
|
||
over, finding the machine in operation in a given territorial assemblage is
|
||
not enough; it is already in operation in the emergence of matters of expres-
|
||
sion, in other words, in the constitution of the assemblage and in the vec-
|
||
tors of deterritorialization that ply it from the start.
|
||
Thus consistency of matters of expression relates, on the one hand, to
|
||
their aptitude to form melodic and rhythmic themes and, on the other
|
||
hand, to the power of the natal. Finally, there is one other aspect: their very
|
||
special relation to the molecular (the machine starts us down this road).
|
||
The very words, "matters of expression," imply that expression has a pri-
|
||
mary relation to matter. As matters of expression take on consistency they
|
||
constitute semiotic systems, but the semiotic components are inseparable
|
||
from material components and are in exceptionally close contact with
|
||
molecular levels. The whole question is thus whether or not the molar-
|
||
molecular relation assumes a new figure here. In general, it has been possi-
|
||
ble to distinguish "molar-molecular" combinations that vary greatly
|
||
depending on the direction followed. First, individual atoms can enter into
|
||
probabilistic or statistical accumulations that tend to efface their individu-
|
||
ality; this already happens on the level of the molecule, and then again in
|
||
the molar aggregate. But they can become complicated in interactions and
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 335
|
||
|
||
retain their individuality inside the molecule, then in the macromolecule,
|
||
etc., setting up direct communications between individuals of different
|
||
orders.39 Second, it is clear that the distinction to be made is not between
|
||
the individual and the statistical. In fact, it is always a question of popula-
|
||
tions; statistics concerns individual phenomena, and antistatistical indi-
|
||
viduality operates only in relation to molecular populations. The distinc-
|
||
tion is between two group movements, as in Alembert's equation, in which
|
||
one group tends toward increasingly equilibrated, homogeneous, and
|
||
probable states (the divergent wave and the delayed potential), and the
|
||
other group tends toward less probable states of concentration (the conver-
|
||
gent wave and the anticipated potential).40 Third, the intramolecular inter-
|
||
nal forces that give an aggregate its molar form can be of two types: they are
|
||
either covalent, arborescent, mechanical, linear, localizable relations sub-
|
||
ject to chemical conditions of action and reaction or to linked reactions, or
|
||
they are indirect, noncovalent, machinic and nonmechanical, superlinear,
|
||
nonlocalizable bonds operating by stereospecific discernment or discrimi-
|
||
nation, rather than by linkage.41
|
||
These are different ways of stating the same distinction, which seems
|
||
much broader than the one we are looking for: it is, in effect, a distinction
|
||
between matter and life, or rather, since there is only one matter, between
|
||
two states, two tendencies of atomic matter (for example, there are bonds
|
||
that immobilize the linked atoms in relation to one another, and other
|
||
bonds that allow free rotation). Stating the distinction in the most general
|
||
way, we could say that it is between stratified systems or systems of stratifi-
|
||
cation on the one hand, and consistent, self-consistent aggregates on the
|
||
other. But the point is that consistency, far from being restricted to com-
|
||
plex life forms, fully pertains even to the most elementary atoms and parti-
|
||
cles. There is a coded system of stratification whenever, horizontally, there
|
||
are linear causalities between elements; and, vertically, hierarchies of order
|
||
between groupings; and, holding it all together in depth, a succession of
|
||
framing forms, each of which informs a substance and in turn serves as a
|
||
substance for another form. These causalities, hierarchies, and framings
|
||
constitute a stratum, as well as the passage from one stratum to another,
|
||
and the stratified combinations of the molecular and molar. On the other
|
||
hand, we may speak of aggregates of consistency when instead of a regu-
|
||
lated succession of forms-substances we are presented with consolidations
|
||
of very heterogeneous elements, orders that have been short-circuited or
|
||
even reverse causalities, and captures between materials and forces of a dif-
|
||
ferent nature: as if a machinic phylum, a destratifying transversality, moved
|
||
through elements, orders, forms and substances, the molar and the molec-
|
||
ular, freeing a matter and tapping forces.
|
||
Now if we ask ourselves where life fits into this distinction, we see that it
|
||
336 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
undoubtedly implies a gain in consistency, in other words, a surplus value
|
||
(surplus value o(destratification). For example, it contains a greater num-
|
||
ber of self-consistent aggregates and processes of consolidation and gives
|
||
them molar scope. It is destratifying from the outset, since its code is not
|
||
distributed throughout the entire stratum but rather occupies an emi-
|
||
nently specialized genetic line. But the question is almost contradictory,
|
||
because asking where life fits in amounts to treating it as a particular stra-
|
||
tum having its own order and befitting order, having its own forms and sub-
|
||
stances. It is true that it is both at once: a particularly complex system of
|
||
stratification and an aggregate of consistency that disrupts orders, forms,
|
||
and substances. As we have seen, the living thing performs a transcoding of
|
||
milieus that can be considered both to constitute a stratum and to effect
|
||
reverse causalities and transversals of destratification. The same question
|
||
can be asked when life no longer restricts itself to mixing milieus but
|
||
assembles territories as well. The territorial assemblage implies a decoding
|
||
and is inseparable from its own deterritorialization (two new types of sur-
|
||
plus value). "Ethology" then can be understood as a very privileged molar
|
||
domain for demonstrating how the most varied components (biochemical,
|
||
behavioral, perceptive, hereditary, acquired, improvised, social, etc.) can
|
||
crystallize in assemblages that respect neither the distinction between
|
||
orders nor the hierarchy of forms. What holds all the components together
|
||
are transversals, and the transversal itself is only a component that has
|
||
taken upon itself the specialized vector of deterritorialization. In effect,
|
||
what holds an assemblage together is not the play of framing forms or linear
|
||
causalities but, actually or potentially, its most deterritorialized compo-
|
||
nent, a cutting edge of deterritorialization. An example is the refrain: it is
|
||
more deterritorialized than the grass stem, but this does not preclude its
|
||
being "determined," in other words, connected to biochemical and molec-
|
||
ular components. The assemblage holds by its most deterritorialized com-
|
||
ponent, but deterritorialized is not the same as indeterminate (the refrain
|
||
may be narrowly connected to the presence of male hormones).42 A compo-
|
||
nent of this kind entering an assemblage may be among the most highly
|
||
determined, even mechanized, of components, but it will still bring "play"
|
||
to what it composes; it fosters the entry of new dimensions of the milieus by
|
||
releasing processes of discernibility, specialization, contraction, and accel-
|
||
eration that open new possibilities, that open the territorial assemblage
|
||
onto interassemblages. Back to the stagemaker: one of its acts consists in
|
||
discerning and causing to be discerned both sides of the leaf. This act is
|
||
connected to the determinism of the "toothed" beak. Assemblages are
|
||
defined simultaneously by matters of expression that take on consistency
|
||
independently of the form-substance relation; reverse causalities or
|
||
"advanced" determinisms, decoded innate functions related to acts ofdis-
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 337
|
||
|
||
cernment or election rather than to linked reactions; and molecular combi-
|
||
nations that proceed by noncovalent bonding rather than by linear
|
||
relations—in short, a new "pace" produced by the imbrication of the
|
||
semiotic and the material. From this standpoint, we may oppose the con-
|
||
sistency of assemblages to the stratification of milieus. But once again, this
|
||
opposition is only relative, entirely relative. Just as milieus swing between
|
||
a stratum state and a movement of destratification, assemblages swing
|
||
between a territorial closure that tends to restratify them and a deterrito-
|
||
rializing movement that on the contrary connects them with the Cosmos.
|
||
Thus it is not surprising that the distinction we were seeking was not
|
||
between assemblages and something else but between the two limits of any
|
||
possible assemblage, in other words, between the system of strata and the
|
||
plane of consistency. We should not forget that the strata rigidify and are
|
||
organized on the plane of consistency, and that the plane of consistency is
|
||
at work and is constructed in the strata, in both cases piece by piece, blow
|
||
by blow, operation by operation.
|
||
|
||
We have gone from stratified milieus to territorialized assemblages and
|
||
simultaneously, from the forces of chaos, as broken down, coded, trans-
|
||
coded by the milieus, to the forces of the earth, as gathered into the assem-
|
||
blages. Then we went from territorial assemblages to interassemblages, to'
|
||
the opening of assemblages along lines of deterritorialization; and simulta-
|
||
neously, the same from the ingathered forces of the earth to the
|
||
deterritorialized, or rather deterritorializing, Cosmos. How does Paul Klee
|
||
present this last movement, which is not a terrestrial "pace" but instead a
|
||
cosmic "breakaway" [echappee: also "opening," "outlet," "vista"; in coun-
|
||
terpoint, "escape tone"—Trans.]? And why so enormous a word, Cosmos,
|
||
to discuss an operation that must be precise? Klee says that one "tries con-
|
||
vulsively to fly from the earth," and that one "rises above i t . . . powered by
|
||
centrifugal forces that triumph over gravity." He adds that the artist begins
|
||
by looking around him- or herself, into all the milieus, but does so in order
|
||
to grasp the trace of creation in the created, of naturing nature in natured
|
||
nature; then, adopting "an earthbound position,"43 the artist turns his or
|
||
her attention to the microscopic, to crystals, molecules, atoms, and parti-
|
||
cles, not for scientific conformity, but for movement, for nothing but
|
||
immanent movement; the artist tells him- or herself that this world has had
|
||
different aspects, will have still others, and that there are already others on
|
||
other planets; finally, the artist opens up to the Cosmos in order to harness
|
||
forces in a "work" (without which the opening onto the Cosmos would only
|
||
be a reverie incapable of enlarging the limits of the earth); this work
|
||
requires very simple, pure, almost childish means, but also the forces of a
|
||
people, which is what is still lacking. "We still lack the ultimate force....
|
||
338 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
We seek a people. We began over there in the Bauhaus.... More we cannot
|
||
do."44
|
||
Classicism refers to form-matter relation, or rather a form-substance
|
||
relation (substance is precisely a matter endowed with form). Matter is
|
||
organized by a succession of forms that are compartmentalized, central-
|
||
ized, and hierarchized in relation to one another, each of which takes
|
||
charge of a greater or lesser amount of matter. Each form is like the code of
|
||
a milieu, and the passage from one form to another is a veritable
|
||
transcoding. Even the seasons are milieus. Two coexistent operations are
|
||
involved, one by which the form differentiates itself according to binary
|
||
distinctions, the other by which the formed substantial parts, milieus or
|
||
seasons, enter into an order of succession that can be the same in either
|
||
direction. But beneath these operations, the classical artist hazards an
|
||
extreme and dangerous adventure. He or she breaks down the milieus,
|
||
separates them, harmonizes them, regulates their mixtures, passes from
|
||
one to the other. What the artist confronts in this way is chaos, the forces
|
||
of chaos, the forces of a raw and untamed matter upon which Forms must
|
||
be imposed in order to make substances, and Codes in order to make
|
||
milieus. Phenomenal agility. That is why no one has ever been able to
|
||
draw a clear line between baroque and classical.45 All of baroque lies
|
||
brewing beneath classicism: the task of the classical artist is God's own,
|
||
that of organizing chaos; and the artist's only cry is Creation! Creation!
|
||
The Tree of Creation! An ancient wooden flute organizes chaos, but chaos
|
||
reigns like the Queen of the Night. The classical artist proceeds with a
|
||
One-Two: the one-two of the differentiation of form divided (man-
|
||
woman, masculine and feminine rhythms, voices, families of instru-
|
||
ments, all the binarities of the ars nova); and the one-two of the
|
||
distinction between parts as they answer each other (the enchanted flute
|
||
and the magic bell). The little tune, the bird refrain, is the binary unity of
|
||
creation, the differentiating unity of the pure beginning: "At first the
|
||
piano complained alone, like a bird deserted by its mate; the violin heard
|
||
and answered it, as from a neighboring tree. It was as at the beginning of
|
||
the world, as if there were as yet only the two of them on earth, or rather in
|
||
this world closed to all the rest, fashioned by the logic of a creator, in
|
||
which there would never be more than the two of them: this sonata."46
|
||
If we attempt an equally summary definition of romanticism, we see
|
||
that everything is clearly different. A new cry resounds: the Earth, the terri-
|
||
tory and the Earth! With romanticism, the artist abandons the ambition of
|
||
de jure universality and his or her status as creator: the artist territorializes,
|
||
enters a territorial assemblage. The seasons are now territorialized. The
|
||
earth is certainly not the same thing as the territory. The earth is the intense
|
||
point at the deepest level of the territory or is projected outside it like a
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 339
|
||
|
||
focal point, where all the forces draw together in close embrace. The earth
|
||
is no longer one force among others, nor is it a substance endowed with
|
||
form or a coded milieu, with bounds and an apportioned share. The earth
|
||
has become that close embrace of all forces, those of the earth as well as of
|
||
other substances, so that the artist no longer confronts chaos, but hell and
|
||
the subterranean, the groundless. The artist no longer risks dissipation in
|
||
the milieus but rather sinking too deeply into the earth: Empedocles. The
|
||
artist no longer identifies with Creation but with the ground or foundation,
|
||
the foundation has become creative. The artist is no longer God but the
|
||
Hero who defies God: Found, Found, instead of Create. Faust, especially
|
||
the second Faust, is impelled by this tendency. Criticism, the Protestant-
|
||
ism of the earth, replaces dogmatism, the Catholicism of the milieus
|
||
(code). It is certain that the Earth as an intense point in depth or in projec-
|
||
tion, as ratio essendi, is always in disjunction with the territory; and the ter-
|
||
ritory as the condition of "knowledge," ratio cognoscendi, is always in
|
||
disjunction with the earth. The territory is German, the Earth Greek. And
|
||
this disjunction is precisely what determines the status of the romantic art-
|
||
ist, in that she or he no longer confronts the gaping of chaos but the pull of
|
||
the Ground (Fond). The little tune, the bird refrain, has changed: it is no
|
||
longer the beginning of a world but draws a territorial assemblage upon the
|
||
earth. It is then no longer made of two consonant parts that seek and answer
|
||
one another; it addresses itself to a deeper singing that founds it, but also
|
||
strikes against it and sweeps it away, making it ring dissonant. The refrain is
|
||
indissolubly constituted by the territorial song and the singing of the earth
|
||
that rises to drown it out. Thus at the end of Das Lied von der Erde (The
|
||
song of the Earth) there are two coexistent motifs, one melodic, evoking the
|
||
assemblages of the bird, the other rhythmic, evoking the deep, eternal
|
||
breathing of the earth. Mahler says that the singing of the birds, the color of
|
||
the flowers, and the fragrance of the forest are not enough to make Nature,
|
||
that the god Dionysus and the great Pan are needed. The Ur-refrain of the
|
||
earth harnesses all refrains whether territorial or not, and all milieu
|
||
refrains. By the end of [Berg's] Wozzeck, the lullaby refrain, military
|
||
refrain, drinking refrain, hunting refrain, child's refrain are so many admi-
|
||
rable assemblages swept up by the powerful earth machine and its cutting
|
||
edges: Wozzeck's voice, by which the earth becomes sonorous, Marie's
|
||
death cry moving over the pond, the repeated B note, when the earth
|
||
howled . . . It is owing to this disjunction, this decoding, that the romantic
|
||
artist experiences the territory; but he or she experiences it as necessarily
|
||
lost, and experiences him- or herself as an exile, a voyager, as deterrito-
|
||
rialized, driven back into the milieus, like the Flying Dutchman or King
|
||
Waldemar (whereas the classical artist inhabited the milieus). Yet this
|
||
movement is still under earth's command, the repulsion from the territory
|
||
340 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
is produced by the attraction of the earth. The signpost now only indicates
|
||
the road of no return. This is the ambiguity of the natal, as it appears in the
|
||
lied (as well as in symphony and opera): the lied is simultaneously the terri-
|
||
tory, the lost territory, and the earth vector. The intermezzo assumed
|
||
increasing importance because it played on all the disjunctions between
|
||
the earth and the territory, inserted itself into them, filled them after its
|
||
fashion, "between night and day," "noon-midnight." From this stand-
|
||
point, the fundamental innovations of romanticism can be said to be the
|
||
following: There were no longer substantial parts corresponding to forms,
|
||
milieus corresponding to codes, or a matter in chaos given order in forms
|
||
and by codes. The parts were instead like assemblages produced and dis-
|
||
mantled at the surface. Form itself became a greatform in continuous devel-
|
||
opment, a gathering of the forces of the earth taking all the parts up into a
|
||
sheaf. Matter itself was no longer a chaos to subjugate and organize but
|
||
rather the moving matter of a continuous variation. The universal had
|
||
become a relation, variation. The continuous variation of matter and the
|
||
continuous development of form. The assemblages thus placed matter and
|
||
form in a new relation: matter ceased to be a matter of content, becoming
|
||
instead a matter of expression, and form ceased to be a code subduing the
|
||
forces of chaos, becoming a force itself, the sum of the forces of the earth.
|
||
There was a new relation to danger, madness, limits: romanticism did not
|
||
go further than baroque classicism; it went elsewhere, with other givens
|
||
and other vectors.
|
||
What romanticism lacks most is a people. The territory is haunted by a
|
||
solitary voice; the voice of the earth resonates with it and provides it per-
|
||
cussion rather than answering it. Even when there is a people, it is
|
||
mediatized by the earth, it rises up from the bowels of the earth and is apt to
|
||
return there: more a subterranean than a terrestrial people. The hero is a
|
||
hero of the earth; he is mythic, rather than being a hero of the people and
|
||
historical. Germany, German romanticism, had a genius for experiencing
|
||
the natal territory not as deserted but as "solitary," regardless of popula-
|
||
tion density; for the population is only an emanation of the earth, and has
|
||
the value of One Alone. The territory does not open onto a people, it half-
|
||
opens onto the Friend, the Loved One; but the Loved One is already dead,
|
||
and the Friend uncertain, disturbing.47 As in the lied, everything in the ter-
|
||
ritory occurs in relation to the One-Alone of the soul and the One-All of the
|
||
earth. That is why romanticism takes on an entirely different aspect and
|
||
even claims a different name, a different placard, in the Latin and Slavic
|
||
countries, where on the contrary everything is put in terms of the theme of
|
||
a people and the forces of a people. This time, it is the earth that is
|
||
mediatized by the people, and exists only through the people. This time,
|
||
the earth can be "deserted," an arid steppe, or a ravaged, dismembered ter-
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 341
|
||
|
||
ritory; yet it is never solitary, it is always filled by a nomadic population
|
||
that divides or regroups, contests or laments, attacks or suffers. This time,
|
||
the hero is a hero of the people, and not of the earth; her is related to the One-
|
||
Crowd, not the One-All. It certainly cannot be said that there is more or less
|
||
nationalism on one side or the other because nationalism is everywhere in
|
||
the figures of romanticism, sometimes as the driving force, sometimes as a
|
||
black hole (fascism used Verdi much less than nazism did Wagner). The
|
||
problem is a truly musical one, technically musical, and all the more politi-
|
||
cal for that. The romantic hero, the voice of the romantic hero, acts as a
|
||
subject, a subjectified individual with "feelings"; but this subjective vocal
|
||
element is reflected in an orchestral and instrumental whole that on the
|
||
contrary mobilizes nonsubjective "affects" and that reaches its height in
|
||
romanticism. It should not be thought that the vocal element and the
|
||
orchestral-instrumental whole are only in an extrinsic relation to one
|
||
another: the orchestration imposes a given role on the voice, and the voice
|
||
envelops a given mode of orchestration. Orchestration-instrumentation
|
||
brings sound forces together or separates them, gathers or disperses them;
|
||
but it changes, and the role of the voice changes too, depending on whether
|
||
the forces are of the Earth or of the People, of the One-All or the One-
|
||
Crowd. In the first case, it is a question of effecting grouping of powers, and
|
||
these are what constitute affects; in the second case, it is group
|
||
individuations that constitute affect and are the object of orchestration.
|
||
Groupings of power are fully diversified, but they are like the relations
|
||
proper to the Universal; we must use another word, the Dividual, to desig-
|
||
nate the type of musical relations and the intra- or intergroup passages
|
||
occurring in group individuation. The sentimental or subjective element
|
||
of the voice has a different role and even a different position depending on
|
||
whether it internally confronts nonsubjectified groupings of power or
|
||
nonsubjectified group individuation, the relations of the universal or the
|
||
relations of the "dividual." Debussy formulated the problem of the One-
|
||
Crowd well when he reproached Wagner for not knowing how to "do" a
|
||
crowd or a people: a crowd must be fully individuated, but by group
|
||
individuations that are not reducible to the individuality of the subjects
|
||
that compose the crowd.48 The people must be individualized, not accord-
|
||
ing to the persons within it, but according to the affects it experiences,
|
||
simultaneously or successively. The concepts of the One-Crowd and the
|
||
Dividual are botched if the people is reduced to a juxtaposition, or if it is
|
||
reduced to a power of the universal. In short, there are two very different
|
||
conceptions of orchestration, depending on whether one is seeking to
|
||
sonorize the forces of the Earth or the forces of the People. The simplest
|
||
example of this difference is doubtless Wagner-Verdi, in that Verdi puts
|
||
increasing emphasis on the relations between the voice and instrumenta-
|
||
342 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
tion and orchestration. Even today, Stockhausen and Berio outline a new
|
||
version of this difference, even though they are grappling with a musical
|
||
problem different from that of romanticism (in Berio there is a search for a
|
||
multiple cry, a cry of the population, in the dividual of the One-Crowd, and
|
||
not for a cry of the Earth in the universal of the One-All). The idea of an
|
||
Opera of the world, or cosmic music, changes drastically depending on
|
||
which pole of orchestration is in play.49 To avoid an oversimplified opposi-
|
||
tion between Wagner and Verdi, we would have to show how Berlioz had a
|
||
genius for passing from one pole to the other in his orchestration, or even
|
||
hesitating between them: a sonorous Nature or People. And how music like
|
||
Mussorgsky's was able to do a crowd (despite what Debussy says). And how
|
||
music like Bartok's was able to use popular, or population, airs to do popu-
|
||
lations, themselves sonorous, instrumental, and orchestral, which impose
|
||
a Dividual scale, a prodigious new chromaticism.50 And then there are all
|
||
the non-Wagnerian paths . . .
|
||
If there is a modern age, it is, of course, the age of the cosmic. Paul Klee
|
||
declared himself anti-Faustian. "As for animals and all the other creatures,
|
||
I do not like them with a terrestrial cordiality; earthly things interest me
|
||
less than cosmic things." The assemblage no longer confronts the forces of
|
||
chaos, it no longer uses the forces of the earth or the people to deepen itself
|
||
but instead opens onto the forces of the Cosmos. All this seems extremely
|
||
general, and somewhat Hegelian, testifying to an absolute Spirit. Yet it is,
|
||
should be, a question of technique, exclusively a question of technique.
|
||
The essential relation is no longer matters-forms (or substances-attri-
|
||
butes); neither is it the continuous development of form and the continu-
|
||
ous variation of matter. It is now a direct relation material-forces. A
|
||
material is a molecularized matter, which must accordingly "harness"
|
||
forces; these forces are necessarily forces of the Cosmos. There is no longer
|
||
a matter that finds its corresponding principle of intelligibility in form. It is
|
||
now a question of elaborating a material charged with harnessing forces of
|
||
a different order: the visual material must capture nonvisible forces. Ren-
|
||
der visible, Klee said; not render or reproduce the visible. From this per-
|
||
spective, philosophy follows the same movement as the other activities;
|
||
whereas romantic philosophy still appealed to a formal synthetic identity
|
||
ensuring a continuous intelligibility of matter (a priori synthesis), modern
|
||
philosophy tends to elaborate a material of thought in order to capture
|
||
forces that are not thinkable in themselves. This is Cosmos philosophy,
|
||
after the manner of Nietzsche. The molecular material has even become so
|
||
deterritorialized that we can no longer even speak of matters of expression,
|
||
as we did in romantic territoriality. Matters of expression are superseded by
|
||
a material of capture. The forces to be captured are no longer those of the
|
||
earth, which still constitute a great expressive Form, but the forces of an
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 343
|
||
|
||
immaterial, nonformal, and energetic Cosmos. The painter Millet used to
|
||
say that what counts in painting is not, for example, what a peasant is carry-
|
||
ing, whether it is a sacred object or a sack of potatoes, but its exact weight.
|
||
This is the postromantic turning point: the essential thing is no longer
|
||
forms and matters, or themes, but forces, densities, intensities. The earth
|
||
itself swings over, tending to take on the value of pure material for a force of
|
||
gravitation or weight. Perhaps it is not until Cezanne that rocks begin to
|
||
exist uniquely through the forces of folding they harness, landscapes
|
||
through thermal and magnetic forces, and apples through forces of germi-
|
||
nation: nonvisual forces that nevertheless have been rendered visible.
|
||
When forces become necessarily cosmic, material becomes necessarily
|
||
molecular, with enormous force operating in an infinitesimal space. The
|
||
problem is no longer that of the beginning, any more than it is that of a
|
||
foundation-ground. It is now a problem of consistency or consolidation:
|
||
how to consolidate the material, make it consistent, so that it can harness
|
||
unthinkable, invisible, nonsonorous forces. Debussy ... Music molecu-
|
||
larizes sound matter and in so doing becomes capable of harnessing
|
||
nonsonorous forces such as Duration and Intensity.51 Render Duration
|
||
sonorous. Let us recall Nietzsche's idea of the eternal return as a little ditty,
|
||
a refrain, but which captures the mute and unthinkable forces of the Cos-
|
||
mos. We thus leave behind the assemblages to enter the age of the Machine,
|
||
the immense mechanosphere, the plane of cosmicization of forces to be
|
||
harnessed. Varese's procedure, at the dawn of this age, is exemplary: a
|
||
musical machine of consistency, a sound machine (not a machine for repro-
|
||
ducing sounds), which molecularizes and atomizes, ionizes sound matter,
|
||
and harnesses a cosmic energy.52 If this machine must have an assemblage,
|
||
it is the synthesizer. By assembling modules, source elements, and ele-
|
||
ments for treating sound (oscillators, generators, and transformers), by
|
||
arranging microintervals, the synthesizer makes audible the sound process
|
||
itself, the production of that process, and puts us in contact with still other
|
||
elements beyond sound matter.53 It unites disparate elements in the mate-
|
||
rial, and transposes the parameters from one formula to another. The syn-
|
||
thesizer, with its operation of consistency, has taken the place of the ground
|
||
in a priori synthetic judgment: its synthesis is of the molecular and the cos-
|
||
mic, material and force, not form and matter, Grundand territory. Philoso-
|
||
phy is no longer synthetic judgment; it is like a thought synthesizer
|
||
functioning to make thought travel, make it mobile, make it a force of the
|
||
Cosmos (in the same way as one makes sound travel).
|
||
This synthesis of disparate elements is not without ambiguity. It has the
|
||
same ambiguity, perhaps, as the modern valorization of children's draw-
|
||
ings, texts by the mad, and concerts of noise. Sometimes one overdoes it,
|
||
puts too much in, works with a jumble of lines and sounds; then instead of
|
||
344 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
producing a cosmic machine capable of "rendering sonorous," one lapses
|
||
back to a machine of reproduction that ends up reproducing nothing but a
|
||
scribble effacing all lines, a scramble effacing all sounds. The claim is that
|
||
one is opening music to all events, all irruptions, but one ends up reproduc-
|
||
ing a scrambling that prevents any event from happening. All one has left is
|
||
a resonance chamber well on the way to forming a black hole. A material
|
||
that is too rich remains too "territorialized": on noise sources, on the
|
||
nature of the objects . . . (this even applies to Cage's prepared piano). One
|
||
makes an aggregate fuzzy, instead of defining the fuzzy aggregate by the
|
||
operations of consistency or consolidation pertaining to it. For this is the
|
||
essential thing: a fuzzy aggregate, a synthesis of disparate elements, is
|
||
defined only by a degree of consistency that makes it possible to distinguish
|
||
the disparate elements constituting that aggregate (discernibility).54 The
|
||
material must be sufficiently deterritorialized to be molecularized and
|
||
open onto something cosmic, instead of lapsing into a statistical heap. This
|
||
condition is met only if there is a certain simplicity in the nonuniform
|
||
material: a maximum of calculated sobriety in relation to the disparate ele-
|
||
ments and the parameters. The sobriety of the assemblages is what makes
|
||
for the richness of the Machine's effects. People often have too much of a
|
||
tendency to reterritorialize on the child, the mad, noise. If this is done, one
|
||
fuzzifles instead of making the fuzzy aggregate consist, or harnessing cos-
|
||
mic forces in the deterritorialized material. That is why it infuriated Paul
|
||
Klee when people would talk about the "childishness" of his drawings (and
|
||
Varese when they would talk about sound effects, etc.). According to Klee,
|
||
what is needed in order to "render visible" or harness the Cosmos is a pure
|
||
and simple line accompanied by the idea of an object, and nothing more: if
|
||
you multiply the lines and take the whole object, you get nothing but a
|
||
scramble, and visual sound effects.55 According to Varese, in order for the
|
||
projection to yield a highly complex form, in other words, a cosmic distri-
|
||
bution, what is necessary is a simple figure in motion and a plane that is
|
||
itself mobile; otherwise, you get sound effects. Sobriety, sobriety: that is the
|
||
common prerequisite for the deterritorialization of matters, the molecu-
|
||
larization of material, and the cosmicization offerees. Maybe a child can
|
||
do that. But the sobriety involved is the sobriety of a becoming-child that is
|
||
not necessarily the becoming o/the child, quite the contrary; the becoming-
|
||
mad involved is not necessarily the becoming o/the madman, quite the
|
||
contrary. It is clear that what is necessary to make sound travel, and to
|
||
travel around sound, is very pure and simple sound, an emission or wave
|
||
without harmonics (La Monte Young has been successful at this). The
|
||
more rarefied the atmosphere, the more disparate the elements you will
|
||
find. Your synthesis of disparate elements will be all the stronger if you pro-
|
||
ceed with a sober gesture, an act of consistency, capture, or extraction that
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 345
|
||
|
||
works in a material that is not meager but prodigiously simplified, crea-
|
||
tively limited, selected. For there is no imagination outside of technique.
|
||
The modern figure is not the child or the lunatic, still less the artist, but the
|
||
cosmic artisan: a homemade atomic bomb—it's very simple really, it's
|
||
been proven, it's been done. To be an artisan and no longer an artist, cre-
|
||
ator, or founder, is the only way to become cosmic, to leave the milieus and
|
||
the earth behind. The invocation to the Cosmos does not at all operate as a
|
||
metaphor; on the contrary, the operation is an effective one, from the
|
||
moment the artist connects a material with forces of consistency or
|
||
consolidation.
|
||
Material thus has three principal characteristics: it is a molecularized
|
||
matter; it has a relation to forces to be harnessed; and it is defined by the
|
||
operations of consistency applied to it. Finally, it is clear that the relation to
|
||
the earth and the people has changed, and is no longer of the romantic type.
|
||
The earth is now at its most deterritorialized: not only a point in a galaxy,
|
||
but one galaxy among others. The people is now at its most molecularized:
|
||
a molecular population, a people of oscillators as so many forces of interac-
|
||
tion. The artist discards romantic figures, relinquishes both the forces of
|
||
the earth and those of the people. The combat, if combat there is, has
|
||
moved. The established powers have occupied the earth, they have built
|
||
people's organizations. The mass media, the great people's organizations
|
||
of the party or union type, are machines for reproduction, fuzzification
|
||
machines that effectively scramble all the terrestrial forces of the people.
|
||
The established powers have placed us in the situation of a combat at once
|
||
atomic and cosmic, galactic. Many artists became aware of this situation
|
||
long ago, even before it had been installed (Nietzsche, for example). They
|
||
became aware of it because the same vector was traversing their own
|
||
domain: a molecularization, an atomization of the material, coupled with
|
||
a cosmicization of the forces taken up by that material. The question then
|
||
became whether molecular or atomic "populations" of all natures (mass
|
||
media, monitoring procedures, computers, space weapons) would con-
|
||
tinue to bombard the existing people in order to train it or control it or
|
||
annihilate it—or if other molecular populations were possible, could slip
|
||
into the first and give rise to a people yet to come. As Virilio says in his very
|
||
rigorous analysis of the depopulation of the people and the deterrito-
|
||
rialization of the earth, the question has become: "To dwell as a poet or as
|
||
an assassin?"56 The assassin is one who bombards the existing people with
|
||
molecular populations that are forever closing all of the assemblages, hurl-
|
||
ing them into an ever wider and deeper black hole. The poet, on the other
|
||
hand, is one who lets loose molecular populations in hopes that this will
|
||
sow the seeds of, or even engender, the people to come, that these popula-
|
||
tions will pass into a people to come, open a cosmos. Once again, we must
|
||
346 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
not make it seem as though the poet gorged on metaphors: it may be that the
|
||
sound molecules of pop music are at this very moment implanting here and
|
||
there a people of a new type, singularly indifferent to the orders of the
|
||
radio, to computer safeguards, to the threat of the atomic bomb. In this
|
||
respect, the relation of artists to the people has changed significantly: the
|
||
artist has ceased to be the One-Alone withdrawn into him- or herself, but
|
||
has also ceased to address the people, to invoke the people as a constituted
|
||
force. Never has the artist been more in need of a people, while stating most
|
||
firmly that the people is lacking—the people is what is most lacking. We
|
||
are not referring to popular or populist artists. Mallarme said that the Book
|
||
needed a people. Kafka said that literature is the affair of the people. Klee
|
||
said that the people is essential yet lacking. Thus the problem of the artist is
|
||
that the modern depopulation of the people results in an open earth, and by
|
||
means of art, or by means to which art contributes. Instead of being bom-
|
||
barded from all sides in a limiting cosmos, the people and the earth must be
|
||
like the vectors of a cosmos that carries them off; then the cosmos itself will
|
||
be art. From depopulation, make a cosmic people; from deterritorializa-
|
||
tion, a cosmic earth—that is the wish of the artisan-artist, here, there,
|
||
locally. Our governments deal with the molecular and the cosmic, and our
|
||
arts make them their affair also, with the same stakes, the people and the
|
||
earth, and with unfortunately incomparable, but nevertheless competi-
|
||
tive, means. Is it not of the nature of creations to operate in silence, locally,
|
||
to seek consolidation everywhere, to go from the molecular to an uncertain
|
||
cosmos, whereas the processes of destruction and conservation work in
|
||
bulk, take center stage, occupy the entire cosmos in order to enslave the
|
||
molecular and to stick it in a conservatory or a bomb?
|
||
These three "ages," the classical, romantic, and modern (for lack of a
|
||
better term), should not be interpreted as an evolution, or as structures sep-
|
||
arated by signifying breaks. They are assemblages enveloping different
|
||
Machines, or different relations to the Machine. In a sense, everything we
|
||
attribute to an age was already present in the preceding age. Forces, for
|
||
example: it has always been a question offerees, designated either as forces
|
||
of chaos or forces of the earth. Similarly, for all of time painting has had the
|
||
project of rendering visible, instead of reproducing the visible, and music
|
||
of rendering sonorous, instead of reproducing the sonorous. Fuzzy aggre-
|
||
gates have been constituting themselves and inventing their processes of
|
||
consolidation all along. A freeing of the molecular was already found in
|
||
classical matters of content, operating by destratification, and in romantic
|
||
matters of expression, operating by decoding. The most we can say is that
|
||
when forces appear as forces of the earth or of chaos, they are not grasped
|
||
directly as forces but as reflected in relations between matter and form.
|
||
Thus it is more a question of thresholds of perception, or thresholds of
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 347
|
||
|
||
discernibility belonging to given assemblages. It is only after matter has
|
||
been sufficiently deterritorialized that it itself emerges as molecular and
|
||
brings forth pure forces attributable only to the Cosmos. It had been pres-
|
||
ent "for all of time," but under different perceptual conditions. New condi-
|
||
tions were necessary for what was buried or covered, inferred or con-
|
||
cluded, presently to rise to the surface. What was composed in an
|
||
assemblage, what was still only composed, becomes a component of a new
|
||
assemblage. In this sense, all history is really the history of perception, and
|
||
what we make history with is the matter of a becoming, not the subject mat-
|
||
ter of a story. Becoming is like the machine: present in a different way in
|
||
every assemblage, passing from one to the other, opening one onto the
|
||
other, outside any fixed order or determined sequence.
|
||
We are now ready to return to the refrain. We can propose a new classifi-
|
||
cation system: milieu refrains, with at least two parts, one of which answers
|
||
the other (the piano and the violin); natal refrains, refrains of the territory,
|
||
where the part is related to the whole, to an immense refrain of the earth,
|
||
according to relations that are themselves variable and mark in each
|
||
instance the disjunction between the earth and the territory (the lullaby,
|
||
the drinking song, hunting song, work song, military song, etc.); folk and
|
||
popular refrains, themselves tied to an immense song of the people,
|
||
according to variable relations of crowd individuations that simultane-
|
||
ously bring into play affects and nations (the Polish, Auvergnat, German,
|
||
Magyar, or Romanian, but also the Pathetic, Panicked, Vengeful, etc.);
|
||
molecularized refrains (the sea and the wind) tied to cosmic forces, the
|
||
Cosmos refrain. For the Cosmos itself is a refrain, and the ear also (every-
|
||
thing that has been taken for a labyrinth is in fact a refrain). But precisely
|
||
why is the refrain eminently sonorous? Why this privileging of the ear,
|
||
when even animals and birds present us with so many visual, chromatic,
|
||
postural, and gestural refrains? Does the painter have fewer refrains than
|
||
the musician? Are there fewer refrains in Cezanne or Klee than in Mozart,
|
||
Schumann, or Debussy? Taking Proust's examples: Does Vermeer's little
|
||
yellow span of wall, or a painter's flowers, Elstir's roses, constitute less of a
|
||
refrain than Vinteuil's little phrase? There is surely no question here of
|
||
declaring a given art supreme on the basis of a formal hierarchy of absolute
|
||
criteria. Our problem is more modest: comparing the powers or coeffi-
|
||
cients of deterritorialization of sonorous and visual components. It seems
|
||
that when sound deterritorializes, it becomes more and more refined; it
|
||
becomes specialized and autonomous. Color clings more, not necessarily
|
||
to the object, but to territoriality. When it deterritorializes, it tends to
|
||
dissolve, to let itself be steered by other components. This is evident in
|
||
phenomena of synesthesia, which are not reducible to a simple color-sound
|
||
correspondence; sounds have a piloting role and induce colors that are
|
||
348 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
superposed upon the colors we see, lending them a properly sonorous
|
||
rhythm and movement.57 Sound owes this power not to signifying or
|
||
"communicational" values (which on the contrary presuppose that pow-
|
||
er), nor to physical properties (which would privilege light over sound),
|
||
but to a phylogenetic line, a machinic phylum that operates in sound
|
||
and makes it a cutting edge of deterritorialization. But this does not
|
||
happen without great ambiguity: sound invades us, impels us, drags us,
|
||
transpierces us. It takes leave of the earth, as much in order to drop us into a
|
||
black hole as to open us up to a cosmos. It makes us want to die. Since its
|
||
force of deterritorialization is the strongest, it also effects the most massive
|
||
of reterritorializations, the most numbing, the most redundant. Ecstasy
|
||
and hypnosis. Colors do not move a people. Flags can do nothing without
|
||
trumpets. Lasers are modulated on sound. The refrain is sonorous par
|
||
excellence, but it can as easily develop its force into a sickly sweet ditty as
|
||
into the purest motif, or Vinteuil's little phrase. And sometimes the two
|
||
combine: Beethoven used as a "signature tune." The potential fascism of
|
||
music. Overall, we may say that music is plugged into a machinic phylum
|
||
infinitely more powerful than that of painting: a line of selective pressure.
|
||
That is why the musician has a different relation to the people, machines,
|
||
and the established powers than does the painter. In particular, the estab-
|
||
lished powers feel a keen need to control the distribution of black holes and
|
||
lines of deterritorialization in this phylum of sounds, in order to ward off
|
||
or appropriate the effects of musical machinism. Painters, at least as com-
|
||
monly portrayed, may be much more open socially, much more political,
|
||
and less controlled from without and within. That is because each time
|
||
they paint, they must create or recreate a phylum, and they must do so on
|
||
the basis of bodies of light and color they themselves produce, whereas
|
||
musicians have at their disposal a kind of germinal continuity, even if it is
|
||
latent or indirect, on the basis of which they produce sound bodies. Two
|
||
different movements of creation: one goes from soma to germen, and the
|
||
other from germen to soma. The painter's refrain is like the flipside of the
|
||
musician's, a negative of music.
|
||
So just what is a refrain? Glass harmonica: the refrain is a prism, a crys-
|
||
tal of space-time. It acts upon that which surrounds it, sound or light,
|
||
extracting from it various vibrations, or decompositions, projections, or
|
||
transformations. The refrain also has a catalytic function: not only to
|
||
increase the speed of the exchanges and reactions in that which surrounds
|
||
it, but also to assure indirect interactions between elements devoid of
|
||
so-called natural affinity, and thereby to form organized masses. The
|
||
refrain is therefore of the crystal or protein type. The seed, or internal
|
||
structure, then has two essential aspects: augmentations and diminutions,
|
||
additions and withdrawals, amplifications and eliminations by unequal
|
||
1837: OF THE REFRAIN D 349
|
||
|
||
values, but also the presence of a retrograde motion running in both direc-
|
||
tions, as "in the side windows of a moving streetcar." The strange ret-
|
||
rograde motion of Joke. It is of the nature of the refrain to become
|
||
concentrated by elimination in a very short moment, as though moving
|
||
from the extremes to a center, or, on the contrary, to develop by additions,
|
||
moving from a center to the extremes, and also to travel these routes in
|
||
both directions.58 The refrain fabricates time (du temps). The refrain is the
|
||
"implied tense" (temps) discussed by the linguist Gustave Guillaume. The
|
||
ambiguity of the refrain is more evident now: for if the retrograde motion
|
||
merely forms a closed circle, if the augmentations and diminutions are reg-
|
||
ular, proceeding, for example, by doubled or halved values, then this false
|
||
spatiotemporal rigor leaves the exterior aggregate all the fuzzier; that
|
||
aggregate now has only descriptive, indicative, or associative relations
|
||
with the seed. It is "a worksite of inauthentic elements for the formation of
|
||
impure crystals," rather than a pure crystal that harnesses cosmic forces.
|
||
The refrain remains a formula evoking a character or landscape, instead of
|
||
itself constituting a rhythmic character or melodic landscape. The refrain
|
||
has two poles. These poles hinge not only on an intrinsic quality but also on
|
||
a state of force on the part of the listener; thus the little phrase from
|
||
Vinteuil's sonata is associated with Swann's love, the character of Odette,
|
||
and the landscape of the Bois de Boulogne for a long time, until it turns
|
||
back on itself, opens onto itself, revealing until then unheard-of potentiali-
|
||
ties, entering into other connections, setting love adrift in the direction of
|
||
other assemblages. Here, Time is not an a priori form; rather, the refrain is
|
||
the a priori form of time, which in each case fabricates different times
|
||
[temps: also, "meters," "tempos"—Trans.].
|
||
It is odd how music does not eliminate the bad or mediocre refrain, or
|
||
the bad usage of the refrain, but on the contrary carries it along, or uses it as
|
||
a springboard. "Ah, vous dirai-je maman" ("Ah, mamma, now you shall
|
||
know"), "Elle avait une jambe de bois" ("She had a wooden leg"), "Frere
|
||
Jacques." Childhood or bird refrain, folk song, drinking song, Viennese
|
||
waltz, cow bells: music uses anything and sweeps everything away. Not that
|
||
a folk song, bird song, or children's song is reducible to the kind of closed
|
||
and associative formula we just mentioned. Instead, what needs to be
|
||
shown is that a musician requires a first type of refrain, a territorial or
|
||
assemblage refrain, in order to transform it from within, deterritorialize it,
|
||
producing a refrain of the second type as the final end of music: the cosmic
|
||
refrain of a sound machine. Gisele Brelet, discussing Bartok, gives a good
|
||
formulation of the problem of the two types: beginning from popular and
|
||
territorial melodies that are autonomous, self-sufficient, and closed in
|
||
upon themselves, how can one construct a new chromaticism that places
|
||
them in communication, thereby creating "themes'" bringing about a devel-
|
||
350 D 1837: OF THE REFRAIN
|
||
|
||
opment of Form, or rather a becoming of Forces? The problem is a general
|
||
one because in many directions refrains will be planted by a new seed that
|
||
brings back modes, makes those modes communicate, undoes tempera-
|
||
ment, melds major and minor, and cuts the tonal system loose, slipping
|
||
through its net instead of breaking with it.59 We may say long live Chabrier,
|
||
as opposed to Schoenberg, just as Nietzsche said long live Bizet, and for the
|
||
same reasons, with the same technical and musical intent. We go from
|
||
modality to an untempered, widened chromaticism. We do not need to
|
||
suppress tonality, we need to turn it loose. We go from assembled refrains
|
||
(territorial, popular, romantic, etc.) to the great cosmic machined refrain.
|
||
But the labor of creation is already under way in the first type; it is there in
|
||
its entirety. Deformations destined to harness a great force are already
|
||
present in the small-form refrain or rondo. Childhood scenes, children's
|
||
games: the starting point is a childlike refrain, but the child has wings
|
||
already, he becomes celestial. The becoming-child of the musician is cou-
|
||
pled with a becoming-aerial of the child, in a nondecomposable block. The
|
||
memory of an angel, or rather the becoming of a cosmos. Crystal: the
|
||
becoming-bird of Mozart is inseparable from a becoming-initiate of the
|
||
bird, and forms a block with it.60 It is the extremely profound labor dedi-
|
||
cated to the first type of refrain that creates the second type, or the little
|
||
phrase of the Cosmos. In a concerto, Schumann requires all the assem-
|
||
blages of the orchestra to make the cello wander the way a light fades into
|
||
the distance or is extinguished. In Schumann, a whole learned labor, at
|
||
once rythmic, harmonic, and melodic, has this sober and simple result:
|
||
deterritorialize the refrain.^ Produce a deterritorialized refrain as the final
|
||
end of music, release it in the Cosmos—that is more important than build-
|
||
ing a new system. Opening the assemblage onto a cosmic force. In the pas-
|
||
sage from one to the other, from the assemblage of sounds to the Machine
|
||
that renders it sonorous, from the becoming-child of the musician to the
|
||
becoming-cosmic of the child, many dangers crop up: black holes, closures,
|
||
paralysis of the finger and auditory hallucinations, Schumann's madness,
|
||
cosmic force gone bad, a note that pursues you, a sound that transfixes you.
|
||
Yet one was already present in the other; the cosmic force was already pres-
|
||
ent in the material, the great refrain in the little refrains, the great maneu-
|
||
ver in the little maneuver. Except we can never be sure we will be strong
|
||
enough, for we have no system, only lines and movements. Schumann.
|
||
12. 1227: Treatise on Nomadology-
|
||
The War Machine
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Nomad Chariot, Entirely of Wood, Altai, Fifth to Fourth Centuries B.C.
|
||
|
||
|
||
AXIOM I. The war machine is exterior to the State apparatus.
|
||
PROPOSITION I. This exteriority is first attested to in mythology, epic,
|
||
drama, and games.
|
||
Georges Dumezil, in his definitive analyses of Indo-European mythology,
|
||
has shown that political sovereignty, or domination, has two heads: the
|
||
magician-king and the jurist-priest. Rex and flamen, raj and Brahman,
|
||
Romulus and Numa, Varuna and Mitra, the despot and the legislator, the
|
||
binder and the organizer. Undoubtedly, these two poles stand in opposi-
|
||
tion term by term, as the obscure and the clear, the violent and the calm, the
|
||
quick and the weighty, the fearsome and the regulated, the "bond" and the
|
||
"pact," etc.1 But their opposition is only relative; they function as a pair, in
|
||
alternation, as though they expressed a division of the One or constituted
|
||
in themselves a sovereign unity. "At once antithetical and complementary,
|
||
necessary to one another and consequently without hostility, lacking a
|
||
351
|
||
352 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
mythology of conflict: a specification on any one level automatically calls
|
||
forth a homologous specification on another. The two together exhaust the
|
||
field of the function." They are the principal elements of a State apparatus
|
||
that proceeds by a One-Two, distributes binary distinctions, and forms a
|
||
milieu of interiority. It is a double articulation that makes the State appara-
|
||
tus into a stratum.
|
||
It will be noted that war is not contained within this apparatus. Either
|
||
the State has at its disposal a violence that is not channeled through war—
|
||
either it uses police officers and jailers in place of warriors, has no arms and
|
||
no need of them, operates by immediate, magical capture, "seizes" and
|
||
"binds," preventing all combat—or, the State acquires an army, but in a
|
||
way that presupposes a juridical integration of war and the organization of
|
||
a military function.2 As for the war machine in itself, it seems to be irreduc-
|
||
ible to the State apparatus, to be outside its sovereignty and prior to its law:
|
||
it comes from elsewhere. Indra, the warrior god, is in opposition to Varuna
|
||
no less than to Mitral He can no more be reduced to one or the other than
|
||
he can constitute a third of their kind. Rather, he is like a pure and immeas-
|
||
urable multiplicity, the pack, an irruption of the ephemeral and the power
|
||
of metamorphosis. He unties the bond just as he betrays the pact. He brings
|
||
& fur or to bear against sovereignty, a celerity against gravity, secrecy against
|
||
the public, a power (puissance) against sovereignty, a machine against the
|
||
apparatus. He bears witness to another kind of justice, one of incompre-
|
||
hensible cruelty at times, but at others of unequaled pity as well (because he
|
||
unties bonds.. .).4 He bears witness, above all, to other relations with
|
||
women, with animals, because he sees all things in relations of becoming,
|
||
rather than implementing binary distributions between "states": a verita-
|
||
ble becoming-animal of the warrior, a becoming-woman, which lies out-
|
||
side dualities of terms as well as correspondences between relations. In
|
||
every respect, the war machine is of another species, another nature,
|
||
another origin than the State apparatus.
|
||
Let us take a limited example and compare the war machine and the
|
||
State apparatus in the context of the theory of games. Let us take chess and
|
||
Go, from the standpoint of the game pieces, the relations between the
|
||
pieces and the space involved. Chess is a game of State, or of the court: the
|
||
emperor of China played it. Chess pieces are coded; they have an internal
|
||
nature and intrinsic properties from which their movements, situations,
|
||
and confrontations derive. They have qualities; a knight remains a knight,
|
||
a pawn a pawn, a bishop a bishop. Each is like a subject of the statement
|
||
endowed with a relative power, and these relative powers combine in a sub-
|
||
ject of enunciation, that is, the chess player or the game's form of
|
||
interiority. Go pieces, in contrast, are pellets, disks, simple arithmetic
|
||
units, and have only an anonymous, collective, or third-person function:
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 353
|
||
|
||
"It" makes a move. "It" could be a man, a woman, a louse, an elephant. Go
|
||
pieces are elements of a nonsubjectified machine assemblage with no
|
||
intrinsic properties, only situational ones. Thus the relations are very dif-
|
||
ferent in the two cases. Within their milieu of interiority, chess pieces
|
||
entertain biunivocal relations with one another, and with the adversary's
|
||
pieces: their functioning is structural. On the other hand, a Go piece has
|
||
only a milieu of exteriority, or extrinsic relations with nebulas or constella-
|
||
tions, according to which it fulfills functions of insertion or situation, such
|
||
as bordering, encircling, shattering. All by itself, a Go piece can destroy an
|
||
entire constellation synchronically; a chess piece cannot (or can do so
|
||
diachronically only). Chess is indeed a war, but an institutionalized, regu-
|
||
lated, coded war, with a front, a rear, battles. But what is proper to Go is war
|
||
without battle lines, with neither confrontation nor retreat, without battles
|
||
even: pure strategy, whereas chess is a semiology. Finally, the space is not at
|
||
all the same: in chess, it is a question of arranging a closed space for oneself,
|
||
thus of going from one point to another, of occupying the maximum num-
|
||
ber of squares with the minimum number of pieces. In Go, it is a question
|
||
of arraying oneself in an open space, of holding space, of maintaining the
|
||
possibility of springing up at any point: the movement is not from one
|
||
point to another, but becomes perpetual, without aim or destination, with-
|
||
out departure or arrival. The "smooth" space of Go, as against the "stri-
|
||
ated" space of chess. The nomos of Go against the State of chess, nomos
|
||
against polls. The difference is that chess codes and decodes space, whereas
|
||
Go proceeds altogether differently, territorializing or deterritorializing it
|
||
(make the outside a territory in space; consolidate that territory by the con-
|
||
struction of a second, adjacent territory; deterritorialize the enemy by
|
||
shattering his territory from within; deterritorialize oneself by renouncing,
|
||
by going elsewhere . ..). Another justice, another movement, another
|
||
space-time.
|
||
"They come like fate, without reason, consideration, or pretext. . ." "In
|
||
some way that is incomprehensible they have pushed right into the capital.
|
||
At any rate, here they are; it seems that every morning there are more of
|
||
them."5 Luc de Heusch analyzes a Bantu myth that leads us to the same
|
||
schema: Nkongolo, an indigenous emperor and administrator of public
|
||
works, a man of the public and a man of the police, gives his half-sisters to
|
||
the hunter Mbidi, who assists him and then leaves. Mbidi's son, a man of
|
||
secrecy, joins up with his father, only to return from the outside with that
|
||
inconceivable thing, an army. He kills Nkongolo and proceeds to build a
|
||
new State.6 "Between" the magical-despotic State and the juridical State
|
||
containing a military institution, we see the flash of the war machine, arriv-
|
||
ing from without.
|
||
From the standpoint of the State, the originality of the man of war, his
|
||
354 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
eccentricity, necessarily appears in a negative form: stupidity, deformity,
|
||
madness, illegitimacy, usurpation, sin. Dumezil analyzes the three "sins"
|
||
of the warrior in the Indo-European tradition: against the king, against the
|
||
priest, against the laws originating in the State (for example, a sexual trans-
|
||
gression that compromises the distribution of men and women, or even a
|
||
betrayal of the laws of war as instituted by the State).7 The warrior is in the
|
||
position of betraying everything, including the function of the military, or
|
||
of understanding nothing. It happens that historians, both bourgeois and
|
||
Soviet, will follow this negative tradition and explain how Genghis Khan
|
||
understood nothing: he "didn't understand" the phenomenon of the city.
|
||
An easy thing to say. The problem is that the exteriority of the war machine
|
||
in relation to the State apparatus is everywhere apparent but remains diffi-
|
||
cult to conceptualize. It is not enough to affirm that the war machine is
|
||
external to the apparatus. It is necessary to reach the point of conceiving
|
||
the war machine as itself a pure form of exteriority, whereas the State appa-
|
||
ratus constitutes the form of interiority we habitually take as a model, or
|
||
according to which we are in the habit of thinking. What complicates
|
||
everything is that this extrinsic power of the war machine tends, under cer-
|
||
tain circumstances, to become confused with one of the two heads of the
|
||
State apparatus. Sometimes it is confused with the magic violence of the
|
||
State, at other times with the State's military institution. For instance, the
|
||
war machine invents speed and secrecy; but there is all the same a certain
|
||
speed and a certain secrecy that pertain to the State, relatively, secondarily.
|
||
So there is a great danger of identifying the structural relation between the
|
||
two poles of political sovereignty, and the dynamic interrelation of these
|
||
two poles, with the power of war. Dumezil cites the lineage of the Roman
|
||
kings: there is a Romulus-Numa relation that recurs throughout a series,
|
||
with variants and an alternation between these two types of equally legiti-
|
||
mate rulers; but there is also a relation with an "evil king," Tullus Hostilius,
|
||
Tarquinius Superbus, an upsurge of the warrior as a disquieting and illegit-
|
||
imate character.8 Shakespeare's kings could also be invoked: even violence,
|
||
murders, and perversion do not prevent the State lineage from producing
|
||
"good" kings; but a disturbing character like Richard III slips in, announc-
|
||
ing from the outset his intention to reinvent a war machine and impose its
|
||
line (deformed, treacherous and traitorous, he claims a "secret close
|
||
intent"9 totally different from the conquest of State power, and another
|
||
—an other—relation with women). In short, whenever the irruption of war
|
||
power is confused with the line of State domination, everything gets mud-
|
||
dled; the war machine can then be understood only through the categories
|
||
of the negative, since nothing is left that remains outside the State. But,
|
||
returned to its milieu of exteriority, the war machine is seen to be of
|
||
another species, of another nature, of another origin. One would have to
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 355
|
||
|
||
say that it is located between the two heads of the State, between the two
|
||
articulations, and that it is necessary in order to pass from one to the other.
|
||
But "between" the two, in that instant, even ephemeral, if only a flash, it
|
||
proclaims its own irreducibility. The State has no war machine of its own; it
|
||
can only appropriate one in the form of a military institution, one that will
|
||
continually cause it problems. This explains the mistrust States have
|
||
toward their military institutions, in that the military institution inherits
|
||
an extrinsic war machine. Karl von Clausewitz has a general sense of this
|
||
situation when he treats the flow of absolute war as an Idea that States par-
|
||
tially appropriate according to their political needs, and in relation to
|
||
which they are more or less good "conductors."
|
||
Trapped between the two poles of political sovereignty, the man of war
|
||
seems outmoded, condemned, without a future, reduced to his own fury,
|
||
which he turns against himself. The descendants of Hercules, Achilles,
|
||
then Ajax, have enough strength left to proclaim their independence from
|
||
Agamemnon, a man of the old State. But they are powerless when it comes
|
||
to Ulysses, a man of the nascent modern State, the first man of the modern
|
||
State. And it is Ulysses who inherits Achilles' arms, only to convert them to
|
||
other uses, submitting them to the laws of the State—not Ajax, who is con-
|
||
demned by the goddess he defied and against whom he sinned.10 No one
|
||
has portrayed the situation of the man of war, at once eccentric and con-
|
||
demned, better than Kleist. In Penthesilea, Achilles is already separated
|
||
from his power: the war machine has passed over to the Amazons, a State-
|
||
less woman-people whose justice, religion, and loves are organized
|
||
uniquely in a war mode. Descendants of the Scythians, the Amazons spring
|
||
forth like lightning, "between" the two States, the Greek and the Trojan.
|
||
They sweep away everything in their path. Achilles is brought before his
|
||
double, Penthesilea. And in his ambiguous struggle, Achilles is unable to
|
||
prevent himself from marrying the war machine, or from loving Penthe-
|
||
silea, and thus from betraying Agamemnon and Ulysses at the same time.
|
||
Nevertheless, he already belongs enough to the Greek State that Pen-
|
||
thesilea, for her part, cannot enter the passional relation of war with
|
||
him without herself betraying the collective law of her people, the law of the
|
||
pack that prohibits "choosing" the enemy and entering into one-to-one
|
||
relationships or binary distinctions.
|
||
Throughout his work, Kleist celebrates the war machine, setting it
|
||
against the State apparatus in a struggle that is lost from the start. Doubt-
|
||
less Arminius heralds a Germanic war machine that breaks with the imper-
|
||
ial order of alliances and armies, and stands forever opposed to the Roman
|
||
State. But the Prince of Homburg lives only in a dream and stands con-
|
||
demned for having reached victory in disobedience of the law of the State.
|
||
As for Kohlhaas, his war machine can no longer be anything more than
|
||
356 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
banditry. Is it the destiny of the war machine, when the State triumphs, to
|
||
be caught in this alternative: either to be nothing more than the disci-
|
||
plined, military organ of the State apparatus, or to turn against itself, to
|
||
become a double suicide machine for a solitary man and a solitary woman?
|
||
Goethe and Hegel, State thinkers both, see Kleist as a monster, and Kleist
|
||
has lost from the start. Why is it, then, that the most uncanny modernity
|
||
lies with him? It is because the elements of his work are secrecy, speed, and
|
||
affect.'' And in Kleist the secret is no longer a content held within a form of
|
||
interiority; rather, it becomes a form, identified with the form of
|
||
exteriority that is always external to itself. Similarly, feelings become
|
||
uprooted from the interiority of a "subject," to be projected violently out-
|
||
ward into a milieu of pure exteriority that lends them an incredible veloc-
|
||
ity, a catapulting force: love or hate, they are no longer feelings but affects.
|
||
And these affects are so many instances of the becoming-woman, the
|
||
becoming-animal of the warrior (the bear, she-dogs). Affects transpierce
|
||
the body like arrows, they are weapons of war. The deterritorialization
|
||
velocity of affect. Even dreams (Homburg's, Pentheselea's) are externa-
|
||
lized, by a system of relays and plug-ins, extrinsic linkages belonging to the
|
||
war machine. Broken rings. This element of exteriority—which dominates
|
||
everything, which Kleist invents in literature, which he is the first to
|
||
invent—will give time a new rhythm: an endless succession of catatonic
|
||
episodes or fainting spells, and flashes or rushes. Catalonia is: "This affect
|
||
is too strong for me," and a flash is: "The power of this affect sweeps me
|
||
away," so that the Self (Moi) is now nothing more than a character whose
|
||
actions and emotions are desubjectified, perhaps even to the point of
|
||
death. Such is Kleist's personal formula: a succession of flights of madness
|
||
and catatonic freezes in which no subjective interiority remains. There is
|
||
much of the East in Kleist: the Japanese fighter, interminably still, who
|
||
then makes a move too quick to see. The Go player. Many things in modern
|
||
art come from Kleist. Goethe and Hegel are old men next to Kleist. Could it
|
||
be that it is at the moment the war machine ceases to exist, conquered by
|
||
the State, that it displays to the utmost its irreducibility, that it scatters into
|
||
thinking, loving, dying, or creating machines that have at their disposal
|
||
vital or revolutionary powers capable of challenging the conquering State?
|
||
Is the war machine already overtaken, condemned, appropriated as part of
|
||
the same process whereby it takes on new forms, undergoes a metamorpho-
|
||
sis, affirms its irreducibility and exteriority, and deploys that milieu of
|
||
pure exteriority that the occidental man of the State, or the occidental
|
||
thinker, continually reduces to something other than itself?
|
||
PROBLEM I. Is there a way of warding off the formation of a State appara-
|
||
tus (or its equivalents in a group)?
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 357
|
||
|
||
PROPOSITION II. The exteriority of the war machine is also attested to by
|
||
ethnology (a tribute to the memory of Pierre Clastres).
|
||
Primitive, segmentary societies have often been defined as societies
|
||
without a State, in other words, societies in which distinct organs of power
|
||
do not appear. But the conclusion has been that these societies did not
|
||
reach the degree of economic development, or the level of political differ-
|
||
entiation, that would make the formation of the State apparatus both
|
||
possible and inevitable: the implication is that primitive people "don't
|
||
understand" so complex an apparatus. The prime interest in Pierre
|
||
Clastres's theories is that they break with this evolutionist postulate. Not
|
||
only does he doubt that the State is the product of an ascribable economic
|
||
development, but he asks if it is not a potential concern of primitive socie-
|
||
ties to ward off or avert that monster they supposedly do not understand.
|
||
Warding off the formation of a State apparatus, making such a formation
|
||
impossible, would be the objective of a certain number of primitive social
|
||
mechanisms, even if they are not consciously understood as such. To be
|
||
sure, primitive societies have chiefs. But the State is not defined by the exis-
|
||
tence of chiefs; it is defined by the perpetuation or conservation of organs
|
||
of power. The concern of the State is to conserve. Special institutions are
|
||
thus necessary to enable a chief to become a man of State, but diffuse, col-
|
||
lective mechanisms are just as necessary to prevent a chief from becoming
|
||
one. Mechanisms for warding off, preventive mechanisms, are a part of
|
||
chieftainship and keep an apparatus distinct from the social body from
|
||
crystallizing. Clastres describes the situation of the chief, who has no insti-
|
||
tuted weapon other than his prestige, no other means of persuasion, no
|
||
other rule than his sense of the group's desires. The chief is more like a
|
||
leader or a star than a man of power and is always in danger of being disa-
|
||
vowed, abandoned by his people. But Clastres goes further, identifying war
|
||
in primitive societies as the surest mechanism directed against the forma-
|
||
tion of the State: war maintains the dispersal and segmentarity of groups,
|
||
and the warrior himself is caught in a process of accumulating exploits
|
||
leading him to solitude and a prestigious but powerless death.12 Clastres
|
||
can thus invoke natural Law while reversing its principal proposition: just
|
||
as Hobbes saw clearly that the State was against war, so war is against the
|
||
State, and makes it impossible. It should not be concluded that war is a
|
||
state of nature, but rather that it is the mode of a social state that wards off
|
||
and prevents the State. Primitive war does not produce the State any more
|
||
than it derives from it. And it is no better explained by exchange than by
|
||
the State: far from deriving from exchange, even as a sanction for its fail-
|
||
ure, war is what limits exchanges, maintains them in the framework of
|
||
358 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
"alliances"; it is what prevents them from becoming a State factor, from
|
||
fusing groups.
|
||
The importance of this thesis is first of all to draw attention to collective
|
||
mechanisms of inhibition. These mechanisms may be subtle, and function
|
||
as micromechanisms. This is easily seen in certain band or pack phenom-
|
||
ena. For example, in the case of gangs of street children in Bogota, Jacques
|
||
Meunier cites three ways in which the leader is prevented from acquiring
|
||
stable power: the members of the band meet and undertake their theft
|
||
activity in common, with collective sharing of the loot, but they disperse to
|
||
eat or sleep separately; also, and especially, each member of the band is
|
||
paired off with one, two, or three other members, so if he has a disagree-
|
||
ment with the leader, he will not leave alone but will take along his allies,
|
||
whose combined departure will threaten to break up the entire gang;
|
||
finally, there is a diffuse age limit, and at about age fifteen a member is
|
||
inevitably induced to quit the gang.13 These mechanisms cannot be under-
|
||
stood without renouncing the evolutionist vision that sees bands or packs
|
||
as a rudimentary, less organized, social form. Even in bands of animals,
|
||
leadership is a complex mechanism that does not act to promote the
|
||
strongest but rather inhibits the installation of stable powers, in favor of a
|
||
fabric of immanent relations.14 One could just as easily compare the form
|
||
"high-society life" to the form "sociability" among the most highly evolved
|
||
men and women: high-society groups are similar to gangs and operate by
|
||
the diffusion of prestige rather than by reference to centers of power, as in
|
||
social groupings (Proust clearly showed this noncorrespondence of high-
|
||
society values and social values). Eugene Sue, a man of high society and a
|
||
dandy, whom legitimists reproached for frequenting the Orleans family,
|
||
used to say: "I'm not on the side of the family, I side with the pack." Packs,
|
||
bands, are groups of the rhizome type, as opposed to the arborescent type
|
||
that centers around organs of power. That is why bands in general, even
|
||
those engaged in banditry or high-society life, are metamorphoses of a war
|
||
machine formally distinct from all State apparatuses or their equivalents,
|
||
which are instead what structure centralized societies. We certainly would
|
||
not say that discipline is what defines a war machine: discipline is the char-
|
||
acteristic required of armies after the State has appropriated them. The
|
||
war machine answers to other rules. We are not saying that they are better,
|
||
of course, only that they animate a fundamental indiscipline of the warrior,
|
||
a questioning of hierarchy, perpetual blackmail by abandonment or
|
||
betrayal, and a very volatile sense of honor, all of which, once again,
|
||
impedes the formation of the State.
|
||
But why does this argument fail to convince us entirely? We follow
|
||
Clastres when he demonstrates that the State is explained neither by a
|
||
development of productive forces nor by a differentiation of political
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 359
|
||
|
||
forces. It is the State, on the contrary, that makes possible the undertaking
|
||
of large-scale projects, the constitution of surpluses, and the organization
|
||
of the corresponding public functions. The State is what makes the distinc-
|
||
tion between governors and governed possible. We do not see how the State
|
||
can be explained by what it presupposes, even with recourse to dialectics.
|
||
The State seems to rise up in a single stroke, in an imperial form, and does
|
||
not depend on progressive factors. Its on-the-spot emergence is like a
|
||
stroke of genius, the birth of Athena. We also follow Clastres when he shows
|
||
that the war machine is directed against the State, either against potential
|
||
States whose formation it wards off in advance, or against actual States
|
||
whose destruction it purposes. No doubt the war machine is realized more
|
||
completely in the "barbaric" assemblages of nomadic warriors than in the
|
||
"savage" assemblages of primitive societies. In any case, it is out of the
|
||
question that the State could be the result of a war in which the conquerors
|
||
imposed, by the very fact of their victory, a new law on the vanquished,
|
||
because the organization of the war machine is directed against the State-
|
||
form, actual or virtual. The State is no better accounted for as a result of
|
||
war than by a progression of economic or political forces. This is where
|
||
Clastres locates the break: between "primitive" counter-State societies and
|
||
"monstrous" State societies whose formation it is no longer possible to
|
||
explain. Clastres is fascinated by the problem of "voluntary servitude," in
|
||
the manner of La Boetie: In what way did people want or desire servitude,
|
||
which most certainly did not come to them as the outcome of an involun-
|
||
tary and unfortunate war? They did, after all, have counter-State mecha-
|
||
nisms at their disposal: So how and why the State? Why did the State
|
||
triumph? The more deeply Clastres delved into the problem, the more he
|
||
seemed to deprive himself of the means of resolving it.'5 He tended to make
|
||
primitive societies hypostases, self-sufficient entities (he insisted heavily
|
||
on this point). He made their formal exteriority into a real independence.
|
||
Thus he remained an evolutionist, and posited a state of nature. Only this
|
||
state of nature was, according to him, a fully social reality instead of a pure
|
||
concept, and the evolution was a sudden mutation instead of a develop-
|
||
ment. For on the one hand, the State rises up in a single stroke, fully
|
||
formed; on the other, the counter-State societies use very specific mecha-
|
||
nisms to ward it off, to prevent it from arising. We believe that these two
|
||
propositions are valid but that their interlinkage is flawed. There is an old
|
||
scenario: "from clans to empires," or "from bands to kingdoms." But noth-
|
||
ing says that this constitutes an evolution, since bands and clans are no less
|
||
organized than empire-kingdoms. We will never leave the evolution
|
||
hypothesis behind by creating a break between the two terms, that is, by
|
||
endowing bands with self-sufficiency and the State with an emergence all
|
||
the more miraculous and monstrous.
|
||
360 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
We are compelled to say that there has always been a State, quite perfect,
|
||
quite complete. The more discoveries archaeologists make, the more
|
||
empires they uncover. The hypothesis of the Urstaat seems to be verified:
|
||
"The State clearly dates back to the most remote ages of humanity." It is
|
||
hard to imagine primitive societies that would not have been in contact
|
||
with imperial States, at the periphery or in poorly controlled areas. But of
|
||
greater importance is the inverse hypothesis: that the State itself has always
|
||
been in a relation with an outside and is inconceivable independent of that
|
||
relationship. The law of the State is not the law of All or Nothing (State
|
||
societies or counter-State societies) but that of interior and exterior. The
|
||
State is sovereignty. But sovereignty only reigns over what it is capable of
|
||
internalizing, of appropriating locally. Not only is there no universal State,
|
||
but the outside of States cannot be reduced to "foreign policy," that is, to a
|
||
set of relations among States. The outside appears simultaneously in two
|
||
directions: huge worldwide machines branched out over the entire
|
||
ecumenon at a given moment, which enjoy a large measure of autonomy in
|
||
relation to the States (for example, commercial organization of the "multi-
|
||
national" type, or industrial complexes, or even religious formations like
|
||
Christianity, Islam, certain prophetic or messianic movements, etc.); but
|
||
also the local mechanisms of bands, margins, minorities, which continue
|
||
to affirm the rights of segmentary societies in opposition to the organs of
|
||
State power. The modern world can provide us today with particularly
|
||
well developed images of these two directions: worldwide ecumenical
|
||
machines, but also a neoprimitivism, a new tribal society as described by
|
||
Marshall McLuhan. These directions are equally present in all social
|
||
fields, in all periods. It even happens that they partially merge. For exam-
|
||
ple, a commercial organization is also a band of pillage, or piracy, for part
|
||
of its course and in many of its activities; or it is in bands that a religious
|
||
formation begins to operate. What becomes clear is that bands, no less than
|
||
worldwide organizations, imply a form irreducible to the State and that
|
||
this form of exteriority necessarily presents itself as a diffuse and
|
||
polymorphous war machine. It is a nomos very different from the "law."
|
||
The State-form, as a form of interiority, has a tendency to reproduce itself,
|
||
remaining identical to itself across its variations and easily recognizable
|
||
within the limits of its poles, always seeking public recognition (there is no
|
||
masked State). But the war machine's form of exteriority is such that it
|
||
exists only in its own metamorphoses; it exists in an industrial innovation
|
||
as well as in a technological invention, in a commercial circuit as well as in a
|
||
religious creation, in all flows and currents that only secondarily allow
|
||
themselves to be appropriated by the State. It is in terms not of indepen-
|
||
dence, but of coexistence and competition in a perpetual field of interac-
|
||
tion, that we must conceive of exteriority and interiority, war machines of
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 361
|
||
|
||
metamorphosis and State apparatuses of identity, bands and kingdoms,
|
||
megamachines and empires. The same field circumscribes its interiority in
|
||
States, but describes its exteriority in what escapes States or stands against
|
||
States.
|
||
PROPOSITION III. The exteriority of the war ma chine is also attested to by
|
||
epistemology, which intimates the existence and perpetuation of a
|
||
"nomad"or "minor science."
|
||
There is a kind of science, or treatment of science, that seems very dif-
|
||
ficult to classify, whose history is even difficult to follow. What we are
|
||
referring to are not "technologies" in the usual sense of the term. But nei-
|
||
ther are they "sciences" in the royal or legal sense established by history.
|
||
According to a recent book by Michel Serres, both the atomic physics of
|
||
Democritus and Lucretius and the geometry of Archimedes are marked
|
||
by it.16 The characteristics of this kind of eccentric science would seem to
|
||
be the following:
|
||
1. First of all, it uses a hydraulic model, rather than being a theory of
|
||
solids treating fluids as a special case; ancient atomism is inseparable from
|
||
flows, and flux is reality itself, or consistency.
|
||
2. The model in question is one of becoming and heterogeneity, as
|
||
opposed to the stable, the eternal, the identical, the constant. It is a "para-
|
||
dox" to make becoming itself a model, and no longer a secondary charac-
|
||
teristic, a copy; in the Timaeus, Plato raises this possibility, but only in
|
||
order to exclude it and conjure it away in the name of royal science. By con-
|
||
trast, in atomism, just such a model of heterogeneity, and of passage or
|
||
becoming in the heterogeneous, is furnished by the famed declination of
|
||
the atom. The clinamen, as the minimum angle, has meaning only between
|
||
a straight line and a curve, the curve and its tangent, and constitutes the
|
||
original curvature of the movement of the atom. The clinamen is the small-
|
||
est angle by which an atom deviates from a straight path.17 It is a passage to
|
||
the limit, an exhaustion, a paradoxical "exhaustive" model. The same
|
||
applies to Archimedean geometry, in which the straight line, defined as
|
||
"the shortest path between two points," is just a way of defining the length
|
||
of a curve in a predifferential calculus.
|
||
3. One no longer goes from the straight line to its parallels, in a lamellar
|
||
or laminar flow,18 but from a curvilinear declination to the formation of
|
||
spirals and vortices on an inclined plane: the greatest slope for the smallest
|
||
angle. From turba to turbo: in other words, from bands or packs of atoms to
|
||
the great vortical organizations.19 The model is a vortical one; it operates in
|
||
an open space throughout which things-flows are distributed, rather than
|
||
plotting out a closed space for linear and solid things. It is the difference
|
||
between a smooth (vectorial, projective, or topological) space and a striated
|
||
362 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
(metric) space: in the first case "space is occupied without being counted,"
|
||
and in the second case "space is counted in order to be occupied."20
|
||
4. Finally, the model is problematic, rather than theorematic: figures
|
||
are considered only from the viewpoint of the affections that befall them:
|
||
sections, ablations, adjunctions, projections. One does not go by specific
|
||
differences from a genus to its species, or by deduction from a stable
|
||
essence to the properties deriving from it, but rather from a problem to
|
||
the accidents that condition and resolve it. This involves all kinds of
|
||
deformations, transmutations, passages to the limit, operations in which
|
||
each figure designates an "event" much more than an essence; the square
|
||
no longer exists independently of a quadrature, the cube of a cubature,
|
||
the straight line of a rectification. Whereas the theorem belongs to the
|
||
rational order, the problem is affective and is inseparable from the meta-
|
||
morphoses, generations, and creations within science itself. Despite what
|
||
Gabriel Marcel may say, the problem is not an "obstacle"; it is the surpass-
|
||
ing of the obstacle, a pro-jection, in other words, a war machine. All of this
|
||
movement is what royal science is striving to limit when it reduces as
|
||
much as possible the range of the "problem-element" and subordinates it
|
||
to the "theorem-element."21
|
||
This Archimedean science, or this conception of science, is bound up in
|
||
an essential way with the war machine: \heproblemata are the war machine
|
||
itself and are inseparable from inclined planes, passages to the limit, vorti-
|
||
ces, and projections. It would seem that the war machine is projected into
|
||
an abstract knowledge formally different from the one that doubles the
|
||
State apparatus. It would seem that a whole nomad science develops
|
||
eccentrically, one that is very different from the royal or imperial sciences.
|
||
Furthermore, this nomad science is continually "barred," inhibited, or
|
||
banned by the demands and conditions of State science. Archimedes, van-
|
||
quished by the Roman State, becomes a symbol.22 The fact is that the two
|
||
kinds of science have different modes of formalization, and State science
|
||
continually imposes its form of sovereignty on the inventions of nomad
|
||
science. State science retains of nomad science only what it can appropri-
|
||
ate; it turns the rest into a set of strictly limited formulas without any real
|
||
scientific status, or else simply represses and bans it. It is as if the "savants"
|
||
of nomad science were caught between a rock and a hard place, between the
|
||
war machine that nourishes and inspires them and the State that imposes
|
||
upon them an order of reasons. The figure of the engineer (in particular the
|
||
military engineer), with all its ambivalence, is illustrative of this situation.
|
||
Most significant are perhaps borderline phenomena in which nomad sci-
|
||
ence exerts pressure on State science, and, conversely, State science appro-
|
||
priates and transforms the elements of nomad science. This is true of the
|
||
art of encampments, "castrametation," which has always mobilized pro-
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 363
|
||
|
||
jections and inclined planes: the State does not appropriate this dimension
|
||
of the war machine without submitting it to civil and metric rules that
|
||
strictly limit, control, localize nomad science, and without keeping it from
|
||
having repercussions throughout the social field (in this respect, Vauban is
|
||
like a repeat of Archimedes, and suffers an analogous defeat). It is true of
|
||
descriptive and projective geometry, which royal science would like to turn
|
||
into a mere practical dependency of analytic, or so-called higher, geometry
|
||
(thus the ambiguous situation of Monge and Poncelet as "savants").23 It is
|
||
also true of differential calculus. For a long time, it had only parascientific
|
||
status and was labeled a "Gothic hypothesis"; royal science only accorded
|
||
it the value of a convenient convention or a well-founded fiction. The great
|
||
State mathematicians did their best to improve its status, but precisely on
|
||
the condition that all the dynamic, nomadic notions—such as becoming,
|
||
heterogeneity, infinitesimal, passage to the limit, continuous variation
|
||
—be eliminated and civil, static, and ordinal rules be imposed upon it
|
||
(Carnot's ambiguous position in this respect). Finally, it is true of the
|
||
hydraulic model, for it is certain that the State itself needs a hydraulic sci-
|
||
ence (there is no going back on Wittfogel's theses on the importance of
|
||
large-scale waterworks for an empire). But it needs it in a very different
|
||
form, because the State needs to subordinate hydraulic force to conduits,
|
||
pipes, embankments, which prevent turbulence, which constrain move-
|
||
ment to go from one point to another, and space itself to be striated and
|
||
measured, which makes the fluid depend on the solid, and flows proceed
|
||
by parallel, laminar layers. The hydraulic model of nomad science and the
|
||
war machine, on the other hand, consists in being distributed by turbu-
|
||
lence across a smooth space, in producing a movement that holds space
|
||
and simultaneously affects all of its points, instead of being held by space in
|
||
a local movement from one specified point to another.24 Democritus,
|
||
Menaechmus, Archimedes, Vauban, Desargues, Bernoulli, Monge,
|
||
Carnot, Poncelet, Perronet, etc.: in each case a monograph would be neces-
|
||
sary to take into account the special situation of these savants whom State
|
||
science used only after restraining or disciplining them, after repressing
|
||
their social or political conceptions.
|
||
The sea as a smooth space is a specific problem of the war machine. As
|
||
Virilio shows, it is at sea that the problem of the fleet in being is posed, in
|
||
other words, the task of occupying an open space with a vortical movement
|
||
that can rise up at any point. In this respect, the recent studies on rhythm,
|
||
on the origin of that notion, do not seem entirely convincing. For we are
|
||
told that rhythm has nothing to do with the movement of waves but rather
|
||
that it designates "form" in general, and more specifically the form of a
|
||
"measured, cadenced" movement.25 However, rhythm is never the same as
|
||
measure. And though the atomist Democritus is one of the authors who
|
||
364 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
speak of rhythm in the sense of form, it should be borne in mind that he
|
||
does so under very precise conditions of fluctuation and that the forms
|
||
made by atoms are primarily large, nonmetric aggregates, smooth spaces
|
||
such as the air, the sea, or even the earth (magnae res). There is indeed such
|
||
a thing as measured, cadenced rhythm, relating to the coursing of a river
|
||
between its banks or to the form of a striated space; but there is also a
|
||
rhythm without measure, which relates to the upswell of a flow, in other
|
||
words, to the manner in which a fluid occupies a smooth space.
|
||
This opposition, or rather this tension-limit between the two kinds of
|
||
science—nomad, war machine science and royal, State science—reap-
|
||
pears at different moments, on different levels. The work of Anne Querrien
|
||
enables us to identify two of these moments; one is the construction of
|
||
Gothic cathedrals in the twelfth century, the other the construction of
|
||
bridges in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.26 Gothic architecture is
|
||
indeed inseparable from a will to build churches longer and taller than the
|
||
Romanesque churches. Ever farther, ever higher . . . But this difference is
|
||
not simply quantitative; it marks a qualitative change: the static relation,
|
||
form-matter, tends to fade into the background in favor of a dynamic rela-
|
||
tion, material-forces. It is the cutting of the stone that turns it into material
|
||
capable of holding and coordinating forces of thrust, and of constructing
|
||
ever higher and longer vaults. The vault is no longer a form but the line of
|
||
continuous variation of the stones. It is as if Gothic conquered a smooth
|
||
space, while Romanesque remained partially within a striated space (in
|
||
which the vault depends on the juxtaposition of parallel pillars). But stone
|
||
cutting is inseparable from, on the one hand, a plane of projection at
|
||
ground level, which functions as a plane limit, and, on the other hand, a
|
||
series of successive approximations (squaring), or placings-in-variation of
|
||
voluminous stones. Of course, one appealed to the theorematic science of
|
||
Euclid in order to find a foundation for the enterprise: mathematical fig-
|
||
ures and equations were thought to be the intelligible form capable of orga-
|
||
nizing surfaces and volumes. But according to the legend, Bernard de
|
||
Clairvaux quickly abandoned the effort as too "difficult," appealing to the
|
||
specificity of an operative, Archimedean geometry, a projective and
|
||
descriptive geometry defined as a minor science, more a mathegraphy than
|
||
a matheology. His journeyman, the monk-mason Garin de Troyes, speaks
|
||
of an operative logic of movement enabling the "initiate" to draw, then hew
|
||
the volumes "in penetration in space," to make it so that "the cutting line
|
||
propels the equation" (le trait pousse le chiffre).21 One does not represent,
|
||
one engenders and traverses. This science is characterized less by the
|
||
absence of equations than by the very different role they play: instead of
|
||
being good forms absolutely that organize matter, they are "generated" as
|
||
"forces of thrust" (poussees) by the material, in a qualitative calculus of the
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 365
|
||
|
||
optimum. This whole current of Archimedean geometry was taken to its
|
||
highest expression, but was also brought to a temporary standstill, by the
|
||
remarkable seventeenth-century mathematician Desargues. Like most of
|
||
his kind, Desargues wrote little; he nevertheless exerted a great influence
|
||
through his actions and left outlines, rough drafts, and projects, all cen-
|
||
tered on problem-events: "Lamentations," "draft project for the cutting of
|
||
stones," "draft project for grappling with the events of the encounters of a
|
||
cone and a plane,. .. Desargues, however, was condemned by the
|
||
parlement of Paris, opposed by the king's secretary; his practices of per-
|
||
spective were banned.28 Royal, or State, science only tolerates and appro-
|
||
priates stone cutting by means of templates (the opposite of squaring),
|
||
under conditions that restore the primacy of the fixed model of form,
|
||
mathematical figures, and measurement. Royal science only tolerates and
|
||
appropriates perspective if it is static, subjected to a central black hole
|
||
divesting it of its heuristic and ambulatory capacities. But the adventure,
|
||
or event, of Desargues is the same one that had already occurred among the
|
||
Gothic "journeymen" on a collective level. For not only did the Church, in
|
||
its imperial form, feel the need to strictly control the movement of this
|
||
nomad science (it entrusted the Templars with the responsibility of deter-
|
||
mining its locations and objects, governing the work sites, and regulating
|
||
construction), but the secular State, in its royal form, turned against the
|
||
Templars themselves, banning the guilds for a number of reasons, at least
|
||
one of which was the prohibition of this operative or minor geometry.
|
||
Is Anne Querrien right to find yet another echo of the same story in the
|
||
case of bridges in the eighteenth century? Doubtless, the conditions were
|
||
very different, for the division of labor according to State norms was by
|
||
then an accomplished fact. But the fact remains that in the government
|
||
agency in charge of bridges and roadways, roadways were under a well-
|
||
centralized administration while bridges were still the object of active,
|
||
dynamic, and collective experimentation. Trudaine organized unusual,
|
||
open "general assemblies" in his home. Perronet took as his inspiration a
|
||
supple model originating in the Orient: The bridge should not choke or
|
||
obstruct the river. To the heaviness of the bridge, to the striated space of
|
||
thick and regular piles, he opposed a thinning and discontinuity of the
|
||
piles, surbase, and vault, a lightness and continuous variation of the whole.
|
||
But his attempt soon ran up against principled opposition; the State, in
|
||
naming Perronet director of the school, followed a frequently used proce-
|
||
dure that inhibited experimentation more than crowning its achieve-
|
||
ments. The whole history of the Ecole des Fonts et Chaussees (School of
|
||
Bridges and Roadways) illustrates how this old, plebeian "corps" was sub-
|
||
ordinated to the Ecole des Mines, the Ecole des Travaux Publics, and the
|
||
Ecole Polytechnique, at the same time as its activities were increasingly
|
||
366 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
normalized.29 We thus come to the question, What is a collective body!
|
||
Undoubtedly, the great collective bodies of a State are differentiated and
|
||
hierarchical organisms that on the one hand enjoy a monopoly over a
|
||
power or function and on the other hand send out local representatives.
|
||
They have a special relation to families, because they link the family model
|
||
to the State model at both ends and regard themselves as "great families" of
|
||
functionaries, clerks, intendants, or farmers. Yet it seems that in many of
|
||
these collective bodies there is something else at work that does not fit into
|
||
this schema. It is not just their obstinate defense of their privileges. It is also
|
||
their aptitude—even caricatural or seriously deformed—to constitute
|
||
themselves as a war machine, following other models, another dynamism,
|
||
a nomadic ambition, over against the State. As an example, there is the
|
||
very old problem of the lobby, a group with fluid contours, whose position
|
||
is very ambiguous in relation to the State it wishes to "influence" and the
|
||
war machine it wishes to promote, to whatever ends.30
|
||
A body (corps) is not reducible to an organism, any more than esprit de
|
||
corps is reducible to the soul of an organism. Spirit is not better, but it is
|
||
volatile, whereas the soul is weighted, a center of gravity. Must we invoke a
|
||
military origin of the collective body and esprit de corps? "Military" is not
|
||
the part that counts, but rather the distant nomadic origin. Ibn Khaldun
|
||
defines the nomad war machine by: families or lineages PLUS esprit de
|
||
corps. The war machine entertains a relation to families that is very differ-
|
||
ent from its relation to the State. In the war machine, the family is a band
|
||
vector instead of a fundamental cell; a genealogy is transferred from one
|
||
family to another according to the aptitude of a given family at a given time
|
||
to realize the maximum of "agnatic solidarity." Here, it is not the public
|
||
eminence of a family that determines its place in a State organism but the
|
||
reverse; it is the secret power (puissance), or strength of solidarity, and the
|
||
corresponding genealogical mobility that determine its eminence in a war
|
||
body.31 This has to do neither with the monopoly of an organic power
|
||
(pouvoir) nor with local representation, but is related to the potential (puis-
|
||
sance) of a vortical body in a nomad space. Of course, the great bodies of a
|
||
modern State can hardly be thought of as Arab tribes. What we wish to say,
|
||
rather, is that collective bodies always have fringes or minorities that recon-
|
||
stitute equivalents of the war machine—in sometimes quite unforeseen
|
||
forms—in specific assemblages such as building bridges or cathedrals or
|
||
rendering judgments or making music or instituting a science, a technology
|
||
. . . A collective body of captains asserts its demands through the organiza-
|
||
tion of the officers and the organism of the superior officers. There are
|
||
always periods when the State as organism has problems with its own col-
|
||
lective bodies, when these bodies, claiming certain privileges, are forced in
|
||
spite of themselves to open onto something that exceeds them, a short revo-
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 367
|
||
|
||
lutionary instant, an experimental surge. A confused situation: each time it
|
||
occurs, it is necessary to analyze tendencies and poles, the nature of the
|
||
movements. All of a sudden, it is as if the collective body of the notary pub-
|
||
lics were advancing like Arabs or Indians, then regrouping and reorganiz-
|
||
ing: a comic opera where you never know what is going to happen next
|
||
(even the cry "The police are with us!" is sometimes heard).
|
||
Husserl speaks of a protogeometry that addresses vague, in other words,
|
||
vagabond or nomadic, morphological essences. These essences are distinct
|
||
from sensible things, as well as from ideal, royal, or imperial essences.
|
||
Protogeometry, the science dealing with them, is itself vague, in the etymo-
|
||
logical sense of "vagabond": it is neither inexact like sensible things nor
|
||
exact like ideal essences, but anexactyet rigorous ("essentially and not acci-
|
||
dentally inexact"). The circle is an organic, ideal, fixed essence, but round-
|
||
ness is a vague and fluent essence, distinct both from the circle and things
|
||
that are round (a vase, a wheel, the sun). A theorematic figure is a fixed
|
||
essence, but its transformations, distortions, ablations, and augmenta-
|
||
tions, all of its variations, form problematic figures that are vague yet rigor-
|
||
ous, "lens-shaped," "umbelliform," or "indented." It could be said that
|
||
vague essences extract from things a determination that is more than
|
||
thinghood (chos'eit'e), which is that of corporeality (corporeite), and which
|
||
perhaps even implies an esprit de corps.32 But why does Husserl see this as a
|
||
protogeometry, a kind of halfway point and not a pure science? Why does
|
||
he make pure essences dependent upon a passage to the limit, when any
|
||
passage to the limit belongs as such to the vague? What we have, rather, are
|
||
two formally different conceptions of science, and, ontologically, a single
|
||
field of interaction in which royal science continually appropriates the
|
||
contents of vague or nomad science while nomad science continually cuts
|
||
the contents of royal science loose. At the limit, all that counts is the con-
|
||
stantly shifting borderline. In Husserl (and also in Kant, though in the
|
||
opposite direction: roundness as the "schema" of the circle), we find a very
|
||
accurate appreciation of the irreducibility of nomad science, but simulta-
|
||
neously the concern of a man of the State, or one who sides with the State,
|
||
to maintain a legislative and constituent primacy for royal science. When-
|
||
ever this primacy is taken for granted, nomad science is portrayed as a
|
||
prescientific or parascientific or subscientific agency. And most impor-
|
||
tant, it becomes impossible to understand the relations between science
|
||
and technology, science and practice, because nomad science is not a sim-
|
||
ple technology or practice, but a scientific field in which the problem of
|
||
these relations is brought out and resolved in an entirely different way than
|
||
from the point of view of royal science. The State is perpetually producing
|
||
and reproducing ideal circles, but a war machine is necessary to make
|
||
something round. Thus the specific characteristics of nomad science are
|
||
368 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
what need to be determined in order to understand both the repression it
|
||
encounters and the interaction "containing" it.
|
||
Nomad science does not have the same relation to work as royal science.
|
||
Not that the division of labor in nomad science is any less thorough; it is
|
||
different. We know of the problems States have always had with journey-
|
||
men's associations, or compagnonnages, the nomadic or itinerant bodies
|
||
of the type formed by masons, carpenters, smiths, etc. Settling, seden-
|
||
tarizing labor power, regulating the movement of the flow of labor, as-
|
||
signing it channels and conduits, forming corporations in the sense of
|
||
organisms, and, for the rest, relying on forced manpower recruited on the
|
||
spot (corvee) or among indigents (charity workshops)—this has always
|
||
been one of the principal affairs of the State, which undertook to conquer
|
||
both a band vagabondage and a body nomadism. Let us return to the exam-
|
||
ple of Gothic architecture for a reminder of how extensively the journey-
|
||
men traveled, building cathedrals near and far, scattering construction
|
||
sites across the land, drawing on an active and passive power (mobility and
|
||
the strike) that was far from convenient for the State. The State's response
|
||
was to take over management of the construction sites, merging all the divi-
|
||
sions of labor in the supreme distinction between the intellectual and the
|
||
manual, the theoretical and the practical, modeled upon the difference
|
||
between "governors" and "governed." In the nomad sciences, as in the
|
||
royal sciences, we find the existence of a "plane," but not at all in the same
|
||
way. The ground-level plane of the Gothic journeyman is opposed to the
|
||
metric plane of the architect, which is on paper and off site. The plane of
|
||
consistency or composition is opposed to another plane, that of organiza-
|
||
tion or formation. Stone cutting by squaring is opposed to stone cutting
|
||
using templates, which implies the erection of a model for reproduction. It
|
||
can be said not only that there is no longer a need for skilled or qualified
|
||
labor, but also that there is a need for unskilled or unqualified labor, for a
|
||
dequalification of labor. The State does not give power (pouvoir) to the
|
||
intellectuals or conceptual innovators; on the contrary, it makes them a
|
||
strictly dependent organ with an autonomy that is only imagined yet is suf-
|
||
ficient to divest those whose job it becomes simply to reproduce or imple-
|
||
ment of all of their power (puissance). This does not shield the State from
|
||
more trouble, this time with the body of intellectuals it itself engendered,
|
||
but which asserts new nomadic and political claims. In any case, if the State
|
||
always finds it necessary to repress the nomad and minor sciences, if it
|
||
opposes vague essences and the operative geometry of the trait, it does so
|
||
not because the content of these sciences is inexact or imperfect, or because
|
||
of their magic or initiatory character, but because they imply a division of
|
||
labor opposed to the norms of the State. The difference is not extrinsic: the
|
||
way in which a science, or a conception of science, participates in the
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 369
|
||
|
||
organization of the social field, and in particular induces a division of
|
||
labor, is part of that science itself. Royal science is inseparable from a
|
||
"hylomorphic" model implying both a form that organizes matter and a
|
||
matter prepared for the form; it has often been shown that this schema
|
||
derives less from technology or life than from a society divided into gover-
|
||
nors and governed, and later, intellectuals and manual laborers. What
|
||
characterizes it is that all matter is assigned to content, while all form
|
||
passes into expression. It seems that nomad science is more immediately in
|
||
tune with the connection between content and expression in themselves,
|
||
each of these two terms encompassing both form and matter. Thus matter,
|
||
in nomad science, is never prepared and therefore homogenized matter,
|
||
but is essentially laden with singularities (which constitute a form of con-
|
||
tent). And neither is expression formal; it is inseparable from pertinent
|
||
traits (which constitute a matter of expression). This is an entirely different
|
||
schema, as we shall see. We can get a preliminary idea of this situation by
|
||
recalling the most general characteristic of nomad art, in which a dynamic
|
||
connection between support and ornament replaces the matter-form dia-
|
||
lectic. From the point of view of nomad science, which presents itself as an
|
||
art as much as a technique, the division of labor fully exists, but it does not
|
||
employ the form-matter duality (even in the case of biunivocal corre-
|
||
spondences). Rather, it follows the connections between singularities of
|
||
matter and traits of expression, and lodges on the level of these connec-
|
||
tions, whether they be natural or forced.33 This is another organization of
|
||
work and of the social field through work.
|
||
It is instructive to contrast two models of science, after the manner of
|
||
Plato in the Timaeus.34 One could be called Compars and the other
|
||
Dispars. The compars is the legal or legalist model employed by royal sci-
|
||
ence. The search for laws consists in extracting constants, even if those con-
|
||
stants are only relations between variables (equations). An invariable form
|
||
for variables, a variable matter of the invariant: such is the foundation of
|
||
the hylomorphic schema. But for the dispars as an element of nomad sci-
|
||
ence the relevant distinction is material-forces rather than matter-form.
|
||
Here, it is not exactly a question of extracting constants from variables but
|
||
of placing the variables themselves in a state of continuous variation. If
|
||
there are still equations, they are adequations, inequations, differential
|
||
equations irreducible to the algebraic form and inseparable from a sensible
|
||
intuition of variation. They seize or determine singularities in the matter,
|
||
instead of constituting a general form. They effect individuations through
|
||
events or haecceities, not through the "object" as a compound of matter
|
||
and form; vague essences are nothing other than haecceities. In all these
|
||
respects, there is an opposition between the logos and the nomos, the law
|
||
and the nomos, prompting the comment that the law still "savors of
|
||
370 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
morality."35 This does not mean, however, that the legal model knows noth-
|
||
ing offerees, the play of forces. That it does is evident in the homogeneous
|
||
space corresponding to the compars. Homogeneous space is in no way a
|
||
smooth space; on the contrary, it is the form of striated space. The space of
|
||
pillars. It is striated by the fall of bodies, the verticals of gravity, the distri-
|
||
bution of matter into parallel layers, the lamellar and laminar movement
|
||
of flows. These parallel verticals have formed an independent dimension
|
||
capable of spreading everywhere, of formalizing all the other dimensions,
|
||
of striating all of space in all of its directions, so as to render it homoge-
|
||
neous. The vertical distance between two points provided the mode of
|
||
comparison for the horizontal distance between two other points. Univer-
|
||
sal attraction became the law of all laws, in that it set the rule for the
|
||
biunivocal correspondence between two bodies; and each time science dis-
|
||
covered a new field, it sought to formalize it in the same mode as the field of
|
||
gravity. Even chemistry became a royal science only by virtue of a whole
|
||
theoretical elaboration of the notion of weight. Euclidean space is founded
|
||
on the famous parallel postulate, but the parallels in question are in the
|
||
first place gravitational parallels, and correspond to the forces exerted by
|
||
gravity on all the elements of a body presumed to fill that space. It is the
|
||
point of application of the resultant of all of these parallel forces that
|
||
remains invariable when their common direction is changed or the body is
|
||
rotated (the center of gravity). In short, it seems that the force of gravity lies
|
||
at the basis of a laminar, striated, homogeneous, and centered space; it
|
||
forms the foundation for those multiplicities termed metric, or
|
||
arborescent, whose dimensions are independent of the situation and are
|
||
expressed with the aid of units and points (movements from one point to
|
||
another). It was not some metaphysical concern, but an effectively scien-
|
||
tific one, that frequently led scientists in the nineteenth century to ask if all
|
||
forces were not reducible to gravity, or rather to the form of attraction that
|
||
gives gravity a universal value (a constant relation for all variables) and
|
||
biunivocal scope (two bodies at a time, and no more). It is the form of
|
||
interiority of all science.
|
||
The nomos, or the dispars, is altogether different. But this is not to say
|
||
that the other forces refute gravity or contradict attraction. Although it is
|
||
true that they do not go against them, they do not result from them either;
|
||
they do not depend on them but testify to events that are always supple-
|
||
mentary or of "variable affects." Each time a new field opened up in
|
||
science—under conditions making this a far more important notion than
|
||
that of form or object—it proved irreducible to the field of attraction and
|
||
the model of the gravitational forces, although not contradictory to them.
|
||
It affirmed a "more" or an excess, and lodged itself in that excess, that devi-
|
||
ation. When chemistry took a decisive step forward, it was always by add-
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 371
|
||
|
||
ing to the force of weight bonds of another type (for example, electric) that
|
||
transformed the nature of chemical equations.36 But it will be noted that
|
||
the simplest considerations of velocity immediately introduce the differ-
|
||
ence between vertical descent and curvilinear motion, or more generally
|
||
between the straight line and the curve, in the differential form of the
|
||
clinamen, or the smallest deviation, the minimum excess. Smooth space is
|
||
precisely the space of the smallest deviation: therefore it has no homogene-
|
||
ity, except between infinitely proximate points, and the linking of proximi-
|
||
ties is effected independently of any determined path. It is a space of
|
||
contact, of small tactile or manual actions of contact, rather than a visual
|
||
space like Euclid's striated space. Smooth space is a field without conduits
|
||
or channels. A field, a heterogeneous smooth space, is wedded to a very
|
||
particular type of multiplicity: nonmetric, acentered, rhizomatic multipli-
|
||
cities that occupy space without "counting" it and can "be explored only by
|
||
legwork." They do not meet the visual condition of being observable from a
|
||
point in space external to them; an example of this is the system of sounds,
|
||
or even of colors, as opposed to Euclidean space.
|
||
When we oppose speed and slowness, the quick and the weighty,
|
||
Celeritas and Gravitas, this must not be seen as a quantitative opposition,
|
||
or as a mythological structure (although Dumezil has established the myth-
|
||
ological importance of this opposition, precisely in relation to the State
|
||
apparatus and its natural "gravity"). The opposition is both qualitative
|
||
and scientific, in that speed is not merely an abstract characteristic of
|
||
movement in general but is incarnated in a moving body that deviates,
|
||
however slightly, from its line of descent or gravity. Slow and rapid are not
|
||
quantitative degrees of movement but rather two types of qualified move-
|
||
ment, whatever the speed of the former or the tardiness of the latter.
|
||
Strictly speaking, it cannot be said that a body that is dropped has a speed,
|
||
however fast it falls; rather it has an infinitely decreasing slowness in accor-
|
||
dance with the law of falling bodies. Laminar movement that striates
|
||
space, that goes from one point to another, is weighty; but rapidity, celerity,
|
||
applies only to movement that deviates to the minimum extent and there-
|
||
after assumes a vortical motion, occupying a smooth space, actually draw-
|
||
ing smooth space itself. In this space, matter-flow can no longer be cut into
|
||
parallel layers, and movement no longer allows itself to be hemmed into
|
||
biunivocal relations between points. In this sense, the role of the qualita-
|
||
tive opposition gravity-celerity, heavy-light, slow-rapid is not that of a
|
||
quantifiable scientific determination but of a condition that is coextensive
|
||
to science and that regulates both the separation and the mixing of the two
|
||
models, their possible interpenetration, the domination of one by the
|
||
other, their alternative. And the best formulation, that of Michel Serres, is
|
||
indeed couched in terms of an alternative, whatever mixes or composi-
|
||
372 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
tions there may be: "Physics is reducible to two sciences, a general theory of
|
||
routes and paths, and a global theory of waves."37
|
||
A distinction must be made between two types of science, or scientific
|
||
procedures: one consists in "reproducing," the other in "following." The
|
||
first involves reproduction, iteration and reiteration; the other, involving
|
||
itineration, is the sum of the itinerant, ambulant sciences. Itineration is too
|
||
readily reduced to a modality of technology, or of the application and veri-
|
||
fication of science. But this is not the case: following is not at all the same
|
||
thing as reproducing, and one never follows in order to reproduce. The
|
||
ideal of reproduction, deduction, or induction is part of royal science, at all
|
||
times and in all places, and treats differences of time and place as so many
|
||
variables, the constant form of which is extracted precisely by the law: for
|
||
the same phenomena to recur in a gravitational and striated space it is suf-
|
||
ficient for the same conditions to obtain, or for the same constant relation
|
||
to hold between the differing conditions and the variable phenomena.
|
||
Reproducing implies the permanence of a fixed point of view that is exter-
|
||
nal to what is reproduced: watching the flow from the bank. But following
|
||
is something different from the ideal of reproduction. Not better, just dif-
|
||
ferent. One is obliged to follow when one is in search of the "singularities"
|
||
of a matter, or rather of a material, and not out to discover a form; when
|
||
one escapes the force of gravity to enter a field of celerity; when one ceases
|
||
to contemplate the course of a laminar flow in a determinate direction, to
|
||
be carried away by a vortical flow; when one engages in a continuous varia-
|
||
tion of variables, instead of extracting constants from them, etc. And the
|
||
meaning of Earth completely changes: with the legal model, one is con-
|
||
stantly reterritorializing around a point of view, on a domain, according to
|
||
a set of constant relations; but with the ambulant model, the process of
|
||
deterritorialization constitutes and extends the territory itself. "Go first to
|
||
your old plant and watch carefully the watercourse made by the rain. By
|
||
now the rain must have carried the seeds far away. Watch the crevices made
|
||
by the runoff, and from them determine the direction of the flow. Then
|
||
find the plant that is growing at the farthest point from your plant. All the
|
||
devil's weed plants that are growing in between are yours. Later. . . you can
|
||
extend the size of your territory."38 There are itinerant, ambulant sciences
|
||
that consist in following a flow in a vectorial field across which singularities
|
||
are scattered like so many "accidents" (problems). For example, why is
|
||
primitive metallurgy necessarily an ambulant science that confers upon
|
||
smiths a quasi-nomadic status? It could be objected that in these examples
|
||
it is still a question of going from one point to another (even if they are sin-
|
||
gular points) through the intermediary of channels, and that it is still possi-
|
||
ble to cut the flow into layers. But this is only true to the extent that
|
||
ambulant procedures and processes are necessarily tied to a striated
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 373
|
||
|
||
space—always formalized by royal science—which deprives them of their
|
||
model, submits them to its own model, and allows them to exist only in the
|
||
capacity of "technologies" or "applied science." As a general rule, a smooth
|
||
space, a vectorial field, a nonmetric multiplicity are always translatable,
|
||
and necessarily translated, into a "compars": a fundamental operation by
|
||
which one repeatedly overlays upon each point of smooth space a tangent
|
||
Euclidean space endowed with a sufficient number of dimensions, by
|
||
which one reintroduces parallelism between two vectors, treating multipli-
|
||
city as though it were immersed in this homogeneous and striated space of
|
||
reproduction, instead of continuing to follow it in an "exploration by leg-
|
||
work."39 This is the triumph of the logos or the law over the nomos. But the
|
||
complexity of the operation testifies to the existence of resistances it must
|
||
overcome. Whenever ambulant procedure and process are returned to
|
||
their own model, the points regain their position as singularities that
|
||
exclude all biunivocal relations, the flow regains its curvilinear and
|
||
vortical motion that excludes any parallelism between vectors, and smooth
|
||
space reconquers the properties of contact that prevent it from remaining
|
||
homogeneous and striated. There is always a current preventing the ambu-
|
||
lant or itinerant sciences from being completely internalized in the repro-
|
||
ductive royal sciences. There is a type of ambulant scientist whom State
|
||
scientists are forever fighting or integrating or allying with, even going so
|
||
far as to propose a minor position for them within the legal system of sci-
|
||
ence and technology.
|
||
It is not that the ambulant sciences are more saturated with irrational
|
||
procedures, with mystery and magic. They only get that way when they fall
|
||
into abeyance. And the royal sciences, for their part, also surround them-
|
||
selves with much priestliness and magic. Rather, what becomes apparent
|
||
in the rivalry between the two models is that the ambulant or nomad sci-
|
||
ences do not destine science to take on an autonomous power, or even to
|
||
have an autonomous development. They do not have the means for that
|
||
because they subordinate all their operations to the sensible conditions of
|
||
intuition and construction—following the flow of matter, drawing and
|
||
linking up smooth space. Everything is situated in an objective zone of
|
||
fluctuation that is coextensive with reality itself. However refined or rigor-
|
||
ous, "approximate knowledge" is still dependent upon sensitive and sensi-
|
||
ble evaluations that pose more problems than they solve: problematics is
|
||
still its only mode. In contrast, what is proper to royal science, to its
|
||
theorematic or axiomatic power, is to isolate all operations from the condi-
|
||
tions of intuition, making them true intrinsic concepts, or "categories."
|
||
That is precisely why deterritorialization, in this kind of science, implies a
|
||
reterritorialization in the conceptual apparatus. Without this categorical,
|
||
apodictic apparatus, the differential operations would be constrained to
|
||
374 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
follow the evolution of a phenomenon; what is more, since the experimen-
|
||
tation would be open-air, and the construction at ground level, the coordi-
|
||
nates permitting them to be erected as stable models would never become
|
||
available. Certain of these requirements are translated in terms of "safety":
|
||
the two cathedrals at Orleans and Beauvais collapsed at the end of the
|
||
twelfth century, and control calculations are difficult to effect for the con-
|
||
structions of ambulant science. Although safety is a fundamental element
|
||
in the theoretical norms of the State, and of the political ideal, there is also
|
||
something else at issue as well. Due to all their procedures, the ambulant
|
||
sciences quickly overstep the possibility of calculation: they inhabit that
|
||
"more" that exceeds the space of reproduction and soon run into problems
|
||
that are insurmountable from that point of view; they eventually resolve
|
||
those problems by means of a real-life operation. The solutions are sup-
|
||
posed to come from a set of activities that constitute them as nonautono-
|
||
mous. Only royal science, in contrast, has at its disposal a metric power that
|
||
can define a conceptual apparatus or an autonomy of science (including
|
||
the autonomy of experimental science). That is why it is necessary to cou-
|
||
ple ambulant spaces with a space of homogeneity, without which the laws
|
||
of physics would depend on particular points in space. But this is less a
|
||
translation than a constitution: precisely that constitution the ambulant
|
||
sciences did not undertake, and do not have the means to undertake. In the
|
||
field of interaction of the two sciences, the ambulant sciences confine
|
||
themselves to inventing problems whose solution is tied to a whole set of
|
||
collective, nonscientific activities but whose scientific solution depends,
|
||
on the contrary, on royal science and the way it has transformed the prob-
|
||
lem by introducing it into its theorematic apparatus and its organization of
|
||
work. This is somewhat like intuition and intelligence in Bergson, where
|
||
only intelligence has the scientific means to solve formally the problems
|
||
posed by intuition, problems that intuition would be content to entrust to
|
||
the qualitative activities of a humanity engaged in following matter.40
|
||
PROBLEM II. Is there a way to extricate thought from the State model?
|
||
PROPOSITION IV. The exteriority of the war machine is attested to,
|
||
finally, by noology.
|
||
Thought contents are sometimes criticized for being too conformist.
|
||
But the primary question is that of form itself. Thought as such is already in
|
||
conformity with a model that it borrows from the State apparatus, and
|
||
which defines for it goals and paths, conduits, channels, organs, an entire
|
||
organon. There is thus an image of thought covering all of thought; it is the
|
||
special object of "noology" and is like the State-form developed in thought.
|
||
This image has two heads, corresponding to the two poles of sovereignty:
|
||
the imperium of true thinking operating by magical capture, seizure or
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 375
|
||
|
||
binding, constituting the efficacy of a foundation (mythos); a republic of
|
||
free spirits proceeding by pact or contract, constituting a legislative and
|
||
juridical organization, carrying the sanction of a ground (logos). These two
|
||
heads are in constant interference in the classical image of thought: a
|
||
"republic of free spirits whose prince would be the idea of the Supreme
|
||
Being." And if these two heads are in interference, it is not only because
|
||
there are many intermediaries and transitions between them, and because
|
||
the first prepares the way for the second and the second uses and retains the
|
||
first, but also because, antithetical and complementary, they are necessary
|
||
to one another. It is not out of the question, however, that in order to pass
|
||
from one to the other there must occur, "between" them, an event of an
|
||
entirely different nature, one that hides outside the image, takes place out-
|
||
side.41 But confining ourselves to the image, it appears that it is not simply
|
||
a metaphor when we are told of an imperium of truth and a republic of spir-
|
||
its. It is the necessary condition for the constitution of thought as principle,
|
||
or as a form of interiority, as a stratum.
|
||
It is easy to see what thought gains from this: a gravity it would never
|
||
have on its own, a center that makes everything, including the State, appear
|
||
to exist by its own efficacy or on its own sanction. But the State gains just as
|
||
much. Indeed, by developing in thought in this way the State-form gains
|
||
something essential: a whole consensus. Only thought is capable of invent-
|
||
ing the fiction of a State that is universal by right, of elevating the State to
|
||
the level of de jure universality. It is as if the sovereign were left alone in the
|
||
world, spanned the entire ecumenon, and now dealt only with actual or
|
||
potential subjects. It is no longer a question of powerful, extrinsic organiza-
|
||
tions, or of strange bands: the State becomes the sole principle separating
|
||
rebel subjects, who are consigned to the state of nature, from consenting
|
||
subjects, who rally to its form of their own accord. If it is advantageous for
|
||
thought to prop itself up with the State, it is no less advantageous for the
|
||
State to extend itself in thought, and to be sanctioned by it as the unique,
|
||
universal form. The particularity of States becomes merely an accident of
|
||
fact, as is their possible perversity, or their imperfection. For the modern
|
||
State defines itself in principle as "the rational and reasonable organiza-
|
||
tion of a community": the only remaining particularity a community has is
|
||
interior or moral (the spirit of a people), at the same time as the community
|
||
is funneled by its organization toward the harmony of a universal (absolute
|
||
spirit). The State gives thought a form of interiority, and thought gives that
|
||
interiority a form of universality: "The goal of worldwide organization is
|
||
the satisfaction of reasonable individuals within particular free States."
|
||
The exchange that takes place between the State and reason is a curious
|
||
one; but that exchange is also an analytic proposition, because realized rea-
|
||
son is identified with the de jure State, just as the State is the becoming of
|
||
376 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
reason.42 In so-called modern philosophy, and in the so-called modern or
|
||
rational State, everything revolves around the legislator and the subject.
|
||
The State must realize the distinction between the legislator and the sub-
|
||
ject under formal conditions permitting thought, for its part, to conceptu-
|
||
alize their identity. Always obey. The more you obey, the more you will be
|
||
master, for you will only be obeying pure reason, in other words yourself...
|
||
Ever since philosophy assigned itself the role of ground it has been giving
|
||
the established powers its blessing, and tracing its doctrine of faculties onto
|
||
the organs of State power. Common sense, the unity of all the faculties at
|
||
the center constituted by the Cogito, is the State consensus raised to the
|
||
absolute. This was most notably the great operation of the Kantian "cri-
|
||
tique," renewed and developed by Hegelianism. Kant was constantly criti-
|
||
cizing bad usages, the better to consecrate the function. It is not at all
|
||
surprising that the philosopher has become a public professor or State
|
||
functionary. It was all over the moment the State-form inspired an image of
|
||
thought. With full reciprocity. Doubtless, the image itself assumes differ-
|
||
ent contours in accordance with the variations on this form: it has not
|
||
always delineated or designated the philosopher, and will not always delin-
|
||
eate him. It is possible to pass from a magical function to a rational func-
|
||
tion. The poet in the archaic imperial State was able to play the role of
|
||
image trainer.43 In modern States, the sociologist succeeded in replacing
|
||
the philosopher (as, for example, when Durkheim and his disciples set out
|
||
to give the republic a secular model of thought). Even today, psychoanaly-
|
||
sis lays claim to the role of Cogitatio universalis as the thought of the Law,
|
||
in a magical return. And there are quite a few other competitors and pre-
|
||
tenders. Noology, which is distinct from ideology, is precisely the study of
|
||
images of thought, and their historicity. In a sense, it could be said that all
|
||
this has no importance, that thought has never had anything but laughable
|
||
gravity. But that is all it requires: for us not to take it seriously. Because that
|
||
makes it all the easier for it to think for us, and to be forever engendering
|
||
new functionaries. Because the less people take thought seriously, the more
|
||
they think in conformity with what the State wants. Truly, what man of the
|
||
State has not dreamed of that paltry impossible thing—to be a thinker?
|
||
But noology is confronted by counterthoughts, which are violent in their
|
||
acts and discontinuous in their appearances, and whose existence is mobile
|
||
in history. These are the acts of a "private thinker," as opposed to the public
|
||
professor: Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, or even Shestov. Wherever they dwell,
|
||
it is the steppe or the desert. They destroy images. Nietzsche's Schopen-
|
||
hauer as Educator is perhaps the greatest critique ever directed against the
|
||
image of thought and its relation to the State. "Private thinker," however, is
|
||
not a satisfactory expression, because it exaggerates interiority, when it is a
|
||
question of outside thought.44 To place thought in an immediate relation
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 377
|
||
|
||
with the outside, with the forces of the outside, in short to make thought a
|
||
war machine, is a strange undertaking whose precise procedures can be
|
||
studied in Nietzsche (the aphorism, for example, is very different from the
|
||
maxim, for a maxim, in the republic of letters, is like an organic State act or
|
||
sovereign judgment, whereas an aphorism always awaits its meaning from
|
||
a new external force, a final force that must conquer or subjugate it, utilize
|
||
it). There is another reason why "private thinker" is not a good expression.
|
||
Although it is true that this counterthought attests to an absolute solitude,
|
||
it is an extremely populous solitude, like the desert itself, a solitude already
|
||
intertwined with a people to come, one that invokes and awaits that people,
|
||
existing only through it, though it is not yet here. "We are lacking that final
|
||
force, in the absence of a people to bear us. We are looking for that popular
|
||
support." Every thought is already a tribe, the opposite of a State. And this
|
||
form of exteriority of thought is not at all symmetrical to the form of
|
||
Anteriority. Strictly speaking, symmetry exists only between different poles
|
||
or focal points of interiority. But the form of exteriority of thought—the
|
||
force that is always external to itself, or the final force, the «th power—is
|
||
not at all another image in opposition to the image inspired by the State
|
||
apparatus. It is, rather, a force that destroys both the image and its copies,
|
||
the model and its reproductions, every possibility of subordinating
|
||
thought to a model of the True, the Just, or the Right (Cartesian truth,
|
||
Kantian just, Hegelian right, etc.). A "method" is the striated space of the
|
||
cogitatio universalis and draws a path that must be followed from one point
|
||
to another. But the form of exteriority situates thought in a smooth space
|
||
that it must occupy without counting, and for which there is no possible
|
||
method, no conceivable reproduction, but only relays, intermezzos, resur-
|
||
gences. Thought is like the Vampire; it has no image, either to constitute a
|
||
model of or to copy. In the smooth space of Zen, the arrow does not go from
|
||
one point to another but is taken up at any point, to be sent to any other
|
||
point, and tends to permute with the archer and the target. The problem of
|
||
the war machine is that of relaying, even with modest means, not that of the
|
||
architectonic model or the monument. An ambulant people of relayers,
|
||
rather than a model society. "Nature propels the philosopher into mankind
|
||
like an arrow; it takes no aim but hopes the arrow will stick somewhere. But
|
||
countless times it misses and is depressed at the fact The artist and the
|
||
philosopher are evidence against the purposiveness of nature as regards the
|
||
means it employs, though they are also first-rate evidence as to the wisdom
|
||
of its purpose. They strike home at only a few, while they ought to strike
|
||
home at everybody—and even these few are not struck with the force with
|
||
which the philosopher and artist launch their shot."45
|
||
We have in mind in particular two pathetic texts, in the sense that in
|
||
them thought is truly a pathos (an antilogos and an antimythos). One is a
|
||
378 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
text by Artaud, in his letters to Jacques Riviere, explaining that thought
|
||
operates on the basis of a central breakdown, that it lives solely by its own
|
||
incapacity to take on form, bringing into relief only traits of expression in a
|
||
material, developing peripherally, in a pure milieu of exteriority, as a func-
|
||
tion of singularities impossible to universalize, of circumstances impossi-
|
||
ble to interiorize. The other is the text by Kleist, "On the Gradual
|
||
Formation of Ideas in Speech" ("Uber die allmachliche Verfertigung der
|
||
Gedanken beim Reden"), in which Kleist denounces the central interiority
|
||
of the concept as a means of control—the control of speech, of language,
|
||
but also of affects, circumstances and even chance. He distinguishes this
|
||
from thought as a proceeding and a process, a bizarre anti-Platonic dia-
|
||
logue, an antidialogue between brother and sister where one speaks before
|
||
knowing while the other relays before having understood: this, Kleist says,
|
||
is the thought of the Gemut, which proceeds like a general in a war machine
|
||
should, or like a body charged with electricity, with pure intensity. "I mix
|
||
inarticulate sounds, lengthen transitional terms, as well as using apposi-
|
||
tions when they are unnecessary." Gain some time, and then perhaps
|
||
renounce, or wait. The necessity of not having control over language, of
|
||
being a foreigner in one's own tongue, in order to draw speech to oneself
|
||
and "bring something incomprehensible into the world." Such is the form
|
||
of exteriority, the relation between brother and sister, the becoming-
|
||
woman of the thinker, the becoming-thought of the woman: the Gemut that
|
||
refuses to be controlled, that forms a war machine. A thought grappling
|
||
with exterior forces instead of being gathered up in an interior form, oper-
|
||
ating by relays instead of forming an image; an event-thought, a haecceity,
|
||
instead of a subject-thought, a problem-thought instead of an essence-
|
||
thought or theorem; a thought that appeals to a people instead of taking
|
||
itself for a government ministry. Is it by chance that whenever a "thinker"
|
||
shoots an arrow, there is a man of the State, a shadow or an image of a man
|
||
of the State, that counsels and admonishes him, and wants to assign him a
|
||
target or "aim"? Jacques Riviere does not hesitate to respond to Artaud:
|
||
work at it, keep on working, things will come out all right, you will succeed
|
||
in finding a method and in learning to express clearly what you think in
|
||
essence (cogitatio universalis). Riviere is not a head of State, but he would
|
||
not be the last in the Nouvelle Revue Francaise to mistake himself for the
|
||
secret prince in a republic of letters or the gray eminence in a State of right.
|
||
Lenz and Kleist confronted Goethe, that grandiose genius, of all men of let-
|
||
ters a veritable man of the State. But that is not the worst of it: the worst is
|
||
the way the texts of Kleist and Artaud themselves have ended up becoming
|
||
monuments, inspiring a model to be copied—a model far more insidious
|
||
than the others—for the artificial stammerings and innumerable tracings
|
||
that claim to be their equal.
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 379
|
||
|
||
The classical image of thought, and the striating of mental space it
|
||
effects, aspires to universality. It in effect operates with two "universals,"
|
||
the Whole as the final ground of being or all-encompassing horizon, and
|
||
the Subject as the principle that converts being into being-for-us.461m-
|
||
perium and republic. Between the two, all of the varieties of the real and the
|
||
true find their place in a striated mental space, from the double point of
|
||
view of Being and the Subject, under the direction of a "universal method."
|
||
It is now easy for us to characterize the nomad thought that rejects this
|
||
image and does things differently. It does not ally itself with a universal
|
||
thinking subject but, on the contrary, with a singular race; and it does not
|
||
ground itself in an all-encompassing totality but is on the contrary de-
|
||
ployed in a horizonless milieu that is a smooth space, steppe, desert, or sea.
|
||
An entirely different type of adequation is established here, between
|
||
the race defined as "tribe" and smooth space defined as "milieu." A tribe
|
||
in the desert instead of a universal subject within the horizon of all-
|
||
encompassing Being. Kenneth White recently stressed this dissymmetrical
|
||
complementarity between a race-tribe (the Celts, those who feel they are
|
||
Celts) and a milieu-space (the Orient, the Gobi desert...). White demon-
|
||
strates that this strange composite, the marriage of the Celt and the Orient,
|
||
inspires a properly nomad thought that sweeps up English literature and
|
||
constitutes American literature.47 We immediately see the dangers, the
|
||
profound ambiguities accompanying in this enterprise, as if each effort
|
||
and each creation faced a possible infamy. For what can be done to prevent
|
||
the theme of a race from turning into a racism, a dominant and all-
|
||
encompassing fascism, or into a sect and a folklore, microfascisms? And
|
||
what can be done to prevent the oriental pole from becoming a phantasy
|
||
that reactivates all the fascisms in a different way, and also all the folklores,
|
||
yoga, Zen, and karate? It is certainly not enough to travel to escape phan-
|
||
tasy, and it is certainly not by invoking a past, real or mythical, that one
|
||
avoids racism. But here again, the criteria for making the distinction are
|
||
simple, whatever the de facto mixes that obscure them at a given level, at a
|
||
given moment. The race-tribe exists only at the level of an oppressed race,
|
||
and in the name of the oppression it suffers: there is no race but inferior,
|
||
minoritarian; there is no dominant race; a race is defined not by its purity
|
||
but rather by the impurity conferred upon it by a system of domination.
|
||
Bastard and mixed-blood are the true names of race. Rimbaud said it all on
|
||
this point: only he or she can invoke race who says, "I have always been of
|
||
an inferior race... I am of an inferior race for all eternity. . . There I am on
|
||
the Breton shore . . . I am a beast, a nigger . . . I am of a distant race: my
|
||
ancestors were Norsemen."48 In the same way that race is not something to
|
||
be rediscovered, the Orient is not something to be imitated: it only exists in
|
||
the construction of a smooth space, just as race only exists in the constitu-
|
||
380 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
tion of a tribe that peoples and traverses a smooth space. All of thought is a
|
||
becoming, a double becoming, rather than the attribute of a Subject and
|
||
the representation of a Whole.
|
||
AXIOM II. The war machine is the invention of the nomads (insofar as it is
|
||
exterior to the State apparatus and distinct from the military institu-
|
||
tion). As such, the war machine has three aspects, a spatiogeographic
|
||
aspect, an arithmetic or algebraic aspect, and an affective aspect.
|
||
PROPOSITION V. Nomad existence necessarily effectuates the conditions
|
||
of the war machine in space.
|
||
The nomad has a territory; he follows customary paths; he goes from
|
||
one point to another; he is not ignorant of points (water points, dwelling
|
||
points, assembly points, etc.). But the question is what in nomad life is a
|
||
principle and what is only a consequence. To begin with, although the
|
||
points determine paths, they are strictly subordinated to the paths they
|
||
determine, the reverse of what happens with the sedentary. The water
|
||
point is reached only in order to be left behind; every point is a relay and
|
||
exists only as a relay. A path is always between two points, but the in-bet-
|
||
ween has taken on all the consistency and enjoys both an autonomy and a
|
||
direction of its own. The life of the nomad is the intermezzo. Even the ele-
|
||
ments of his dwelling are conceived in terms of the trajectory that is for-
|
||
ever mobilizing them.49 The nomad is not at all the same as the migrant;
|
||
for the migrant goes principally from one point to another, even if the sec-
|
||
ond point is uncertain, unforeseen, or not well localized. But the nomad
|
||
goes from point to point only as a consequence and as a factual necessity;
|
||
in principle, points for him are relays along a trajectory. Nomads and
|
||
migrants can mix in many ways, or form a common aggregate; their
|
||
causes and conditions are no less distinct for that (for example, those who
|
||
joined Mohammed at Medina had a choice between a nomadic or bed-
|
||
ouin pledge, and a pledge of hegira or emigration).50
|
||
Second, even though the nomadic trajectory may follow trails or cus-
|
||
tomary routes, it does not fulfill the function of the sedentary road, which
|
||
is to parcel out a closed space to people, assigning each person a share and
|
||
regulating the communication between shares. The nomadic trajectory
|
||
does the opposite: it distributes people (or animals) in an open space, one
|
||
that is indefinite and noncommunicating. The nomos came to designate
|
||
the law, but that was originally because it was distribution, a mode of distri-
|
||
bution. It is a very special kind of distribution, one without division into
|
||
shares, in a space without borders or enclosure. The nomos is the consis-
|
||
tency of a fuzzy aggregate: it is in this sense that it stands in opposition to
|
||
the law or the polis, as the backcountry, a mountainside, or the vague
|
||
expanse around a city ("either nomos or polis").51 Therefore, and this is the
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 381
|
||
|
||
third point, there is a significant difference between the spaces: sedentary
|
||
space is striated, by walls, enclosures, and roads between enclosures, while
|
||
nomad space is smooth, marked only by "traits" that are effaced and dis-
|
||
placed with the trajectory. Even the lamellae of the desert slide over each
|
||
other, producing an inimitable sound. The nomad distributes himself in a
|
||
smooth space; he occupies, inhabits, holds that space; that is his territorial
|
||
principle. It is therefore false to define the nomad by movement. Toynbee
|
||
is profoundly right to suggest that the nomad is on the contrary he who does
|
||
not move. Whereas the migrant leaves behind a milieu that has become
|
||
amorphous or hostile, the nomad is one who does not depart, does not want
|
||
to depart, who clings to the smooth space left by the receding forest, where
|
||
the steppe or the desert advances, and who invents nomadism as a response
|
||
to this challenge.52 Of course, the nomad moves, but while seated, and he is
|
||
only seated while moving (the Bedouin galloping, knees on the saddle, sit-
|
||
ting on the soles of his upturned feet, "a feat of balance"). The nomad
|
||
knows how to wait, he has infinite patience. Immobility and speed, catato-
|
||
nia and rush, a "stationary process," station as process—these traits of
|
||
Kleist's are eminently those of the nomad. It is thus necessary to make a
|
||
distinction between speed and movement: a movement may be very fast,
|
||
but that does not give it speed; a speed may be very slow, or even immobile,
|
||
yet it is still speed. Movement is extensive; speed is intensive. Movement
|
||
designates the relative character of a body considered as "one," and which
|
||
goes from point to point; speed, on the contrary, constitutes the absolute
|
||
character of a body whose irreducible parts (atoms) occupy or fill a smooth
|
||
space in the manner of a vortex, with the possibility of springing up at any
|
||
point. (It is therefore not surprising that reference has been made to spiri-
|
||
tual voyages effected without relative movement, but in intensity, in one
|
||
place: these are part of nomadism.) In short, we will say by convention that
|
||
only nomads have absolute movement, in other words, speed; vortical or
|
||
swirling movement is an essential feature of their war machine.
|
||
It is in this sense that nomads have no points, paths, or land, even though
|
||
they do by all appearances. If the nomad can be called the Deterritorialized
|
||
par excellence, it is precisely because there is no reterritorialization after-
|
||
ward as with the migrant, or upon something else as with the sedentary (the
|
||
sedentary's relation with the earth is mediatized by something else, a prop-
|
||
erty regime, a State apparatus). With the nomad, on the contrary, it is
|
||
deterritorialization that constitutes the relation to the earth, to such a
|
||
degree that the nomad reterritorializes on deterritorialization itself. It is
|
||
the earth that deterritorializes itself, in a way that provides the nomad with
|
||
a territory. The land ceases to be land, tending to become simply ground
|
||
(sot) or support. The earth does not become deterritorialized in its global
|
||
and relative movement, but at specific locations, at the spot where the for-
|
||
382 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
est recedes, or where the steppe and the desert advance. Hubac is right to
|
||
say that nomadism is explainable less by universal changes in climate
|
||
(which relate instead to migrations) as by the "divagation of local cli-
|
||
mates."53 The nomads are there, on the land, wherever there forms a
|
||
smooth space that gnaws, and tends to grow, in all directions. The nomads
|
||
inhabit these places; they remain in them, and they themselves make them
|
||
grow, for it has been established that the nomads make the desert no less
|
||
than they are made by it. They are vectors of deterritorialization. They add
|
||
desert to desert, steppe to steppe, by a series of local operations whose ori-
|
||
entation and direction endlessly vary.54 The sand desert has not only oases,
|
||
which are like fixed points, but also rhizomatic vegetation that is tempo-
|
||
rary and shifts location according to local rains, bringing changes in the
|
||
direction of the crossings.55 The same terms are used to describe ice deserts
|
||
as sand deserts: there is no line separating earth and sky; there is no inter-
|
||
mediate distance, no perspective or contour; visibility is limited; and yet
|
||
there is an extraordinarily fine topology that relies not on points or objects
|
||
but rather on haecceities, on sets of relations (winds, undulations of snow
|
||
or sand, the song of the sand or the creaking of ice, the tactile qualities of
|
||
both). It is a tactile space, or rather "haptic," a sonorous much more than a
|
||
visual space.56 The variability, the polyvocality of directions, is an essential
|
||
feature of smooth spaces of the rhizome type, and it alters their cartogra-
|
||
phy. The nomad, nomad space, is localized and not delimited. What is both
|
||
limited and limiting is striated space, the relative global: it is limited in its
|
||
parts, which are assigned constant directions, are oriented in relation to
|
||
one another, divisible by boundaries, and can interlink; what is limiting
|
||
(limes or wall, and no longer boundary) is this aggregate in relation to the
|
||
smooth spaces it "contains," whose growth it slows or prevents, and which
|
||
it restricts or places outside. Even when the nomad sustains its effects, he
|
||
does not belong to this relative global, where one passes from one point to
|
||
another, from one region to another. Rather, he is in a local absolute, an
|
||
absolute that is manifested locally, and engendered in a series of local oper-
|
||
ations of varying orientations: desert, steppe, ice, sea.
|
||
Making the absolute appear in a particular place—is that not a very gen-
|
||
eral characteristic of religion (recognizing that the nature of the appear-
|
||
ance, and the legitimacy, or lack thereof, of the images that reproduce it are
|
||
open to debate)? But the sacred place of religion is fundamentally a center
|
||
that repels the obscure nomos. The absolute of religion is essentially a hori-
|
||
zon that encompasses, and, if the absolute itself appears at a particular
|
||
place, it does so in order to establish a solid and stable center for the global.
|
||
The encompassing role of smooth spaces (desert, steppe, or ocean) in
|
||
monotheism has been frequently noted. In short, religion converts the
|
||
absolute. Religion is in this sense a piece in the State apparatus (in both of
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 383
|
||
|
||
its forms, the "bond" and the "pact or alliance"), even if it has within itself
|
||
the power to elevate this model to the level of the universal or to constitute
|
||
an absolute Imperium. But for the nomad the terms of the question are
|
||
totally different: locality is not delimited; the absolute, then, does not
|
||
appear at a particular place but becomes a nonlimited locality; the coup-
|
||
ling of the place and the absolute is achieved not in a centered, oriented
|
||
globalization or universalization but in an infinite succession of local oper-
|
||
ations. Limiting ourselves to this opposition between points of view, it may
|
||
be observed that nomads do not provide a favorable terrain for religion; the
|
||
man of war is always committing an offense against the priest or the god.
|
||
The nomads have a vague, literally vagabond "monotheism," and content
|
||
themselves with that, and with their ambulant fires. The nomads have a
|
||
sense of the absolute, but a singularly atheistic one. The universalist reli-
|
||
gions that have had dealings with nomads—Moses, Mohammed, even
|
||
Christianity with the Nestorian heresy—have always encountered prob-
|
||
lems in this regard, and have run up against what they have termed obsti-
|
||
nate impiety. These religions are not, in effect, separable from a firm and
|
||
constant orientation, from an imperial de jure State, even, and especially,
|
||
in the absence of a de facto State; they have promoted an ideal of sedentari-
|
||
zation and addressed themselves more to the migrant components than the
|
||
nomadic ones. Even early Islam favored the theme of the hegira, or migra-
|
||
tion, over nomadism; rather, it was through certain schisms (such as the
|
||
Khariji movement) that it won over the Arab or Berber nomads.57
|
||
However, it does not exhaust the question to establish a simple opposi-
|
||
tion between two points of view, religion-nomadism. For monotheistic
|
||
religion, at the deepest level of its tendency to project a universal or spiri-
|
||
tual State over the entire ecumenon, is not without ambivalence or fringe
|
||
areas; it goes beyond even the ideal limits of the State, even the imperial
|
||
State, entering a more indistinct zone, an outside of States where it has the
|
||
possibility of undergoing a singular mutation or adaptation. We are refer-
|
||
ring to religion as an element in a war machine and the idea of holy war as
|
||
the motor of that machine. The prophet, as opposed to the state personality
|
||
of the king and the religious personality of the priest, directs the movement
|
||
by which a religion becomes a war machine or passes over to the side of
|
||
such a machine. It has often been said that Islam, and the prophet Moham-
|
||
med, performed such a conversion of religion and constituted a veritable
|
||
esprit de corps: in the formula of Georges Bataille, "early Islam, a society
|
||
reduced to the military enterprise." This is what the West invokes in order
|
||
to justify its antipathy toward Islam. Yet the Crusades were a properly
|
||
Christian adventure of this type. The prophets may very well condemn
|
||
nomad life; the war machine may very well favor the movement of
|
||
migration and the ideal of establishment; religion in general may very well
|
||
384 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
compensate for its specific deterritorialization with a spiritual and even
|
||
physical reterritorialization, which in the case of the holy war assumes the
|
||
well-directed character of a conquest of the holy lands as the center of the
|
||
world. Despite all that, when religion sets itself up as a war machine, it
|
||
mobilizes and liberates a formidable charge of nomadism or absolute
|
||
deterritorialization; it doubles the migrant with an accompanying nomad,
|
||
or with the potential nomad the migrant is in the process of becoming; and
|
||
finally, it turns its dream of an absolute State back against the State-form.58
|
||
And this turning-against is no less a part of the "essence" of religion than
|
||
that dream. The history of the Crusades is marked by the most astonishing
|
||
series of directional changes: the firm orientation toward the Holy Land as
|
||
a center to reach often seems nothing more than a pretext. But it would be
|
||
wrong to say that the play of self-interest, or economic, commercial, or
|
||
political factors, diverted the crusade from its pure path. The idea of the
|
||
crusade in itself implies this variability of directions, broken and changing,
|
||
and intrinsically possesses all these factors or all these variables from the
|
||
moment it turns religion into a war machine and simultaneously utilizes
|
||
and gives rise to the corresponding nomadism.59 The necessity of main-
|
||
taining the most rigorous of distinctions between sedentaries, migrants,
|
||
and nomads does not preclude de facto mixes; on the contrary, it makes
|
||
them all the more necessary in turn. And it is impossible to think of the gen-
|
||
eral process of sedentarization that vanquished the nomads without also
|
||
envisioning the gusts of local nomadization that carried off sedentaries
|
||
and doubled migrants (notably, to the benefit of religion).
|
||
Smooth or nomad space lies between two striated spaces: that of the for-
|
||
est, with its gravitational verticals, and that of agriculture, with its grids
|
||
and generalized parallels, its now independent arborescence, its art of
|
||
extracting the tree and wood from the forest. But being "between" also
|
||
means that smooth space is controlled by these two flanks, which limit it,
|
||
oppose its development, and assign it as much as possible a communica-
|
||
tional role; or, on the contrary, it means that it turns against them, gnawing
|
||
away at the forest on one side, on the other side gaining ground on the culti-
|
||
vated lands, affirming a noncommunicating force or a force of divergence
|
||
like a "wedge" digging in. The nomads turn first against the forest and the
|
||
mountain dwellers, then descend upon the farmers. What we have here is
|
||
something like the flipside or the outside of the State-form—but in what
|
||
sense? This form, as a global and relative space, implies a certain number of
|
||
components: forest-clearing of fields; agriculture-grid laying; animal rais-
|
||
ing subordinated to agricultural work and sedentary food production;
|
||
commerce based on a constellation of town-country (polis-nomos) com-
|
||
munications. When historians inquire into the reasons for the victory of
|
||
the West over the Orient, they primarily mention the following characteris-
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 385
|
||
|
||
tics, which put the Orient in general at a disadvantage: deforestation rather
|
||
than clearing for planting, making it extremely difficult to extract or even
|
||
to find wood; cultivation of the type "rice paddy and garden" rather than
|
||
arborescence and field; animal raising for the most part outside the control
|
||
of the sedentaries, with the result that they lacked animal power and meat
|
||
foods; the low communication content of the town-country relation, mak-
|
||
ing commerce far less flexible.60 The conclusion is not that the State-form
|
||
is absent in the Orient. Quite to the contrary, a more rigid agency becomes
|
||
necessary in order to retain and reunite the various components plied by
|
||
escape vectors. States always have the same composition; if there is even
|
||
one truth in the political philosophy of Hegel, it is that every State carries
|
||
within itself the essential moments of its existence. States are made up not
|
||
only of people but also of wood, fields, gardens, animals, and commodities.
|
||
There is a unity of composition of all States, but States have neither the
|
||
same development nor the same organization. In the Orient, the compo-
|
||
nents are much more disconnected, disjointed, necessitating a great immu-
|
||
table Form to hold them together: "despotic formations," Asian or African,
|
||
are rocked by incessant revolts, by secessions and dynastic changes, which
|
||
nevertheless do not affect the immutability of the form. In the West, on the
|
||
other hand, the interconnectedness of the components makes possible
|
||
transformations of the State-form through revolution. It is true that the
|
||
idea of revolution itself is ambiguous; it is Western insofar as it relates to a
|
||
transformation of the State, but Eastern insofar as it envisions the destruc-
|
||
tion, the abolition of the State.61 The great empires of the Orient, Africa,
|
||
and America run up against wide-open smooth spaces that penetrate them
|
||
and maintain gaps between their components (the nomos does not become
|
||
countryside, the countryside does not communicate with the town, large-
|
||
scale animal raising is the affair of the nomads, etc.): the oriental State is in
|
||
direct confrontation with a nomad war machine. This war machine may
|
||
fall back to the road of integration and proceed solely by revolt and dynas-
|
||
tic change; nevertheless, it is the war machine, as nomad, that invents the
|
||
abolitionist dream and reality. Western States are much more sheltered in
|
||
their striated space and consequently have much more latitude in holding
|
||
their components together; they confront the nomads only indirectly,
|
||
through the intermediary of the migrations the nomads trigger or adopt as
|
||
their stance.62
|
||
One of the fundamental tasks of the State is to striate the space over
|
||
which it reigns, or to utilize smooth spaces as a means of communication in
|
||
the service of striated space. It is a vital concern of every State not only to
|
||
vanquish nomadism but to control migrations and, more generally, to
|
||
establish a zone of rights over an entire "exterior," over all of the flows
|
||
traversing the ecumenon. If it can help it, the State does not dissociate itself
|
||
386 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
from a process of capture of flows of all kinds, populations, commodities
|
||
or commerce, money or capital, etc. There is still a need for fixed paths in
|
||
well-defined directions, which restrict speed, regulate circulation,
|
||
relativize movement, and measure in detail the relative movements of sub-
|
||
jects and objects. That is why Paul Virilio's thesis is important, when he
|
||
shows that "the political power of the State ispolis, police, that is, manage-
|
||
ment of the public ways," and that "the gates of the city, its levies and
|
||
duties, are barriers, filters against the fluidity of the masses, against the
|
||
penetration power of migratory packs," people, animals, and goods.63
|
||
Gravity, gravitas, such is the essence of the State. It is not at all that the
|
||
State knows nothing of speed; but it requires that movement, even the fast-
|
||
est, cease to be the absolute state of a moving body occupying a smooth
|
||
space, to become the relative characteristic of a "moved body" going from
|
||
one point to another in a striated space. In this sense, the State never ceases
|
||
to decompose, recompose, and transform movement, or to regulate speed.
|
||
The State as town surveyor, converter, or highway interchange: the role of
|
||
the engineer from this point of view. Speed and absolute movement are not
|
||
without their laws, but they are the laws of the nomos, of the smooth space
|
||
that deploys it, of the war machine that populates it. If the nomads formed
|
||
the war machine, it was by inventing absolute speed, by being "synony-
|
||
mous" with speed. And each time there is an operation against the State—
|
||
insubordination, rioting, guerrilla warfare, or revolution as act—it can be
|
||
said that a war machine has revived, that a new nomadic potential has
|
||
appeared, accompanied by the reconstitution of a smooth space or a man-
|
||
ner of being in space as though it were smooth (Virilio discusses the impor-
|
||
tance of the riot or revolutionary theme of "holding the street"). It is in this
|
||
sense that the response of the State against all that threatens to move
|
||
beyond it is to striate space. The State does not appropriate the war
|
||
machine without giving even it the form of relative movement: this was the
|
||
case with the model of the fortress as a regulator of movement, which was
|
||
precisely the obstacle the nomads came up against, the stumbling block
|
||
and parry by which absolute vortical movement was broken. Conversely,
|
||
when a State does not succeed in striating its interior or neighboring space,
|
||
the flows traversing that State necessarily adopt the stance of a war
|
||
machine directed against it, deployed in a hostile or rebellious smooth
|
||
space (even if other States are able to slip their striations in). This was the
|
||
adventure of China: toward the end of the fourteenth century, and in spite
|
||
of its very high level of technology in ships and navigation, it turned its
|
||
back on its huge maritime space, saw its commercial flows turn against it
|
||
and ally themselves with piracy, and was unable to react except by a politics
|
||
of immobility, of the massive restriction of commerce, which only
|
||
reinforced the connection between commerce and the war machine.64
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 387
|
||
|
||
The situation is much more complicated than we have let on. The sea is
|
||
perhaps principal among smooth spaces, the hydraulic model par excel-
|
||
lence. But the sea is also, of all smooth spaces, the first one attempts were
|
||
made to striate, to transform into a dependency of the land, with its fixed
|
||
routes, constant directions, relative movements, a whole counterhydraulic
|
||
of channels and conduits. One of the reasons for the hegemony of the West
|
||
was the power of its State apparatuses to striate the sea by combining the
|
||
technologies of the North and the Mediterranean and by annexing the
|
||
Atlantic. But this undertaking had the most unexpected result: the multi-
|
||
plication of relative movements, the intensification of relative speeds in
|
||
striated space, ended up reconstituting a smooth space or absolute move-
|
||
ment. As Virilio emphasizes, the sea became the place of the fleet in being,
|
||
where one no longer goes from one point to another, but rather holds space
|
||
beginning from any point: instead of striating space, one occupies it with a
|
||
vector of deterritorialization in perpetual motion. This modern strategy
|
||
was communicated from the sea to the air, as the new smooth space, but
|
||
also to the entire Earth considered as desert or sea. As converter and
|
||
capturer, the State does not just relativize movement, it reimparts absolute
|
||
movement. It does not just go from the smooth to the striated, it reconsti-
|
||
tutes smooth space; it reimparts smooth in the wake of the striated. It is
|
||
true that this new nomadism accompanies a worldwide war machine
|
||
whose organization exceeds the State apparatuses and passes into energy,
|
||
military-industrial, and multinational complexes. We say this as a
|
||
reminder that smooth space and the form of exteriority do not have an irre-
|
||
sistible revolutionary calling but change meaning drastically depending on
|
||
the interactions they are part of and the concrete conditions of their exer-
|
||
cis,e or establishment (for example, the way in which total war and popular
|
||
war, and even guerrilla warfare, borrow one another's methods).65
|
||
PROPOSITION VI. Nomad existence necessarily implies the numerical
|
||
elements of a war machine.
|
||
Tens, hundreds, thousands, myriads: all armies retain these decimal
|
||
groupings, to the point that each time they are encountered it is safe to
|
||
assume the presence of a military organization. Is this not the way an army
|
||
deterritorializes its soldiers? An army is composed of units, companies,
|
||
and divisions. The Numbers may vary in function, in combination; they
|
||
may enter into entirely different strategies; but there is always a connection
|
||
between the Number and the war machine. It is a question not of quantity
|
||
but of organization or composition. When the State creates armies, it
|
||
always applies this principle of numerical organization; but all it does is
|
||
adopt the principle, at the same time as it appropriates the war machine.
|
||
For so peculiar an idea—the numerical organization of people—came
|
||
388 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
from the nomads. It was the Hyksos, conquering nomads, who brought it to
|
||
Egypt; and when Moses applied it to his people in exodus, it was on the
|
||
advice of his nomad father-in-law, Jethro the Kenite, and was done in such
|
||
a way as to constitute a war machine, the elements of which are described in
|
||
the biblical book of Numbers. The nomos is fundamentally numerical,
|
||
arithmetic. When Greek geometrism is contrasted with Indo-Arab
|
||
arithmetism, it becomes clear that the latter implies a nomos opposable to
|
||
the logos: not that the nomads "do" arithmetic or algebra, but because
|
||
arithmetic and algebra arise in a strongly nomad influenced world.
|
||
Up to now we have known three major types of human organization: lin-
|
||
eal, territorial, and numerical. Lineal organization allows us to define
|
||
so-called primitive societies. Clan lineages are essentially segments in
|
||
action; they meld and divide, and vary according to the ancestor consid-
|
||
ered, the tasks, and the circumstances. Of course, number plays an impor-
|
||
tant role in the determination of lineage, or in the creation of new
|
||
lineages—as does the earth, since a clan segmentarity is doubled by a tribal
|
||
segmentarity. The earth is before all else the matter upon which the
|
||
dynamic of lineages is inscribed, and the number, a means of inscription:
|
||
the lineages write upon the earth and with the number, constituting a kind
|
||
of "geodesy." Everything changes with State societies: it is often said that
|
||
the territorial principle becomes dominant. One could also speak of
|
||
deterritorialization, since the earth becomes an object, instead of being an
|
||
active material element in combination with lineage. Property is precisely
|
||
the deterritorialized relation between the human being and the earth; this
|
||
is so whether property constitutes a good belonging to the State,
|
||
superposed upon continuing possession by a lineal community, or whether
|
||
it itself becomes a good belonging to private individuals constituting a new
|
||
community. In both cases (and according to the two poles of the State),
|
||
something like an overcoding of the earth replaces geodesy. Of course, line-
|
||
ages remain very important, and numbers take on their own importance.
|
||
But what moves to the forefront is a "territorial" organization, in the sense
|
||
that all the segments, whether of lineage, land, or number, are taken up by
|
||
an astronomical space or a geometrical extension that overcodes them—
|
||
but certainly not in the same way in the archaic imperial State and in mod-
|
||
ern States. The archaic State envelops a spatium with a summit, a
|
||
differentiated space with depth and levels, whereas modern States (begin-
|
||
ning with the Greek city-state) develop a homogeneous extensio with an
|
||
immanent center, divisible homologous parts, and symmetrical and
|
||
reversible relations. Not only do the two models, the astronomical and the
|
||
geometrical, enter into intimate mixes, but even when they are supposedly
|
||
pure, both imply the subordination of lineages and numbers to this metric
|
||
power, as it appears either in the imperial spatium or in the political
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 389
|
||
|
||
extension Arithmetic, the number, has always had a decisive role in the
|
||
State apparatus: this is so even as early as the imperial bureaucracy, with
|
||
the three conjoined operations of the census, taxation, and election. It is
|
||
even truer of modern forms of the State, which in developing utilized all
|
||
the calculation techniques that were springing up at the border between
|
||
mathematical science and social technology (there is a whole social calcu-
|
||
lus at the basis of political economy, demography, the organization of
|
||
work, etc.). This arithmetic element of the State found its specific power in
|
||
the treatment of all kinds of matter: primary matters (raw materials), the
|
||
secondary matter of wrought objects, or the ultimate matter constituted by
|
||
the human population. Thus the number has always served to gain mastery
|
||
over matter, to control its variations and movements, in other words, to
|
||
submit them to the spatiotemporal framework of the State—either the
|
||
imperial spatium, or the modern extensio.61 The State has a territorial
|
||
principle, or a principle of deterritorialization, that links the number to
|
||
metric magnitudes (taking into account the increasingly complex metrics
|
||
effecting the overcoding). We do not believe that the conditions of inde-
|
||
pendence or autonomy of the Number are to be found in the State, even
|
||
though all the factors of its development are present.
|
||
The Numbering Number, in other words, autonomous arithmetic organ-
|
||
ization, implies neither a superior degree of abstraction nor very large
|
||
quantities. It relates only to conditions of possibility constituted by
|
||
nomadism and to conditions of effectuation constituted by the war
|
||
machine. It is in State armies that the problem of the treatment of large
|
||
quantities arises, in relation to other matters; but the war machine operates
|
||
with small quantities that it treats using numbering numbers. These num-
|
||
bers appear as soon as one distributes something in space, instead of divid-
|
||
ing up space or distributing space itself. The number becomes a subject.
|
||
The independence of the number in relation to space is a result not of
|
||
abstraction but of the concrete nature of smooth space, which is occupied
|
||
without itself being counted. The number is no longer a means of counting
|
||
or measuring but of moving: it is the number itself that moves through
|
||
smooth space. There is undoubtedly a geometry of smooth space: but as we
|
||
have seen, it is a minor, operative geometry, a geometry of the trait. The
|
||
more independent space is from a metrics, the more independent the num-
|
||
ber is from space. Geometry as a royal science has little importance for the
|
||
war machine (its only importance is in State armies, and for sedentary for-
|
||
tification, but it leads generals to serious defeats).68 The number becomes a
|
||
principle whenever it occupies a smooth space, and is deployed within it as
|
||
subject, instead of measuring a striated space. The number is the mobile
|
||
occupant, the movable (meuble) in smooth space, as opposed to the
|
||
geometry of the immovable (immeuble) in striated space. The nomadic
|
||
390 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
numerical unit is the ambulant fire, and not the tent, which is still too much
|
||
of an immovable: "The fire takes precedence over the yurt." The number-
|
||
ing number is no longer subordinated to metric determinations or geomet-
|
||
rical dimensions, but has only a dynamic relation with geographical
|
||
directions: it is a directional number, not a dimensional or metric one.
|
||
Nomad organization is indissolubly arithmetic and directional; quantity is
|
||
everywhere, tens, hundreds, direction is everywhere, left, right: the numer-
|
||
ical chief is also the chief of the left or the right.69 The numbering number is
|
||
rhythmic, not harmonic. It is not related to cadence or measure: it is only in
|
||
State armies, and for reasons of discipline and show, that one marches in
|
||
cadence; but autonomous numerical organization finds its meaning else-
|
||
where, whenever it is necessary to establish an order of displacement on the
|
||
steppe, the desert—at the point where the lineages of the forest dwellers
|
||
and the figures of the State lose their relevance. "He moved with the ran-
|
||
dom walk which made only those sounds natural to the desert. Nothing in
|
||
his passage would [indicate] that human flesh moved there. It was a way of
|
||
walking so deeply conditioned in him that he didn't need to think about it.
|
||
The feet moved of themselves, no measurable rhythm to their pacing."70 In
|
||
the war machine and nomadic existence, the number is no longer num-
|
||
bered, but becomes a Cipher (Chiffre), and it is in this capacity that it con-
|
||
stitutes the "esprit de corps" and invents the secret and its outgrowths
|
||
(strategy, espionage, war ruses, ambush, diplomacy, etc.).
|
||
A ciphered, rhythmic, directional, autonomous, movable, numbering
|
||
number: the war machine is like the necessary consequence of nomadic
|
||
organization (Moses experienced it, with all its consequences). Some peo-
|
||
ple nowadays are too eager to criticize this numerical organization,
|
||
denouncing it as a military or even concentration-camp society where peo-
|
||
ple are no longer anything more than deterritorialized "numbers." But that
|
||
is false. Horror for horror, the numerical organization of people is certainly
|
||
no crueler than the lineal or State organizations. Treating people like num-
|
||
bers is not necessarily worse than treating them like trees to prune, or geo-
|
||
metrical figures to shape and model. Moreover, the use of the number as a
|
||
numeral, as a statistical element, is proper to the numbered number of the
|
||
State, not to the numbering number. And the world of the concentration
|
||
camp operates as much by lineages and territories as by numeration. The
|
||
question is not one of good or bad but of specificity. The specificity of
|
||
numerical organization rests on the nomadic mode of existence and the
|
||
war machine function. The numbering number is distinct both from lineal
|
||
codes and State overcoding. Arithmetic composition, on the one hand,
|
||
selects, extracts from the lineages the elements that will enter into
|
||
nomadism and the war machine and, on the other hand, directs them
|
||
against the State apparatus, opposing a machine and an existence to the
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 391
|
||
|
||
State apparatus, drawing a deterritorialization that cuts across both the lin-
|
||
eal territorialities and the territory or deterritoriality of the State.
|
||
A first characteristic of the numbering, nomadic or war, number is that
|
||
it is always complex, that is, articulated. A complex of numbers every time.
|
||
It is exactly for this reason that it in no way implies large, homogenized
|
||
quantities, like State numbers or the numbered number, but rather pro-
|
||
duces its effect of immensity by its fine articulation, in other words, by its
|
||
distribution of heterogeneity in a free space. Even State armies do not do
|
||
away with this principle when they deal with large numbers (despite the
|
||
predominance of "base" 10). The Roman legion was a number made up of
|
||
numbers, articulated in such a way that the segments became mobile, and
|
||
the figures geometrical, changing, transformational. The complex or artic-
|
||
ulated number comprises not only men but necessarily weapons, animals,
|
||
and vehicles. The arithmetic base unit is therefore a unit of assemblage, for
|
||
example, man-horse-bow, 1 x 1 X 1, according to the formula that carried
|
||
the Scythians to triumph; and the formula becomes more complicated to
|
||
the extent that certain "weapons" assemble or articulate several men or
|
||
animals, as in the case of the chariot with two horses and two men, one to
|
||
drive and the other to throw, 2 X 1 X 2 = 1; or in the case of the famous
|
||
two-handled shield of the hoplite reform, which soldered together human
|
||
chains. However small the unit, it is articulated. The numbering number
|
||
always has several bases at the same time. It is also necessary to take into
|
||
account arithmetic relations that are external yet still contained in the
|
||
number, expressing the proportion of combatants among the members of a
|
||
lineage or tribe, the role of reserves and stocks, the upkeep of people,
|
||
things, and animals. Logistics is the art of these external relations, which
|
||
are no less a part of the war machine than the internal relations of strategy,
|
||
in other words, the composition of combat units in relation to one another.
|
||
The two together constitute the science of the articulation of numbers of
|
||
war. Every assemblage has this strategic aspect and this logistical aspect.
|
||
But the numbering number has a second, more secret, characteristic.
|
||
Everywhere, the war machine displays a curious process of arithmetic rep-
|
||
lication or doubling, as if it operated along two nonsymmetrical and
|
||
nonequal series. On the one hand, the lineages are indeed organized and
|
||
reshuffled numerically; a numerical composition is superimposed upon
|
||
the lineages in order to bring the new principle into predominance. But on
|
||
the other hand, men are simultaneously extracted from each lineage to
|
||
form a special numerical body—as if the new numerical composition of
|
||
the lineage-body could not succeed without the constitution of a body
|
||
proper to it, itself numerical. We believe that this is not an accidental
|
||
phenomenon but rather an essential constituent of the war machine, a
|
||
necessary operation for the autonomy of the number: the number of the
|
||
392 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
body must have as its correlate a body of the number; the number must be
|
||
doubled according to two complementary operations. For the social body
|
||
to be numerized, the number must form a special body. When Genghis
|
||
Khan undertook his great composition of the steppe, he numerically or-
|
||
ganized the lineages, and the fighters in each lineage, placing them under a
|
||
cipher and a chief (groups of ten with decurions, groups of one hundred
|
||
with centurions, groups of one thousand with chiliarchs). He also extracted
|
||
from each arithmetized lineage a small number of men who were to consti-
|
||
tute his personal guard, in other words, a dynamic formation comprising a
|
||
staff, commissars, messengers, and diplomats ("antrustions").71 One is
|
||
never without the other: a double deterritorialization, the second of which
|
||
is to a higher power. When Moses undertook his great composition of the
|
||
desert—where the influence he felt from the nomads was necessarily
|
||
stronger than that of Yahweh—he took a census of each tribe and or-
|
||
ganized them numerically; he also decreed a law according to which the
|
||
firstborn of each tribe at that particular time belonged by right to Yahweh.
|
||
As these firstborn were obviously still too young, their role in the Number
|
||
was transferred to a special tribe, the Levites, who provided the body of the
|
||
Number or the special guard of the ark; and as the Levites were less numer-
|
||
ous than the new firstborn of the tribes taken together, the excess firstborn
|
||
had to be bought back by the tribes in the form of taxes (bringing us back to
|
||
a fundamental aspect of logistics). The war machine would be unable to
|
||
function without this double series: it is necessary both that numerical
|
||
composition replace lineal organization and that it conjure away the ter-
|
||
ritorial organization of the State. Power in the war machine is defined ac-
|
||
cording to this double series: power is no longer based on segments and
|
||
centers, on the potential resonance of centers and overcoding of segments,
|
||
but on these relations internal to the Number and independent of quantity.
|
||
Tensions or power struggles are also a result of this: between Moses' tribes
|
||
and the Levites, between Genghis's "noyans" and "antrustions." This is
|
||
not simply a protest on the part of lineages wishing to regain their former
|
||
autonomy; nor is it the prefiguration of a struggle for control over a State
|
||
apparatus. It is a tension inherent in the war machine, in its special power,
|
||
and in the particular limitations placed on the power of the "chief."
|
||
Thus numerical composition, or the numbering number, implies several
|
||
operations: the arithmetization of the starting aggregates or sets (the line-
|
||
ages); the union of the extracted subsets (the constitution of groups often,
|
||
one hundred, etc.); and the formation by substitution of another set in cor-
|
||
respondence with the united set (the special body). It is this last operation
|
||
that implies the most variety and originality in nomad existence. The same
|
||
problem arises even in State armies, when the war machine is appropriated
|
||
by the State. In effect, if the arithmetization of the social body has as its cor-
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE d 393
|
||
|
||
relate the formation of a distinct special body, itself arithmetic, this special
|
||
body may be constructed in several ways: (1) from a privileged lineage or
|
||
tribe, the dominance of which subsequently takes on a new meaning (the
|
||
case of Moses, with the Levites); (2) from representatives of each lineage,
|
||
who subsequently serve also as hostages (the firstborn; this would actually
|
||
be the Asian case, or the case of Genghis); (3) from a totally different ele-
|
||
ment, one exterior to the base society, slaves, foreigners, or people of
|
||
another religion (this was already the case as early as the Saxon regime, in
|
||
which the king used Prankish slaves to compose his special body; but Islam
|
||
is the prime example, even inspiring a specific sociological category, that of
|
||
"military slavery": the Mameluks of Egypt, slaves from the steppe or the
|
||
Caucasus who were purchased at a very early age by the sultan; or the Otto-
|
||
man Janissaries, who came from Christian communities).72
|
||
Is this not the origin of an important theme, "the nomads as child
|
||
stealers"? It is clear, especially in the last example, how the special body is
|
||
instituted as an element determinant of power in the war machine. The war
|
||
machine and nomadic existence have to ward off two things simultane-
|
||
ously: a return of the lineal aristocracy and the formation of imperial
|
||
functionaries. What complicates everything is that the State itself has often
|
||
been determined in such a way as to use slaves as high functionaries. As we
|
||
shall see, the reasons for this varied, and although the two currents con-
|
||
verged in armies, they came from two distinct sources. For the power of
|
||
slaves, foreigners, or captives in a war machine of nomadic origin is very
|
||
different from the power of lineal aristocracies, as well as from that of State
|
||
functionaries and bureaucrats. They are "commissars," emissaries, diplo-
|
||
mats, spies, strategists, and logisticians, sometimes smiths. They cannot be
|
||
explained away as a "whim of the sultan." On the contrary, it is the possibil-
|
||
ity of the war chief having whims that is explained by the objective exis-
|
||
tence and necessity of this special numerical body, this Cipher that has
|
||
value only in relation to a nomos. There is both a deterritorialization and a
|
||
becoming proper to the war machine; the special body, in particular the
|
||
slave-infidel-foreigner, is the one who becomes a soldier and believer while
|
||
remaining deterritorialized in relation to the lineages and the State. You
|
||
have to be born an infidel to become a believer; you have to be born a slave
|
||
to become a soldier. Specific schools or institutions are needed for this pur-
|
||
pose: the special body is an invention proper to the war machine, which
|
||
States always utilize, adapting it so totally to their own ends that it becomes
|
||
unrecognizable, or restituting it in bureaucratic staff form, or in the tech-
|
||
nocratic form of very special bodies, or in "esprit de corps" that serve the
|
||
State as much as they resist it, or among the commissars who double the
|
||
State as much as they serve it.
|
||
It is true that the nomads have no history; they only have a geography.
|
||
394 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
And the defeat of the nomads was such, so complete, that history is one
|
||
with the triumph of States. We have witnessed, as a result, a generalized cri-
|
||
tique dismissing the nomads as incapable of any innovation, whether tech-
|
||
nological or metallurgical, political or metaphysical. Historians, bourgeois
|
||
or Soviet (Grousset or Vladimirtsov), consider the nomads a pitiable seg-
|
||
ment of humanity that understands nothing: not technology, to which it
|
||
supposedly remained indifferent; not agriculture, not the cities and States
|
||
it destroyed or conquered. It is difficult to see, however, how the nomads
|
||
could have triumphed in war if they did not possess strong metallurgical
|
||
capabilities (the idea that the nomads received their technical weapons and
|
||
political counseling from renegades from an imperial State is highly im-
|
||
probable). It is difficult to see how the nomads could have undertaken to
|
||
destroy cities and States, except in the name of a nomad organization and a
|
||
war machine defined not by ignorance but by their positive characteristics,
|
||
by their specific space, by a composition all their own that broke with line-
|
||
ages and warded off the State-form. History has always dismissed the
|
||
nomads. Attempts have been made to apply a properly military category to
|
||
the war machine (that of "military democracy") and a properly sedentary
|
||
category to nomadism (that of "feudalism"). But these two hypotheses pre-
|
||
suppose a territorial principle: either that an imperial State appropriates
|
||
the war machine, distributing land to warriors as a benefit of their position
|
||
(cleroi and false fiefs), or that property, once it has become private, in itself
|
||
posits relations of dependence among the property owners constituting the
|
||
army (true fiefs and vassalage).73 In both cases, the number is subordinated
|
||
to an "immobile" fiscal organization, in order to establish which land can
|
||
be or has been ceded, as well as to set the taxes owed by the beneficiaries
|
||
themselves. There is no doubt that nomad organization and the war
|
||
machine deal with these same problems, both the level of land and of taxa-
|
||
tion (in which the nomadic warriors were great innovators, despite what is
|
||
said to the contrary). But they invent a territoriality and a "movable" fiscal
|
||
organization that testify to the autonomy of a numerical principle: there
|
||
can be a confusion or combination of the systems, but the specificity of the
|
||
nomadic system remains the subordination of land to numbers that are
|
||
displaced and deployed, and of taxation to relations internal to those num-
|
||
bers (already with Moses, for example, taxation played a role in the relation
|
||
between the numerical bodies and the special body of the number). In
|
||
short, military democracy and feudalism, far from explaining the numeri-
|
||
cal composition of the nomads, instead testify to what may survive of them
|
||
in sedentary regimes.
|
||
PROPOSITION VII. Nomad existence has for "affects" the weapons of a
|
||
war machine.
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 395
|
||
|
||
A distinction can always be made between weapons and tools on the
|
||
basis of their usage (destroying people or producing goods). But although
|
||
this extrinsic distinction explains certain secondary adaptations of a tech-
|
||
nical object, it does not preclude a general convertibility between the two
|
||
groups, to the extent that it seems very difficult to propose an intrinsic dif-
|
||
ference between weapons and tools. The types of percussion, as defined by
|
||
Andre Leroi-Gourhan, are found on both sides. "For ages on end agricul-
|
||
tural implements and weapons of war must have remained identical."74
|
||
Some have spoken of an "ecosystem," not only situated at the origin, in
|
||
which work tools and weapons of war exchange their determinations: it
|
||
seems that the same machinicphylum traverses both. And yet we have the
|
||
feeling that there are many internal differences, even if they are not intrin-
|
||
sic, in other words, logical or conceptual, and even if they remain approxi-
|
||
mate. As a first approximation, weapons have a privileged relation with
|
||
projection. Anything that throws or is thrown is fundamentally a weapon,
|
||
and propulsion is its essential moment. The weapon is ballistic; the very
|
||
notion of the "problem" is related to the war machine. The more mecha-
|
||
nisms of projection a tool has, the more it behaves like a weapon, poten-
|
||
tially or simply metaphorically. In addition, tools are constantly compen-
|
||
sating for the projective mechanisms they possess, or else they adapt them
|
||
to other ends. It is true that missile weapons, in the strict sense, whether
|
||
projected or projecting, are only one kind among others; but even hand-
|
||
held weapons require a usage of the hand and arm different from that
|
||
required by tools, a projective usage exemplified in the martial arts. The
|
||
tool, on the other hand, is much more introceptive, introjective: it prepares
|
||
a matter from a distance, in order to bring it to a state of equilibrium or to
|
||
appropriate it for a form of interiority. Action at a distance exists in both
|
||
cases, but in one case it is centrifugal and in the other, centripetal. One
|
||
could also say that the tool encounters resistances, to be conquered or put
|
||
to use, while the weapon has to do with counterattack, to be avoided or
|
||
invented (the counterattack is in fact the precipitating and inventive factor
|
||
in the war machine, to the extent that it is not simply reducible to a quanti-
|
||
tative rivalry or defensive parade).
|
||
Second, weapons and tools do not "tendentially" (approximately) have
|
||
the same relation to movement, to speed. It is yet another essential contri-
|
||
bution of Paul Virilio to have stressed this weapon-speed complemen-
|
||
tarity: the weapon invents speed, or the discovery of speed invents the
|
||
weapon (the projective character of weapons is the result). The war
|
||
machine releases a vector of speed so specific to it that it needs a special
|
||
name; it is not only the power of destruction, but "dromocracy" (= nomos).
|
||
Among other advantages, this idea articulates a new mode of distinction
|
||
between the hunt and war. For it is certain not only that war does not derive
|
||
396 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
from the hunt but also that the hunt does not promote weapons: either war
|
||
evolved in the sphere of indistinction and convertibility between weapons
|
||
and tools, or it used to its own advantage weapons already distinguished,
|
||
already constituted. As Virilio says, war in no way appears when man
|
||
applies to man the relation of the hunter to the animal, but on the contrary
|
||
when he captures the force of the hunted animal and enters an entirely new
|
||
relation to man, that of war (enemy, no longer prey). It is therefore not sur-
|
||
prising that the war machine was the invention of the animal-raising
|
||
nomads: animal breeding and training are not to be confused either with
|
||
the primitive hunt or with sedentary domestication, but are in fact the dis-
|
||
covery of a projecting and projectile system. Rather than operating by
|
||
blow-by-blow violence, or constituting a violence "once and for all," the
|
||
war machine, with breeding and training, institutes an entire economy of
|
||
violence, in other words, a way of making violence durable, even unlim-
|
||
ited. "Bloodletting, immediate killing, run contrary to the unlimited usage
|
||
of violence, that is, to its economy.... The economy of violence is not that of
|
||
the hunter in the animal raiser, but that of the hunted animal. In horseback
|
||
riding, one conserves the kinetic energy, the speed of the horse, and no
|
||
longer its proteins (the motor, and no longer the flesh).. . . Whereas in the
|
||
hunt the hunter's aim was to arrest the movement of wild animality
|
||
through systematic slaughter, the animal breeder [sets about] conserving it,
|
||
and, by means of training, the rider joins with this movement, orienting it
|
||
and provoking its acceleration." The technological motor would develop
|
||
this tendency further, but "horseback riding was the first projector of the
|
||
warrior, his first system of arms."75 Whence becoming-animal in the war
|
||
machine. Does this mean that the war machine did not exist before horse-
|
||
back riding and the cavalry? That is not the issue. The issue is that the war
|
||
machine implies the release of a Speed vector that becomes a free or inde-
|
||
pendent variable; this does not occur in the hunt, where speed is associated
|
||
primarily with the hunted animal. It is possible for this race vector to be
|
||
released in an infantry, without recourse to horseback riding; it is possible,
|
||
moreover, for there to be horseback riding, but as a means of transporta-
|
||
tion or even of portage having nothing to do with the free vector. In any
|
||
event, what the warrior borrows from the animal is more the idea of the
|
||
motor than the model of the prey. He does not generalize the idea of the
|
||
prey by applying it to the enemy; he abstracts the idea of the motor, apply-
|
||
ing it to himself.
|
||
Two objections immediately arise. According to the first, the war
|
||
machine possesses as much weight and gravity as it does speed (the distinc-
|
||
tion between the heavy and the light, the dissymmetry between defense and
|
||
attack, the opposition between rest and tension). But it would be easy to
|
||
demonstrate that phenomena of "temporization," and even of immobility
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 397
|
||
|
||
and catatonia, so important in wars, relate in certain cases to a component
|
||
of pure speed. And the rest of the time, they relate to the conditions under
|
||
which State apparatuses appropriate the war machine, notably by arrang-
|
||
ing a striated space where opposing forces can come to an equilibrium. It
|
||
can happen that speed is abstracted as the property of a projectile, a bullet
|
||
or artillery shell, which condemns the weapon itself, and the soldier, to
|
||
immobility (for example, immobility in the First World War). But an equi-
|
||
librium offerees is a phenomenon of resistance, whereas the counterattack
|
||
implies a rush or change of speed that breaks the equilibrium: it was the
|
||
tank that regrouped all of the operations in the speed vector and recreated a
|
||
smooth space for movement by uprooting men and arms.76
|
||
The opposite objection is more complex: it is that speed does indeed
|
||
seem to be as much a part of the tool as of the weapon, and is no way specific
|
||
to the war machine. The history of the motor is not only military. But per-
|
||
haps there is too much of a tendency to think in terms of quantities of
|
||
movement, instead of seeking qualitative models. The two ideal models of
|
||
the motor are those of work and free action. Work is a motor cause that
|
||
meets resistances, operates upon the exterior, is consumed and spent in its
|
||
effect, and must be renewed from one moment to the next. Free action is
|
||
also a motor cause, but one that has no resistance to overcome, operates
|
||
only upon the mobile body itself, is not consumed in its effect, and contin-
|
||
ues from one moment to the next. Whatever its measure or degree, speed is
|
||
relative in the first case, absolute in the second (the idea of a perpetuum
|
||
mobile). In work, what counts is the point of application of a resultant force
|
||
exerted by the weight of a body considered as "one" (gravity), and the rela-
|
||
tive displacement of this point of application. In free action, what counts is
|
||
the way in which the elements of the body escape gravitation to occupy
|
||
absolutely a nonpunctuated space. Weapons and weapon handling seem to
|
||
be linked to a free-action model, and tools to a work model. Linear dis-
|
||
placement, from one point to another, constitutes the relative movement
|
||
of the tool, but it is the vortical occupation of a space that constitutes the
|
||
absolute movement of the weapon. It is as though the weapon were moving,
|
||
self-propelling, while the tool is moved. This link between tools and work
|
||
remains obscured unless work receives the motor, or real, definition we
|
||
have just given it. The tool does not define work; just the opposite. The tool
|
||
presupposes work. It must be added that weapons, also, obviously imply a
|
||
renewal of the cause, an expending or even disappearance in the effect, the
|
||
encountering of external resistances, a displacement of force, etc. It would
|
||
be futile to credit weapons with a magical power in contrast to the con-
|
||
straints of tools: weapons and tools are subject to the same laws, which
|
||
define, precisely, their common sphere. But the principle behind all tech-
|
||
nology is to demonstrate that a technical element remains abstract,
|
||
398 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
entirely undetermined, as long as one does not relate it to an assemblage it
|
||
presupposes. It is the machine that is primary in relation to the technical
|
||
element: not the technical machine, itself a collection of elements, but the
|
||
social or collective machine, the machinic assemblage that determines
|
||
what is a technical element at a given moment, what is its usage, extension,
|
||
comprehension, etc.
|
||
It is through the intermediary of assemblages that the phylum selects,
|
||
qualifies, and even invents the technical elements. Thus one cannot speak
|
||
of weapons or tools before defining the constituent assemblages they pre-
|
||
suppose and enter into. This is what we meant when we said that weapons
|
||
and tools are not merely distinguished from one another in an extrinsic
|
||
manner, and yet they have no distinctive intrinsic characteristics. They
|
||
have internal (and not intrinsic) characteristics relating to the respective
|
||
assemblages with which they are associated. What effectuates a free-action
|
||
model is not the weapons in themselves and in their physical aspect but the
|
||
"war machine" assemblage as formal cause of the weapons. And what
|
||
effectuates the work model is not the tools but the "work machine" assem-
|
||
blage as formal cause of the tools. When we say that the weapon is insepara-
|
||
ble from a speed vector, while the tool remains tied to conditions of gravity,
|
||
we are claiming only to signal a difference between two types of assem-
|
||
blage, a distinction that holds even if in the assemblage proper to it the tool
|
||
is abstractly "faster," and the weapon abstractly "weightier." The tool is
|
||
essentially tied to a genesis, a displacement, and an expenditure of force
|
||
whose laws reside in work, while the weapon concerns only the exercise or
|
||
manifestation of force in space and time, in conformity with free action.
|
||
The weapon does not fall from the sky, and obviously assumes production,
|
||
displacement, expenditure, and resistance. But this aspect relates to the
|
||
common sphere of the weapon and the tool, and does not yet concern the
|
||
specificity of the weapon, which appears only when force is considered in
|
||
itself, when it is no longer tied to anything but the number, movement,
|
||
space, or time, or when speed is added to displacement.17 Concretely, a
|
||
weapon as such relates not to the Work model but to the Free-Action
|
||
model, with the assumption that the conditions of work are fulfilled else-
|
||
where. In short, from the point of view offeree, the tool is tied to a gravity-
|
||
displacement, weight-height system, and the weapon to a speed-perpetuum
|
||
mobile system (it is in this sense that it can be said that speed in itself is a
|
||
"weapons system").
|
||
The very general primacy of the collective and machinic assemblage
|
||
over the technical element applies generally, for tools as for weapons.
|
||
Weapons and tools are consequences, nothing but consequences. It has
|
||
often been remarked that a weapon is nothing outside of the combat organ-
|
||
ization it is bound up with. For example, "hoplite" weapons existed only by
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 399
|
||
|
||
virtue of the phalanx as a mutation of the war machine: the only new
|
||
weapon at the time, the two-handled shield, was created by this assem-
|
||
blage; the other weapons were preexistent, but in other combinations
|
||
where they had a different function, a different nature. 78 It is always the
|
||
assemblage that constitutes the weapons system. The lance and the sword
|
||
came into being in the Bronze Age only by virtue of the man-horse assem-
|
||
blage, which caused a lengthening of the dagger and pike, and made the
|
||
first infantry weapons, the morning star and the battle-ax, obsolete. The
|
||
stirrup, in turn, occasioned a new figure of the man-horse assemblage,
|
||
entailing a new type of lance and new weapons; and this man-horse-stirrup
|
||
constellation is itself variable, and has different effects depending on
|
||
whether it is bound up with the general conditions of nomadism, or later
|
||
readapted to the sedentary conditions of feudalism. The situation is
|
||
exactly the same for the tool: once again, everything depends on an organi-
|
||
zation of work, and variable assemblages of human, animal, and thing.
|
||
Thus the heavy plow exists as a specific tool only in a constellation where
|
||
"long open fields" predominate, where the horse tends to replace the ox as
|
||
draft animal, where the land begins to undergo triennial rotation, and
|
||
where the economy becomes communal. Beforehand, the heavy plow may
|
||
well have existed, but on the margins of other assemblages that did not
|
||
bring out its specificity, that left unexploited its differential character with
|
||
the scratch plow.79
|
||
Assemblages are passional, they are compositions of desire. Desire has
|
||
nothing to do with a natural or spontaneous determination; there is no
|
||
desire but assembling, assembled, desire. The rationality, the efficiency, of
|
||
an assemblage does not exist without the passions the assemblage brings into
|
||
play, without the desires that constitute it as much as it constitutes
|
||
them. Detienne has shown that the Greek phalanx was inseparable from a
|
||
whole reversal of values, and from a passional mutation that drastically
|
||
changed the relations between desire and the war machine. It is a case of
|
||
man dismounting from the horse, and of the man-animal relation being
|
||
replaced by a relation between men in an infantry assemblage that paves
|
||
the way for the advent of the peasant-soldier, the citizen-soldier: the entire
|
||
Eros of war changes, a group homosexual Eros tends to replace the
|
||
zoosexual Eros of the horseman. Undoubtedly, whenever a State appropri-
|
||
ates the war machine, it tends to assimilate the education of the citizen to
|
||
the training of the worker to the apprenticeship of the soldier. But if it is
|
||
true that all assemblages are assemblages of desire, the question is whether
|
||
the assemblages of war and work, considered in themselves, do not funda-
|
||
mentally mobilize passions of different orders. Passions are effectuations
|
||
of desire that differ according to the assemblage: it is not the same justice or
|
||
the same cruelty, the same pity, etc. The work regime is inseparable from an
|
||
400 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
organization and a development of Form, corresponding to which is the
|
||
formation of the subject. This is the passional regime of feeling as "the
|
||
form of the worker." Feeling implies an evaluation of matter and its resis-
|
||
tances, a direction (sens, also "meaning") to form and its developments, an
|
||
economy offeree and its displacements, an entire gravity. But the regime of
|
||
the war machine is on the contrary that of affects, which relate only to the
|
||
moving body in itself, to speeds and compositions of speed among ele-
|
||
ments. Affect is the active discharge of emotion, the counterattack,
|
||
whereas feeling is an always displaced, retarded, resisting emotion. Affects
|
||
are projectiles just like weapons; feelings are introceptive like tools. There
|
||
is a relation between the affect and the weapon, as witnessed not only in
|
||
mythology but also in the chanson degeste, and the chivalric novel or novel
|
||
of courtly love. Weapons are affects and affects weapons. From this stand-
|
||
point, the most absolute immobility, pure catatonia, is a part of the speed
|
||
vector, is carried by this vector, which links the petrification of the act to
|
||
the precipitation of movement. The knight sleeps on his mount, then
|
||
departs like an arrow. Kleist is the author who best integrated these sudden
|
||
catatonic fits, swoons, suspenses, with the utmost speeds of a war machine.
|
||
He presents us with a becoming-weapon of the technical element simulta-
|
||
neous to a becoming-affect of the passional element (the Penthesilea equa-
|
||
tion). The martial arts have always subordinated weapons to speed, and
|
||
above all to mental (absolute) speed; for this reason, they are also the arts of
|
||
suspense and immobility. The affect passes through both extremes. Thus
|
||
•the martial arts do not adhere to a code, as an affair of the State, but follow
|
||
ways, which are so many paths of the affect; upon these ways, one learns to
|
||
"unuse" weapons as much as one learns to use them, as if the power and cul-
|
||
tivation of the affect were the true goal of the assemblage, the weapon being
|
||
only a provisory means. Learning to undo things, and to undo oneself, is
|
||
proper to the war machine: the "not-doing" of the warrior, the undoing of
|
||
the subject. A movement of decoding runs through the war machine, while
|
||
overcoding solders the tool to an organization of work and of the State (the
|
||
tool is never unlearned; one can only compensate for its absence). It is true
|
||
that the martial arts continually invoke the center of gravity and the rules
|
||
for its displacement. That is because these ways are not the ultimate ones.
|
||
However far they go, they are still in the domain of Being, and only trans-
|
||
late absolute movements of another nature into the common space—those
|
||
effectuated in the Void, not in nothingness, but in the smooth of the void
|
||
where there is no longer any goal: attacks, counterattacks, and headlong
|
||
plunges.80
|
||
Still from the standpoint of the assemblage, there is an essential relation
|
||
between tools and signs. That is because the work model that defines the
|
||
tool belongs to the State apparatus. It has often been said that people in
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 401
|
||
|
||
primitive societies do not, strictly speaking, work, even if their activities
|
||
are very constrained and regulated; and the man of war, in his capacity as a
|
||
man of war, does not work either (the "labors" of Hercules assume submis-
|
||
sion to a king). The technical element becomes a tool when it is abstracted
|
||
from the territory and is applied to the earth as an object; but at the same
|
||
time, the sign ceases to be inscribed upon the body and is written upon an
|
||
immobile, objective matter. For there to be work, there must be a capture
|
||
of activity by the State apparatus, and a semiotization of activity by writ-
|
||
ing. Hence the affinity between the assemblages signs-tools, and signs of
|
||
writing-organization of work. Entirely different is the case of the weapon,
|
||
which is in an essential relation with jewelry. Jewelry has undergone so
|
||
many secondary adaptations that we no longer have a clear understanding
|
||
of what it is. But something lights up in our mind when we are told that
|
||
metalworking was the "barbarian," or nomad, art par excellence, and when
|
||
we see these masterpieces of minor art. These fibulas, these gold or silver
|
||
plaques, these pieces of jewelry, are attached to small movable objects; they
|
||
are not only easy to transport, but pertain to the object only as object in
|
||
motion. These plaques constitute traits of expression of pure speed, car-
|
||
ried on objects that are themselves mobile and moving. The relation
|
||
between them is not that of form-matter but of motif-support, where the
|
||
earth is no longer anything more than ground (sol), where there is no longer
|
||
even any ground at all because the support is as mobile as the motif. They
|
||
lend colors the speed of light, turning gold to red and silver to white light.
|
||
They are attached to the horse's harness, the sheath of the sword, the
|
||
warrior's garments, the handle of the weapon; they even decorate things
|
||
used only once, such as arrowheads. Regardless of the effort or toil they
|
||
imply, they are of the order of free action, related to pure mobility, and not
|
||
of the order of work with its conditions of gravity, resistance, and expendi-
|
||
ture. The ambulant smith links metalworking to the weapon, and vice
|
||
versa. Gold and silver have taken on many other functions but cannot be
|
||
understood apart from this nomadic contribution made by the war
|
||
machine, in which they are not matters but traits of expression appropriate
|
||
to weapons (the whole mythology of war not only subsists in money but is
|
||
the active factor in it). Jewels are the affects corresponding to weapons, that
|
||
are swept up by the same speed vector.
|
||
Metalworking, jewelry making, ornamentation, even decoration, do not
|
||
form a writing, even though they have a power of abstraction that is in
|
||
every way equal to that of writing. But this power is assembled differently.
|
||
In the case of writing, the nomads had no need to create their own system;
|
||
they borrowed that of their sedentary imperial neighbors, who even fur-
|
||
nished them with a phonetic transcription of their languages.81 "The
|
||
goldsmith's and silversmith's is the barbarian art par excellence; filigree
|
||
402 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
and gold and silver plating. . . . Scythian art, tied as it was to a nomadic and
|
||
warlike economy that both used and repudiated a commerce reserved for
|
||
foreigners, now moved toward this luxurious and decorative type of work.
|
||
The barbarians. .. did not need to possess or create a precise code, such as
|
||
for instance an elementary picto-ideographic one—still less a syllabic writ-
|
||
ing of their own, which would indeed have had to compete with the ones in
|
||
use among their more advanced neighbors. Toward the fourth and third
|
||
centuries B.C. the Scythian art of the Black Sea region thus tends naturally
|
||
toward a graphic schematization of its forms, which makes them more of a
|
||
linear ornamentation than a proto-writing."82 Of course, one may write on
|
||
jewelry, metal plaques, or even weapons, but only in the sense that one
|
||
applies a preexisting writing system to these matters. The case of runic writ-
|
||
ing is more troubling because its origins seem exclusively tied to jewelry,
|
||
fibulas, elements of metalworking, small movable objects. The point is
|
||
that in its early period runic writing had only a weak communication value
|
||
and a very restricted public function. Its secret character has led many to
|
||
interpret it as magical writing. Rather, it is an affective semiotic, compris-
|
||
ing in particular: (1) signatures, as marks of possession or fabrication, and
|
||
(2) short war or love messages. It constitutes a text that is "ornamental"
|
||
rather than scriptural, "an invention with little utility, half-aborted," a sub-
|
||
stitute writing. It only takes on the value of writing during a second period,
|
||
when monumental inscriptions appear, with the Danish reform of the
|
||
ninth century A.D., in connection with the State and work.83
|
||
It may be objected that tools, weapons, signs, and jewelry in fact occur
|
||
everywhere, in a common sphere. But that is not the problem, any more
|
||
than it is to seek an origin in each case. It is a question of assigning assem-
|
||
blages, in other words, of determining the differential traits according to
|
||
which an element formally belongs to one assemblage rather than to
|
||
another. It could also be said that architecture and cooking have an appar-
|
||
ent affinity with the State, whereas music and drugs have differential traits
|
||
that place them on the side of the nomadic war machine.84 // is therefore a
|
||
differential method that establishes the distinction between weapons and
|
||
tools, from at least five points of view: the direction (sens) (projection-
|
||
introception), the vector (speed-gravity), the model (free action-work), the
|
||
expression (jewelry-signs), and the passional or desiring tonality (affect-
|
||
feeling). Doubtless the State apparatus tends to bring uniformity to the
|
||
regimes, by disciplining its armies, by making work a fundamental unit, in
|
||
other words, by imposing its own traits. But it is not impossible for weap-
|
||
ons and tools, if they are taken up by new assemblages of metamorphosis,
|
||
to enter other relations of alliance. The man of war may at times form peas-
|
||
ant or worker alliances, but it is more frequent for a worker, industrial or
|
||
agricultural, to reinvent a war machine. Peasants made an important con-
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 403
|
||
|
||
|
||
tribution to the history of artillery during the Hussite wars, when Zizka
|
||
armed mobile fortresses made from oxcarts with portable cannons. A
|
||
worker-soldier, weapon-tool, sentiment-affect affinity marks the right
|
||
time, however fleeting, for revolutions and popular wars. There is a schizo-
|
||
phrenic taste for the tool that moves it away from work and toward free
|
||
action, a schizophrenic taste for the weapon that turns it into a means for
|
||
peace, for obtaining peace. A counterattack and a resistance simultane-
|
||
ously. Everything is ambiguous. But we do not believe that Ernst Junger's
|
||
analyses are disqualified by this ambiguity when he portrays the "Rebel" as
|
||
a transhistorical figure drawing the Worker, on the one hand, and the Sol-
|
||
dier, on the other, down a shared line of flight where one says simultane-
|
||
ously "I seek a weapon" and "I am looking for a tool": Draw the line, or
|
||
what amounts to the same thing, cross the line, pass over the line, for the
|
||
line is only drawn by surpassing the line of separation.85 Undoubtedly,
|
||
nothing is more outmoded than the man of war: he has long since been
|
||
transformed into an entirely different character, the military man. And the
|
||
worker himself has undergone so many misadventures . . . And yet men of
|
||
war reappear, with many ambiguities: they are all those who know the use-
|
||
lessness of violence but who are adjacent to a war machine to be recreated,
|
||
one of active, revolutionary counterattacks. Workers also reappear who do
|
||
not believe in work but who are adjacent to a work machine to be recreated,
|
||
one of active resistance and technological liberation. They do not resusci-
|
||
tate old myths or archaic figures; they are the new figures of a transhistor-
|
||
ical assemblage (neither historical nor eternal, but untimely): the nomad
|
||
warrior and the ambulant worker. A somber caricature already precedes
|
||
them, the mercenary or mobile military adviser, and the technocrat or
|
||
transhumant analyst, CIA and IBM. But transhistorical figures must
|
||
defend themselves as much against old myths as against preestablished,
|
||
anticipatory disfigurations. "One does not go back to reconquer the myth,
|
||
one encounters it anew, when time quakes at its foundations under the
|
||
empire of extreme danger." Martial arts and state-of-the-art technologies
|
||
have value only because they create the possibility of bringing together
|
||
worker and warrior masses of a new type. The shared line of flight of the
|
||
weapon and the tool: a pure possibility, a mutation. There arise subterra-
|
||
nean, aerial, submarine technicians who belong more or less to the world
|
||
order, but who involuntarily invent and amass virtual charges of knowl-
|
||
edge and action that are usable by others, minute but easily acquired for
|
||
new assemblages. The borrowings between warfare and the military appa-
|
||
ratus, work and free action, always run in both directions, for a struggle that
|
||
is all the more varied.
|
||
PROBLEM III. How do the nomads invent or find their weapons?
|
||
404 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
PROPOSITION VIII. Metallurgy in itself constitutes a flow necessarily con-
|
||
fluent with nomadism.
|
||
The political, economic, and social regime of the peoples of the steppe
|
||
are less well known than their innovations in war, in the areas of offensive
|
||
and defensive weapons, composition or strategy, and technological ele-
|
||
ments (the saddle, stirrup, horseshoe, harness, etc.). History contests each
|
||
innovation but cannot succeed in effacing the nomad traces. What the
|
||
nomads invented was the man-animal-weapon, man-horse-bow assem-
|
||
blage. Through this assemblage of speed, the ages of metal are marked by
|
||
innovation. The socketed bronze battle-ax of the Hyksos and the iron
|
||
sword of the Hittites have been compared to miniature atomic bombs. It
|
||
has been possible to establish a rather precise periodization of the weapons
|
||
of the steppe, showing the alternation between heavy and light armament
|
||
(the Scythian type and the Sarmatian type), and their mixed forms. The
|
||
cast steel saber, often short and curved, a weapon for side attack with the
|
||
edge of the blade, envelops a different dynamic space than the forged iron
|
||
sword used for frontal attack with the point: it was the Scythians who
|
||
brought it to India and Persia, where the Arabs would later acquire it. It is
|
||
commonly agreed that the nomads lost their role as innovators with the
|
||
advent of firearms, in particular the cannon ("gunpowder overtook
|
||
them"). But it was not necessarily because they did not know how to use
|
||
them. Not only did armies like the Turkish army, whose nomadic tradi-
|
||
tions remained strong, develop extensive firepower, a new space, but addi-
|
||
tionally, and even more characteristically, light artillery was thoroughly
|
||
integrated into mobile formations of wagons, pirate ships, etc. If the can-
|
||
non marks a limit for the nomads, it is on the contrary because it implies an
|
||
economic investment that only a State apparatus can make (even commer-
|
||
cial cities do not suffice). The fact remains that for weapons other than fire-
|
||
arms, and even for the cannon, there is always a nomad on the horizon of a
|
||
given technological lineage***
|
||
Obviously, each case is controversial, as demonstrated by the debates on
|
||
the stirrup.87 The problem is that it is generally difficult to distinguish
|
||
between what comes from the nomads as such, and what they receive from
|
||
the empire they communicate with, conquer, or integrate with. There are
|
||
so many gray areas, intermediaries, and combinations between an imper-
|
||
ial army and a nomad war machine that it is often the case that things origi-
|
||
nate in the empire. The example of the saber is typical, and unlike the
|
||
stirrup, there is no longer any doubt. Although it is true that the Scythians
|
||
were the propagators of the saber, introducing it to the Hindus, Persians,
|
||
and Arabs, they were also its first victims, they started off on the receiving
|
||
end; it was invented by the Chinese empire of the Ch'in and Han dynasties,
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 405
|
||
|
||
the exclusive master of steel casting or crucible steel.88 This is a good exam-
|
||
ple to illustrate the difficulties facing modern archaeologists and his-
|
||
torians. Even archaeologists are not immune from a certain hatred or
|
||
contempt for the nomads. In the case of the saber, where the facts already
|
||
speak sufficiently in favor of an imperial origin, the best of the commenta-
|
||
tors finds it fitting to add that the Scythians could not have invented it at
|
||
any rate—poor nomads that they were—and that crucible steel necessarily
|
||
came from a sedentary milieu. But why follow the very old, official Chinese
|
||
version according to which deserters from the imperial army revealed the
|
||
secrets to the Scythians? And what can "revealing the secret" mean if the
|
||
Scythians were incapable of putting it to use, and understood nothing of all
|
||
that? Blame the deserters, why don't you. You don't make an atomic bomb
|
||
with a secret, any more than you make a saber if you are incapable of repro-
|
||
ducing it, and of integrating it under different conditions, of transferring it
|
||
to other assemblages. Propagation and diffusion are fully a part of the line
|
||
of innovation; they mark a bend in it. On top of that, why say that crucible
|
||
steel is necessarily the property of sedentaries or imperial subjects, when it
|
||
is first of all the invention of metallurgists? It is assumed that these metal-
|
||
lurgists were necessarily controlled by a State apparatus; but they also had
|
||
to enjoy a certain technological autonomy, and social clandestinity, so that,
|
||
even controlled, they did not belong to the State any more than they were
|
||
themselves nomads. There were no deserters who betrayed the secret, but
|
||
rather metallurgists who communicated it and made its adaptation and
|
||
propagation possible: an entirely different kind of "betrayal." In the last
|
||
analysis, what makes the discussions so difficult (both in the controversial
|
||
case of the stirrup and in the definite case of the saber) are not only the prej-
|
||
udices about the nomads but also the absence of a sufficiently elaborated
|
||
concept of the technological lineage (what defines a technological line or
|
||
continuum, and its variable extension, from a given standpoint?).
|
||
It would be useless to say that metallurgy is a science because it discovers
|
||
constant laws, for example, the melting point of a metal at all times and in
|
||
all places. For metallurgy is inseparable from several lines of variation: var-
|
||
iation between meteorites and indigenous metals; variation between ores
|
||
and proportions of metal; variation between alloys, natural and artificial;
|
||
variation between the operations performed upon a metal; variation
|
||
between the qualities that make a given operation possible, or that result
|
||
from a given operation (for example, twelve varieties of copper identified
|
||
and inventoried at Sumer by place of origin and degree of refinement).89
|
||
All of these variables can be grouped under two overall rubrics: singulari-
|
||
ties or spatiotemporal haecceities of different orders, and the operations
|
||
associated with them as processes of deformation or transformation;
|
||
affective qualities or traits of expression of different levels, corresponding to
|
||
406 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
these singularities and operations (hardness, weight, color, etc.). Let us
|
||
return to the example of the saber, or rather of crucible steel. It implies the
|
||
actualization of a first singularity, namely, the melting of the iron at high
|
||
temperature; then a second singularity, the successive decarbonations; cor-
|
||
responding to these singularities are traits of expression—not only the
|
||
hardness, sharpness, and finish, but also the undulations or designs traced
|
||
by the crystallization and resulting from the internal structure of the cast
|
||
steel. The iron sword is associated with entirely different singularities
|
||
because it is forged and not cast or molded, quenched and not air cooled,
|
||
produced by the piece and not in number; its traits of expression are neces-
|
||
sarily very different because it pierces rather than hews, attacks from the
|
||
front rather than from the side; even the expressive designs are obtained in
|
||
an entirely different way, by inlay.90 We may speak of a machinic phylum, or
|
||
technological lineage, wherever we find a constellation of singularities,
|
||
prolongable by certain operations, which converge, and make the operations
|
||
converge, upon one or several assignable traits of expression. If the singulari-
|
||
ties or operations diverge, in different materials or in the same material, we
|
||
must distinguish two different phyla: this is precisely the case for the iron
|
||
sword, descended from the dagger, and the steel saber, descended from the
|
||
knife. Each phylum has its own singularities and operations, its own quali-
|
||
ties and traits, which determine the relation of desire to the technical ele-
|
||
ment (the affects the saber "has" are not the same as those of the sword).
|
||
But it is always possible to situate the analysis on the level of singulari-
|
||
ties that are prolongable from one phylum to another, and to tie the two
|
||
phyla together. At the limit, there is a single phylogenetic lineage, a single
|
||
machinic phylum, ideally continuous: the flow of matter-movement, the
|
||
flow of matter in continuous variation, conveying singularities and traits
|
||
of expression. This operative and expressive flow is as much artificial as
|
||
natural: it is like the unity of human beings and Nature. But at the same
|
||
time, it is not realized in the here and now without dividing, differentiat-
|
||
ing. We will call an assemblage every constellation of singularities and
|
||
traits deducted from the flow—selected, organized, stratified—in such a
|
||
way as to converge (consistency) artificially and naturally; an assemblage,
|
||
in this sense, is a veritable invention. Assemblages may group themselves
|
||
into extremely vast constellations constituting "cultures," or even "ages";
|
||
within these constellations, the assemblages still differentiate the phyla or
|
||
the flow, dividing it into so many different phylas, of a given order, on a
|
||
given level, and introducing selective discontinuities in the ideal continu-
|
||
ity of matter-movement. The assemblages cut the phylum up into distinct,
|
||
differentiated lineages, at the same time as the machinic phylum cuts
|
||
across them all, taking leave of one to pick up again in another, or making
|
||
them coexist. A certain singularity embedded in the flanks of the phylum,
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 407
|
||
|
||
for example, the chemistry of carbon, will be brought up to the surface by a
|
||
given assemblage that selects, organizes, invents it, and through which all
|
||
or part of the phylum passes, at a given place at a given time. We may distin-
|
||
guish in every case a number of very different lines. Some of them,
|
||
phylogenetic lines, travel long distances between assemblages of various ages
|
||
and cultures (from the blowgun to the cannon? from the prayer wheel
|
||
to the propeller? from the pot to the motor?); others, ontogenetic lines, are
|
||
internal to one assemblage and link up its various elements or else cause
|
||
one element to pass, often after a delay, into another assemblage of a differ-
|
||
ent nature but of the same culture or age (for example, the horseshoe, which
|
||
spread through agricultural assemblages). It is thus necessary to take into
|
||
account the selective action of the assemblages upon the phylum, and the
|
||
evolutionary reaction of the phylum as the subterranean thread that passes
|
||
from one assemblage to another, or quits an assemblage, draws it forward
|
||
and opens it up. Vital impulsel Leroi-Gourhan has gone the farthest
|
||
toward a technological vitalism taking biological evolution in general as
|
||
the model for technical evolution: a Universal Tendency, laden with all of
|
||
the singularities and traits of expression, traverses technical and interior
|
||
milieus that refract or differentiate it in accordance with the singularities
|
||
and traits each of them retains, selects, draws together, causes to converge,
|
||
invents.91 There is indeed a machinic phylum in variation that creates the
|
||
technical assemblages, whereas the assemblages invent the various phyla.
|
||
A technological lineage changes significantly according to whether one
|
||
draws it upon the phylum or inscribes it in the assemblages; but the two are
|
||
inseparable.
|
||
So how are we to define this matter-movement, this matter-energy, this
|
||
matter-flow, this matter in variation that enters assemblages and leaves
|
||
them? It is a destratified, deterritorialized matter. It seems to us that
|
||
Husserl brought thought a decisive step forward when he discovered a
|
||
region of vague and material essences (in other words, essences that are
|
||
vagabond, anexact and yet rigorous), distinguishing them from fixed,
|
||
metric and formal, essences. We have seen that these vague essences are as
|
||
distinct from formed things as they are from formal essences. They con-
|
||
stitute fuzzy aggregates. They relate to a corporeality (materiality) that is
|
||
not to be confused either with an intelligible, formal essentiality or a sen-
|
||
sible, formed and perceived, thinghood. This corporeality has two char-
|
||
acteristics: on the one hand, it is inseparable from passages to the limit as
|
||
changes of state, from processes of deformation or transformation that oper-
|
||
ate in a space-time itself anexact and that act in the manner of events
|
||
(ablation, adjunction, projection . . .); on the other hand, it is inseparable
|
||
from expressive or intensive qualities, which can be higher or lower in
|
||
degree, and are produced in the manner of variable affects (resistance,
|
||
408 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
hardness, weight, color . . .)• There is thus an ambulant coupling, events-
|
||
affects, which constitutes the vague corporeal essence and is distinct from
|
||
the sedentary linkage, "fixed essence-properties of the thing deriving
|
||
from the essence," "formal essence-formed thing." Doubtless Husserl had a
|
||
tendency to make the vague essence a kind of intermediary between the
|
||
essence and the sensible, between the thing and the concept, a little like the
|
||
Kantian schema. Is not roundness a schematic or vague essence, intermediary
|
||
between rounded sensible things and the conceptual essence of the circle? In
|
||
effect, roundness exists only as a threshold-affect (neither flat nor pointed)
|
||
and as a limit-process (becoming rounded), through sensible things and tech-
|
||
nical agents, millstone, lathe, wheel, spinning wheel socket, etc. But it is only
|
||
"intermediary" to the extent that what is intermediary is autonomous,
|
||
initially stretching itself between things, and between thoughts, to estab-
|
||
lish a whole new relation between thoughts and things, a vague identity
|
||
between the two.
|
||
Certain distinctions proposed by Simondon can be compared to those
|
||
of Husserl. For Simondon exposes the technological insufficiency of the
|
||
matter-form model, in that it assumes a fixed form and a matter deemed
|
||
homogeneous. It is the idea of the law that assures the model's coherence,
|
||
since laws are what submit matter to this or that form, and conversely,
|
||
realize in matter a given property deduced from the form. But Simondon
|
||
demonstrates that the hylomorphic model leaves many things, active and
|
||
affective, by the wayside. On the one hand, to the formed or formable mat-
|
||
ter we must add an entire energetic materiality in movement, carrying sin-
|
||
gularities or haecceities that are already like implicit forms that are
|
||
topological, rather than geometrical, and that combine with processes of
|
||
deformation: for example, the variable undulations and torsions of the
|
||
fibers guiding the operation of splitting wood. On the other hand, to the
|
||
essential properties of the matter deriving from the formal essence we must
|
||
add variable intensive affects, now resulting from the operation, now on the
|
||
contrary making it possible: for example, wood that is more or less porous,
|
||
more or less elastic and resistant. At any rate, it is a question of surrender-
|
||
ing to the wood, then following where it leads by connecting operations to a
|
||
materiality, instead of imposing a form upon a matter: what one addresses
|
||
is less a matter submitted to laws than a materiality possessing a nomos.
|
||
One addresses less a form capable of imposing properties upon a matter
|
||
than material traits of expression constituting affects. Of course, it is
|
||
always possible to " translate" into a model that which escapes the model;
|
||
thus, one may link the materiality's power of variation to laws adapting a
|
||
fixed form and a constant matter to one another. But this cannot be done
|
||
without a distortion that consists in uprooting variables form the state of
|
||
continuous variation, in order to extract from them fixed points and con-
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 409
|
||
|
||
stant relations. Thus one throws the variables off, even changing the nature
|
||
of the equations, which cease to be immanent to matter-movement
|
||
(inequations, adequations). The question is not whether such a translation
|
||
is conceptually legitimate—it is—but what intuition gets lost in it. In
|
||
short, what Simondon criticizes the hylomorphic model for is taking form
|
||
and matter to be two terms defined separately, like the ends of two half-
|
||
chains whose connection can no longer be seen, like a simple relation of
|
||
molding behind which there is a perpetually variable, continuous modula-
|
||
tion that it is no longer possible to grasp.92 The critique of the hylomorphic
|
||
schema is based on "the existence, between form and matter, of a zone of
|
||
medium and intermediary dimension," of energetic, molecular dimen-
|
||
sion—a space unto itself that deploys its materiality through matter, a
|
||
number unto itself that propels its traits through form.
|
||
We always get back to this definition: the machinic phylum is ma-
|
||
teriality, natural or artificial, and both simultaneously; it is matter in
|
||
movement, in flux, in variation, matter as a conveyor of singularities and
|
||
traits of expression. This has obvious consequences: namely, this matter-
|
||
flow can only be followed. Doubtless, the operation that consists in follow-
|
||
ing can be carried out in one place: an artisan who planes follows the wood,
|
||
the fibers of the wood, without changing location. But this way of following
|
||
is only one particular sequence in a more general process. For artisans are
|
||
obliged to follow in another way as well, in other words, to go find the wood
|
||
where it lies, and to find the wood with the right kind of fibers. Otherwise,
|
||
they must have it brought to them: it is only because merchants take care of
|
||
one segment of the journey in reverse that the artisans can avoid making
|
||
the trip themselves. But artisans are complete only if they are also prospec-
|
||
tors; and the organization that separates prospectors, merchants, and arti-
|
||
sans already mutilates artisans in order to make "workers" of them. We will
|
||
therefore define the artisan as one who is determined in such a way as to
|
||
follow a flow of matter, a machinic phylum. The artisan is the itinerant, the
|
||
ambulant. To follow the flow of matter is to itinerate, to ambulate. It is
|
||
intuition in action. Of course, there are second-order itinerancies where it
|
||
is no longer a flow of matter that one prospects and follows, but, for exam-
|
||
ple, a market. Nevertheless, it is always a flow that is followed, even if the
|
||
flow is not always that of matter. And, above all, there are secondary
|
||
itinerancies, which derive from another "condition," even if they are nec-
|
||
essarily entailed by it. For example, a transhumant, whether a farmer or an
|
||
animal raiser, changes land after it is worn out, or else seasonally; but
|
||
transhumants only secondarily follow a land flow, because they undertake
|
||
a rotation meant from the start to return them to the point from which they
|
||
left, after the forest has regenerated, the land has rested, the weather has
|
||
changed. Transhumants do not follow a flow, they draw a circuit; they only
|
||
410 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
follow the part of the flow that enters into the circuit, even an ever-wid-
|
||
ening one. Transhumants are therefore itinerant only consequentially, or
|
||
become itinerant only when their circuit of land or pasture has been
|
||
exhausted, or when the rotation has become so wide that the flows escape
|
||
the circuit. Even the merchant is a transhumant, to the extent that mercan-
|
||
tile flows are subordinated to the rotation between a point of departure and
|
||
a point of arrival (go get-bring back, import-export, buy-sell). Whatever
|
||
the reciprocal implications, there are considerable differences between a
|
||
flow and a circuit. The migrant, we have seen, is something else again. And
|
||
the nomad is not primarily defined as an itinerant or as a transhumant, nor
|
||
as a migrant, even though nomads become these consequentially. The pri-
|
||
mary determination of nomads is to occupy and hold a smooth space: it is
|
||
this aspect that determines them as nomad (essence). On their own
|
||
account, they will be transhumants, or itinerants, only by virtue of the
|
||
imperatives imposed by the smooth spaces. In short, whatever the de facto
|
||
mixes between nomadism, itinerancy, and transhumance, the primary
|
||
concept is different in the three cases (smooth space, matter-flow, rota-
|
||
tion). It is only on the basis of the distinct concept that we can make a judg-
|
||
ment on the mix—on when it is produced, on the form in which it is
|
||
produced, and on the order in which it is produced.
|
||
But in the course of the preceding discussion, we have wandered from
|
||
the question: Why is the machinic phylum, the flow of matter, essentially
|
||
metallic or metallurgical? Here again, it is only the distinct concept that
|
||
can give us an answer, in that it shows that there is a special, primary rela-
|
||
tion between itinerance and metallurgy (deterritorialization). However,
|
||
the examples we took from Husserl and Simondon concerned wood and
|
||
clay as well as metals. Besides, are there not flows of grass, water, herds,
|
||
which form so many phyla or matters in movement? It is easier for us to
|
||
answer these questions now. For it is as if metal and metallurgy imposed
|
||
upon and raised to consciousness something that is only hidden or buried
|
||
in the other matters and operations. The difference is that elsewhere the
|
||
operations occur between two thresholds, one of which constitutes the
|
||
matter prepared for the operation, and the other the form to be incarnated
|
||
(for example, the clay and the mold). The hylomorphic model derives its
|
||
general value from this, since the incarnated form that marks the end of an
|
||
operation can serve as the matter for a new operation, but in a fixed order
|
||
marking a succession of thresholds. In metallurgy, on the other hand, the
|
||
operations are always astride the thresholds, so that an energetic
|
||
materiality overspills the prepared matter, and a qualitative deformation
|
||
or transformation overspills the form. 93 For example, quenching follows
|
||
forging and takes place after the form has been fixed. Or, to take another
|
||
example, in molding, the metallurgist in a sense works inside the mold. Or
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 411
|
||
|
||
again, steel that is melted and molded later undergoes a series of successive
|
||
decarbonations. Finally, metallurgy has the option of melting down and
|
||
reusing a matter to which it gives an ingot-form: the history of metal is
|
||
inseparable from this very particular form, which is not to be confused
|
||
with either a stock or a commodity; monetary value derives from it. More
|
||
generally, the metallurgical idea of the "reducer" expresses this double lib-
|
||
eration of a materiality in relation to a prepared matter, and of a transfor-
|
||
mation in relation to the form to be incarnated. Matter and form have
|
||
never seemed more rigid than in metallurgy; yet the succession of forms
|
||
tends to be replaced by the form of a continuous development, and the var-
|
||
iability of matters tends to be replaced by the matter of a continuous varia-
|
||
tion. If metallurgy has an essential relation with music, it is by virtue not
|
||
only of the sounds of the forge but also of the tendency within both arts to
|
||
bring into its own, beyond separate forms, a continuous development of
|
||
form, and beyond variable matters, a continuous variation of matter: a
|
||
widened chromaticism sustains both music and metallurgy; the musical
|
||
smith was the first "transformer."94 In short, what metal and metallurgy
|
||
bring to light is a life proper to matter, a vital state of matter as such, a mate-
|
||
rial vitalism that doubtless exists everywhere but is ordinarily hidden or
|
||
covered, rendered unrecognizable, dissociated by the hylomorphic model.
|
||
Metallurgy is the consciousness or thought of the matter-flow, and metal
|
||
the correlate of this consciousness. As expressed in panmetallism, metal is
|
||
coextensive to the whole of matter, and the whole of matter to metallurgy.
|
||
Even the waters, the grasses and varieties of wood, the animals are popu-
|
||
lated by salts or mineral elements. Not everything is metal, but metal is
|
||
everywhere. Metal is the conductor of all matter. The machinic phylum is
|
||
metallurgical, or at least has a metallic head, as its itinerant probe-head or
|
||
guidance device. And thought is born more from metal than from stone:
|
||
metallurgy is minor science in person, "vague" science or the phenom-
|
||
enology of matter. The prodigious idea of Nanorganic Life—the very same
|
||
idea Worringer considered the barbarian idea par excellence95—was the
|
||
invention, the intuition of metallurgy. Metal is neither a thing nor an
|
||
organism, but a body without organs. The "Northern, or Gothic, line" is
|
||
above all a mining or metallic line delimiting this body. The relation
|
||
between metallurgy and alchemy reposes not, as Jung believed, on the sym-
|
||
bolic value of metal and its correspondence with an organic soul but on the
|
||
immanent power of corporeality in all matter, and on the esprit de corps
|
||
accompanying it.
|
||
The first and primary itinerant is the artisan. But artisans are neither
|
||
hunters, farmers, nor animal raisers. Neither are they winnowers or pot-
|
||
ters, who only secondarily take up craft activity. Rather, artisans are those
|
||
who follow the matter-flow as pure productivity: therefore in mineral
|
||
412 O 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
form, and not in vegetable or animal form. They are not of the land, or of
|
||
the soil, but of the subsoil. Because metal is the pure productivity of matter,
|
||
those who follow metal are producers of objects par excellence. As demon-
|
||
strated by V. Gordon Childe, the metallurgist is the first specialized arti-
|
||
san, and in this respect forms a collective body (secret societies, guilds,
|
||
journeymen's associations). Artisans-metallurgists are itinerants because
|
||
they follow the matter-flow of the subsoil. Of course metallurgists have
|
||
relations with "the others," those of the soil, land, and sky. They have rela-
|
||
tions with the farmers of the sedentary communities, and with the celestial
|
||
functionaries of the empire who overcode those communities; in fact, they
|
||
need them to survive, they depend on an imperial agricultural stockpile for
|
||
their very sustenance.96 But in their work, they have relations with the for-
|
||
est dwellers, and partially depend on them: they must establish their work-
|
||
shops near the forest in order to obtain the necessary charcoal. In their
|
||
space, they have relations with the nomads, since the subsoil unites the
|
||
ground (sol) of smooth space and the land of striated space: there are no
|
||
mines in the alluvial valleys of the empire-dominated farmers; it is neces-
|
||
sary to cross deserts, approach the mountains; and the question of control
|
||
over the mines always involves nomadic peoples. Every mine is a line of
|
||
flight that is in communication with smooth spaces—there are parallels
|
||
today in the problems with oil.
|
||
Archaeology and history remain strangely silent on this question of the
|
||
control over the mines. There have been empires with a strong metallurgi-
|
||
cal organization that had no mines; the Near East lacked tin, so necessary
|
||
for the fabrication of bronze. Large quantities of metal arrived in ingot
|
||
form, and from very far away (for instance, tin from Spain or even from
|
||
Cornwall). So complex a situation implies not only a strong imperial
|
||
bureaucracy and elaborate long-distance commercial circuits; it also
|
||
implies a shifting politics, in which States confront an outside, in which
|
||
very different peoples confront one another, or else reach some accommo-
|
||
dation on particular aspects of the control of mines (extraction, charcoal,
|
||
workshops, transportation). It is not enough to say that there are wars and
|
||
mining expeditions; or to invoke "a Eurasian synthesis of the nomadic
|
||
workshops from the approaches of China to the tip of Britanny," and
|
||
remark that "the nomadic populations had been in contact with the princi-
|
||
pal metallurgical centers of the ancient world since prehistoric times."97
|
||
What is needed is a better knowledge of the nomads' relations with these
|
||
centers, with the smiths they themselves employed or frequented, with
|
||
properly metallurgical peoples or groups who were their neighbors. What
|
||
was the situation in the Caucasus and in the Altai? In Spain and North
|
||
Africa? Mines are a source of flow, mixture, and escape with few equiva-
|
||
lents in history. Even when they are well controlled by an empire that owns
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 413
|
||
|
||
them (as in the Chinese and Roman empires), there is a major movement of
|
||
clandestine exploitation, and of miners' alliances either with nomad and
|
||
barbarian incursions or peasant revolts. The study of myths, and even eth-
|
||
nographic considerations on the status of smiths, divert us from these
|
||
political questions. Mythology and ethnology do not have the right method
|
||
in this regard. It is too often asked how the others "react" to the smith, and
|
||
as a result, one succumbs to the usual platitudes about the ambivalence of
|
||
feelings; it is said that the smith is simultaneously honored, feared, and
|
||
scorned—more or less scorned among the nomads, more or less honored
|
||
among the sedentaries.98 But this loses sight of the reasons for this situa-
|
||
tion, of the specificity of the smiths themselves, of the nonsymmetrical
|
||
relation they entertain with the nomads and the sedentaries, the type of
|
||
affects they invent (metallic affect). Before looking at the feelings of others
|
||
toward smiths, it is necessary to evaluate the smiths themselves as Other;
|
||
as such, they have different affective relations with the sedentaries and the
|
||
nomads.
|
||
There are no nomadic or sedentary smiths. Smiths are ambulant, itiner-
|
||
ant. Particularly important in this respect is the way in which smiths live:
|
||
their space is neither the striated space of the sedentary nor the smooth
|
||
space of the nomad. Smiths may have a tent, they may have a house; they
|
||
inhabit them in the manner of an "ore bed" (gite, shelter, home, mineral
|
||
deposit), like metal itself, in the manner of a cave or a hole, a hut half or all
|
||
underground. They are cave dwellers not by nature but by artistry and
|
||
need." A splendid text by Elie Faure evokes the infernal progress of the
|
||
itinerant peoples of India as they bore holes in space and create the fantas-
|
||
tic forms corresponding to these breakthroughs, the vital forms of
|
||
nonorganic life: "There at the shore of the sea, at the base of a mountain,
|
||
they encountered a great wall of granite. Then they all entered the granite;
|
||
in its shadows they lived, loved, worked, died, were born, and, three or four
|
||
centuries afterward, they came out again, leagues away, having traversed
|
||
the mountain. Behind them they left the emptied rock, its galleries hol-
|
||
lowed out in every direction, its sculptured, chiseled walls, its natural or
|
||
artificial pillars turned into a deep lacework with ten thousand horrible or
|
||
charming figures.. . . Here man confesses unresistingly his strength and his
|
||
nothingness. He does not exact the affirmation of a determined ideal from
|
||
form.... He extracts it rough from formlessness, according to the dictates
|
||
of the formless. He utilizes the indentations and accidents of the rock."100
|
||
Metallurgical India. Transpierce the mountains instead of scaling them,
|
||
excavate the land instead of striating it, bore holes in space instead of keep-
|
||
ing it smooth, turn the earth into swiss cheese. An image from the film
|
||
Strike [by Eisenstein] presents a holey space where a disturbing group of
|
||
414 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Holey Space
|
||
|
||
people are rising, each emerging from his or her hole as if from a field
|
||
mined in all directions. The sign of Cain is the corporeal and affective sign
|
||
of the subsoil, passing through both the striated land of sedentary space
|
||
and the nomadic ground (sol) of smooth space without stopping at either
|
||
one, the vagabond sign of itinerancy, the double theft and double betrayal
|
||
of the metallurgist, who shuns agriculture at the same time as animal rais-
|
||
ing. Must we reserve the name Cainite for these metallurgical peoples who
|
||
haunt the depths of History? Prehistoric Europe was crisscrossed by the
|
||
battle-ax people, who came in off the steppes like a detached metallic
|
||
branch of the nomads, and the people known for their bell-shaped pottery,
|
||
the beaker people, originating in Andalusia, a detached branch of mega-
|
||
lithic agriculture.101 Strange peoples, dolicocephalics and brachycephalics
|
||
who mix and spread across all of Europe. Are they the ones who kept up the
|
||
mines, boring holes in European space from every direction, constituting
|
||
our European space?
|
||
Smiths are not nomadic among the nomads and sedentary among the
|
||
sedentaries, nor half-nomadic among the nomads, half-sedentary among
|
||
sedentaries. Their relation to others results from their internal itinerancy,
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 415
|
||
|
||
from their vague essence, and not the reverse. It is in their specificity, it is
|
||
by virtue of their itinerancy, by virtue of their inventing a holey space, that
|
||
they necessarily communicate with the sedentaries and with the nomads
|
||
(and with others besides, with the transhumant forest dwellers). They are
|
||
in themselves double: a hybrid, an alloy, a twin formation. As Griaule says,
|
||
Dogon smiths are not "impure" but "mixed," and it is because they are
|
||
mixed that they are endogamous, that they do not intermarry with the
|
||
pure, who have a simplified progeny while they reconstitute a twin prog-
|
||
eny.102 Childe demonstrates that metallurgists are necessarily doubled,
|
||
that they exist two times, once as captured by and maintained within the
|
||
apparatus of the oriental empire, again in the Aegean world, where they
|
||
were much more mobile and much freer. But the two segments cannot be
|
||
separated, simply by relating each of them to their particular context. The
|
||
metallurgist belonging to an empire, the worker, presupposes a metallur-
|
||
gist-prospector, however far away; and the prospector ties in with a mer-
|
||
chant, who brings the metal to the first metallurgist. In addition, the metal
|
||
is worked on by each segment, and the ingot-form is common to them all:
|
||
we must imagine less separate segments than a chain of mobile workshops
|
||
constituting, from hole to hole, a line of variation, a gallery. Thus the met-
|
||
allurgists' relation to the nomads and the sedentaries also passes through
|
||
the relations they have with other metallurgists.103 This hybrid metallur-
|
||
gist, a weapon- and toolmaker, communicates with the sedentaries and
|
||
with the nomads at the same time. Holey space itself communicates with
|
||
smooth space and striated space. In effect, the machinic phylum or the
|
||
metallic line passes through all of the assemblages: nothing is more
|
||
deterritorialized than matter-movement. But it is not at all in the same
|
||
way, and the two communications are not symmetrical. Worringer, in the
|
||
domain of aesthetics, said that the abstract line took on two quite different
|
||
expressions, one in barbarian Gothic art, the other in the organic classical
|
||
art. Here, we would say that the phylum simultaneously has two different
|
||
modes of liaison: it is always connected to nomad space, whereas it conju-
|
||
gates with sedentary space. On the side of the nomadic assemblages and
|
||
war machines, it is a kind of rhizome, with its gaps, detours, subterranean
|
||
passages, stems, openings, traits, holes, etc. On the other side, the seden-
|
||
tary assemblages and State apparatuses effect a capture of the phylum, put
|
||
the traits of expression into a form or a code, make the holes resonate
|
||
together, plug the lines of flight, subordinate the technological operation to
|
||
the work model, impose upon the connections a whole regime of arbor-
|
||
escent conjunctions.
|
||
AXIOM III. The nomad war machine is the form of expression, of which
|
||
itinerant metallurgy is the correlative form of content.
|
||
416 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Content Expression
|
||
|
||
Substance Holey space Smooth space
|
||
(machinic phylum
|
||
or matter-flow)
|
||
|
||
Form Itinerant Nomad war
|
||
metallurgy machine
|
||
|
||
PROPOSITION IX. War does not necessarily have the battle as its object,
|
||
and more important, the war machine does not necessarily have war as
|
||
its object, although war and the battle may be its necessary result
|
||
(under certain conditions).
|
||
We now come to three successive problems. First, is the battle the
|
||
"object" of war? But also, is war the "object" of the war machine? And
|
||
finally, to what extent is the war machine the "object" of the State appara-
|
||
tus? The ambiguity of the first two problems is certainly due to the term
|
||
"object," but implies their dependency on the third. We must nevertheless
|
||
approach these problems gradually, even if we are reduced to multiplying
|
||
examples. The first question, that of the battle, requires an immediate dis-
|
||
tinction to be made between two cases: when a battle is sought, and when it
|
||
is essentially avoided by the war machine. These two cases in no way coin-
|
||
cide with the offensive and the defensive. But war in the strict sense
|
||
(according to a conception of it that culminated in Foch) does seem to have
|
||
the battle as its object, whereas guerrilla warfare explicitly aims for the
|
||
nonbattle. However, the development of war into the war of movement,
|
||
and into total war, also places the notion of the battle in question, as much
|
||
from the offensive as the defensive points of view: the concept of the
|
||
nonbattle seems capable of expressing the speed of a flash attack, and the
|
||
counterspeed of an immediate response.104 Conversely, the development
|
||
of guerilla warfare implies a moment when, and forms under which, a bat-
|
||
tle must be effectively sought, in connection with exterior and interior
|
||
"support points." And it is true that guerrilla warfare and war proper are
|
||
constantly borrowing each other's methods and that the borrowings run
|
||
equally in both directions (for example, stress has often been laid on the
|
||
inspirations land-based guerrilla warfare received from maritime war). All
|
||
we can say is that the battle and the nonbattle are the double object of war,
|
||
according to a criterion that does not coincide with the offensive and the
|
||
defensive, or even with war proper and guerrilla warfare.
|
||
That is why we push the question further back, asking if war itself is the
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 417
|
||
|
||
object of the war machine. It is not at all obvious. To the extent that war
|
||
(with or without the battle) aims for the annihilation or capitulation of
|
||
enemy forces, the war machine does not necessarily have war as its object
|
||
(for example, the raid can be seen as another object, rather than as a partic-
|
||
ular form of war). But more generally, we have seen that the war machine
|
||
was the invention of the nomad, because it is in its essence the constitutive
|
||
element of smooth space, the occupation of this space, displacement
|
||
within this space, and the corresponding composition of people: this is its
|
||
sole and veritable positive object (nomos). Make the desert, the steppe,
|
||
grow; do not depopulate it, quite the contrary. If war necessarily results, it
|
||
is because the war machine collides with States and cities, as forces (of stri-
|
||
ation) opposing its positive object: from then on, the war machine has as its
|
||
enemy the State, the city, the state and urban phenomenon, and adopts as
|
||
its objective their annihilation. It is at this point that the war machine
|
||
becomes war: annihilate the forces of the State, destroy the State-form. The
|
||
Attila, or Genghis Khan, adventure clearly illustrates this progression
|
||
from the positive object to the negative object. Speaking like Aristotle, we
|
||
would say that war is neither the condition nor the object of the war
|
||
machine, but necessarily accompanies or completes it; speaking like
|
||
Derrida, we would say that war is the "supplement" of the war machine. It
|
||
may even happen that this supplementarity is comprehended through a
|
||
progressive, anxiety-ridden revelation. Such, for example, was the adven-
|
||
ture of Moses: leaving the Egyptian State behind, launching into the desert,
|
||
he begins by forming a war machine, on the inspiration of the old past of
|
||
the nomadic Hebrews and on the advice of his father-in-law, who came
|
||
from the nomads. This is the machine of the Just, already a war machine,
|
||
but one that does not yet have war as its object. Moses realizes, little by lit-
|
||
tle, in stages, that war is the necessary supplement of that machine, because
|
||
it encounters or must cross cities and States, because it must send ahead
|
||
spies (armed observation), then perhaps take things to extremes (war of
|
||
annihilation). Then the Jewish people experience doubt, and fear that they
|
||
are not strong enough; but Moses also doubts, he shrinks before the revela-
|
||
tion of this supplement. And it will be Joshua, not Moses, who is charged
|
||
with waging war. Finally, speaking like Kant, we would say that the relation
|
||
between war and the war machine is necessary but "synthetic" (Yahweh is
|
||
necessary for the synthesis).
|
||
The question of war, in turn, is pushed further back and is subordinated
|
||
to the relations between the war machine and the State apparatus. States
|
||
were not the first to make war: war, of course, is not a phenomenon one
|
||
finds in the universality of Nature, as nonspecific violence. But war is not
|
||
the object of States, quite the contrary. The most archaic States do not even
|
||
seem to have had a war machine, and their domination, as we will see, was
|
||
418 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
based on other agencies (comprising, rather, the police and prisons). It is
|
||
safe to assume that the intervention of an extrinsic or nomad war machine
|
||
that counterattacked and destroyed the archaic but powerful States was
|
||
one of the mysterious reasons for their sudden annihilation. But the State
|
||
learns fast. One of the biggest questions from the point of view of universal
|
||
history is: How will the State appropriate the war machine, that is, consti-
|
||
tute one for itself, in conformity with its size, its domination, and its aims?
|
||
And with what risks? (What we call a military institution, or army, is not at
|
||
all the war machine in itself, but the form under which it is appropriated by
|
||
the State.) In order to grasp the paradoxical character of such an undertak-
|
||
ing, we must recapitulate the hypothesis in its entirety. (1) The war
|
||
machine is that nomad invention that in fact has war not as its primary
|
||
object but as its second-order, supplementary or synthetic objective, in the
|
||
sense that it is determined in such a way as to destroy the State-form and
|
||
city-form with which it collides. (2) When the State appropriates the war
|
||
machine, the latter obviously changes in nature and function, since it is
|
||
afterward directed against the nomad and all State destroyers, or else
|
||
expresses relations between States, to the extent that a State undertakes
|
||
exclusively to destroy another State or impose its aims upon it. (3) It is pre-
|
||
cisely after the war machine has been appropriated by the State in this way
|
||
that it tends to take war for its direct and primary object, for its "analytic"
|
||
object (and that war tends to take the battle for its object). In short, it is at
|
||
one and the same time that the State apparatus appropriates a war
|
||
machine, that the war machine takes war as its object, and that war be-
|
||
comes subordinated to the aims of the State.
|
||
This question of appropriation is so varied historically that it is neces-
|
||
sary to distinguish between several kinds of problems. The first concerns
|
||
the possibility of the operation: it is precisely because war is only the sup-
|
||
plementary or synthetic object of the nomad war machine that it experi-
|
||
ences the hesitation that proves fatal to it, and that the State apparatus for
|
||
its part is able to lay hold of war and thus turn the war machine back against
|
||
the nomads. The hesitation of the nomad is legendary: What is to be done
|
||
with the lands conquered and crossed? Return them to the desert, to the
|
||
steppe, to open pastureland? Or let a State apparatus survive that is capa-
|
||
ble of exploiting them directly, at the risk of becoming, sooner or later, sim-
|
||
ply a new dynasty of that apparatus: sooner or later because Genghis Khan
|
||
and his followers were able to hold out for a long time by partially integrat-
|
||
ing themselves into the conquered empires, while at the same time main-
|
||
taining a smooth space on the steppes to which the imperial centers were
|
||
subordinated. That was their genius, the Pax Mongolica. It remains the
|
||
case that the integration of the nomads into the conquered empires was one
|
||
of the most powerful factors of appropriation of the war machine by the
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 419
|
||
|
||
State apparatus: the inevitable danger to which the nomads succumbed.
|
||
But there is another danger as well, the one threatening the State when it
|
||
appropriates the war machine (all States have felt the weight of this danger,
|
||
as well as the risks this appropriation represents for them). Tamerlane is
|
||
the extreme example. He was not Genghis Khan's successor but his exact
|
||
opposite: it was Tamerlane who constructed a fantastic war machine
|
||
turned back against the nomads, but who, by that very fact, was obliged to
|
||
erect a State apparatus all the heavier and more unproductive since it
|
||
existed only as the empty form of appropriation of that machine.105 Turn-
|
||
ing the war machine back against the nomads may constitute for the State a
|
||
danger as great as that presented by nomads directing the war machine
|
||
against States.
|
||
A second type of problem concerns the concrete forms the appropria-
|
||
tion of the war machine takes: Mercenary or territorial? A professional
|
||
army or a conscripted army? A special body or national recruiting? Not
|
||
only are these formulas not equivalent, but there are all the possible mixes
|
||
between them. Perhaps the most relevant distinction to make, or the most
|
||
general one, would be: Is there merely "encastment" of the war machine,
|
||
or "appropriation" proper? The capture of the war machine by the State
|
||
apparatus took place following two paths, by encasting a society of warri-
|
||
ors (who arrived from without or arose from within), or on the contrary
|
||
by constituting it in accordance with rules corresponding to civil society
|
||
as a whole. Once again, there is passage and transition from one formula
|
||
to another. Last, the third type of problem concerns the means of appro-
|
||
priation. We must consider from this standpoint the various data pertain-
|
||
ing to the fundamental aspects of the State apparatus: territoriality, work
|
||
or public works, taxation. The constitution of a military institution or an
|
||
army necessarily implies a territorialization of the war machine, in other
|
||
words, the granting of land ("colonial" or domestic), which can take very
|
||
diverse forms. But at the same time, fiscal regimes determine both the
|
||
nature of the services and taxes owed by the beneficiary warriors, and
|
||
especially the kind of civil tax to which all or part of society is subject for
|
||
the maintenance of the army. And the State enterprise of public works
|
||
must be reorganized along the lines of a "laying out of the territory" in
|
||
which the army plays a determining role, not only in the case of fortresses
|
||
and fortified cities, but also in strategic communication, the logistical
|
||
structure, the industrial infrastructure, etc. (the role and function of the
|
||
Engineer in this form of appropriation).106
|
||
Let us compare this hypothesis as a whole with Clausewitz's formula:
|
||
"War is the continuation of politics by other means." As we know, this for-
|
||
mula is itself extracted from a theoretical and practical, historic and
|
||
transhistoric, aggregate whose parts are interconnected. (1) There is a pure
|
||
420 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
concept of war as absolute, unconditioned war, an Idea not given in experi-
|
||
ence (bring down or "upset" the enemy, who is assumed to have no other
|
||
determination, with no political, economic, or social considerations
|
||
entering in). (2) What is given are real wars as submitted to State aims;
|
||
States are better or worse "conductors" in relation to absolute war, and in
|
||
any case condition its realization in experience. (3) Real wars swing
|
||
between two poles, both subject to State politics: the war of annihilation,
|
||
which can escalate to total war (depending on the objectives of the annihi-
|
||
lation) and tends to approach the unconditioned concept via an ascent to
|
||
extremes; and limited war, which is no "less" a war, but one that effects a
|
||
descent toward limiting conditions, and can de-escalate to mere "armed
|
||
observation."107
|
||
In the first place, the distinction between absolute war as Idea and real
|
||
wars seems to us to be of great importance, but only if a different criterion
|
||
than that of Clausewitz is applied. The pure Idea is not that of the abstract
|
||
elimination of the adversary but that of a war machine that does not have
|
||
war as its object and that only entertains a potential or supplementary syn-
|
||
thetic relation with war. Thus the nomad war machine does not appear to
|
||
us to be one case of real war among others, as in Clausewitz, but on the con-
|
||
trary the content adequate to the Idea, the invention of the Idea, with its
|
||
own objects, space, and composition of the nomos. Nevertheless it is still
|
||
an Idea, and it is necessary to retain the concept of the pure Idea, even
|
||
though this war machine was realized by the nomads. It is the nomads,
|
||
rather, who remain an abstraction, an Idea, something real and nonactual,
|
||
and for several reasons: first, because the elements of nomadism, as we
|
||
have seen, enter into de facto mixes with elements of migration, itinerancy,
|
||
and transhumance; this does not affect the purity of the concept, but intro-
|
||
duces always mixed objects, or combinations of space and composition,
|
||
which react back upon the war machine from the beginning. Second, even
|
||
in the purity of its concept, the nomad war machine necessarily effectuates
|
||
its synthetic relation with war as supplement, uncovered and developed in
|
||
opposition to the State-form, the destruction of which is at issue. But that is
|
||
exactly it; it does not effectuate this supplementary object or this synthetic
|
||
relation without the State, for its part, finding the opportunity to appropri-
|
||
ate the war machine, and the means of making war the direct object of this
|
||
turned-around machine (thus the integration of the nomad into the State is
|
||
a vector traversing nomadism from the very beginning, from the first act of
|
||
war against the State).
|
||
The question is therefore less the realization of war than the appropria-
|
||
tion of the war machine. It is at the same time that the State apparatus
|
||
appropriates the war machine, subordinates it to its "political" aims, and
|
||
gives it war as its direct object. And it is one and the same historical ten-
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 421
|
||
|
||
dency that causes State to evolve from a triple point of view: going from fig-
|
||
ures of encastment to forms of appropriation proper, going from limited
|
||
war to so-called total war, and transforming the relation between aim and
|
||
object. The factors that make State war total war are closely connected to
|
||
capitalism: it has to do with the investment of constant capital in equip-
|
||
ment, industry, and the war economy, and the investment of variable capi-
|
||
tal in the population in its physical and mental aspects (both as warmaker
|
||
and as victim of war).108 Total war is not only a war of annihilation but
|
||
arises when annihilation takes as its "center" not only the enemy army, or
|
||
the enemy State, but the entire population and its economy. The fact that
|
||
this double investment can be made only under prior conditions of limited
|
||
war illustrates the irresistible character of the capitalist tendency to
|
||
develop total war.' °9 It is therefore true that total war remains subordinated
|
||
to State political aims and merely realizes the maximal conditions of the
|
||
appropriation of the war machine by the State apparatus. But it is also true
|
||
that when total war becomes the object of the appropriated war machine,
|
||
then at this level in the set of all possible conditions, the object and the aim
|
||
enter into new relations that can reach the point of contradiction. This
|
||
explains Clausewitz's vacillation when he asserts at one point that total war
|
||
remains a war conditioned by the political aim of States, and at another
|
||
that it tends to effectuate the Idea of unconditioned war. In effect, the aim
|
||
remains essentially political and determined as such by the State, but the
|
||
object itself has become unlimited. We could say that the appropriation
|
||
has changed direction, or rather that States tend to unleash, reconstitute,
|
||
an immense war machine of which they are no longer anything more than
|
||
the opposable or apposed parts. This worldwide war machine, which in a
|
||
way "reissues" from the States, displays two successive figures: first, that of
|
||
fascism, which makes war an unlimited movement with no other aim than
|
||
itself; but fascism is only a rough sketch, and the second, postfascist, figure
|
||
is that of a war machine that takes peace as its obj ect directly, as the peace of
|
||
Terror or Survival. The war machine reforms a smooth space that now
|
||
claims to control, to surround the entire earth. Total war itself is surpassed,
|
||
toward a form of peace more terrifying still. The war machine has taken
|
||
charge of the aim, worldwide order, and the States are now no more than
|
||
objects or means adapted to that machine. This is the point at which
|
||
Clausewitz's formula is effectively reversed; to be entitled to say that poli-
|
||
tics is the continuation of war by other means, it is not enough to invert the
|
||
order of the words as if they could be spoken in either direction; it is neces-
|
||
sary to follow the real movement at the conclusion of which the States, hav-
|
||
ing appropriated a war machine, and having adapted it to their aims,
|
||
reimpart a war machine that takes charge of the aim, appropriates the
|
||
States, and assumes increasingly wider political functions.110
|
||
422 D 1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE
|
||
|
||
Doubtless, the present situation is highly discouraging. We have
|
||
watched the war machine grow stronger and stronger, as in a science fiction
|
||
story; we have seen it assign as its objective a peace still more terrifying
|
||
than fascist death; we have seen it maintain or instigate the most terrible of
|
||
local wars as parts of itself; we have seen it set its sights on a new type of
|
||
enemy, no longer another State, or even another regime, but the "unspeci-
|
||
fied enemy"; we have seen it put its counterguerrilla elements into place, so
|
||
that it can be caught by surprise once, but not twice. Yet the very conditions
|
||
that make the State or World war machine possible, in other words, con-
|
||
stant capital (resources and equipment) and human variable capital,
|
||
continually recreate unexpected possibilities for counterattack, unfore-
|
||
seen initiatives determining revolutionary, popular, minority, mutant
|
||
machines. The definition of the Unspecified Enemy testifies to this: "mul-
|
||
tiform, maneuvering and omnipresent... of the moral, political, subver-
|
||
sive or economic order, etc.," the unassignable material Saboteur or
|
||
human Deserter assuming the most diverse forms."' The first theoretical
|
||
element of importance is the fact that the war machine has many varied
|
||
meanings, and this is precisely because the war machine has an extremely
|
||
variable relation to war itself. The war machine is not uniformly defined,
|
||
and comprises something other than increasing quantities of force. We
|
||
have tried to define two poles of the war machine: at one pole, it takes war
|
||
for its object and forms a line of destruction prolongable to the limits of the
|
||
universe. But in all of the shapes it assumes here—limited war, total war,
|
||
worldwide organization—war represents not at all the supposed essence of
|
||
the war machine but only, whatever the machine's power, either the set of
|
||
conditions under which the States appropriate the machine, even going so
|
||
far as to project it as the horizon of the world, or the dominant order of
|
||
which the States themselves are now only parts. The other pole seemed to be
|
||
the essence; it is when the war machine, with infinitely lower "quantities,"
|
||
has as its object not war but the drawing of a creative line of flight, the com-
|
||
position of a smooth space and of the movement of people in that space. At
|
||
this other pole, the machine does indeed encounter war, but as its supple-
|
||
mentary or synthetic object, now directed against the State and against the
|
||
worldwide axiomatic expressed by States.
|
||
We thought it possible to assign the invention of the war machine to the
|
||
nomads. This was done only in the historical interest of demonstrating that
|
||
the war machine as such was invented, even if it displayed from the begin-
|
||
ning all of the ambiguity that caused it to enter into composition with the
|
||
other pole, and swing toward it from the start. However, in conformity with
|
||
the essence, the nomads do not hold the secret: an "ideological," scientific,
|
||
or artistic movement can be a potential war machine, to the precise extent
|
||
to which it draws, in relation to zphylum, a plane of consistency, a creative
|
||
1227: TREATISE ON NOMADOLOGY—THE WAR MACHINE D 423
|
||
|
||
line of flight, a smooth space of displacement. It is not the nomad who
|
||
defines this constellation of characteristics; it is this constellation that
|
||
defines the nomad, and at the same time the essence of the war machine. If
|
||
guerrilla warfare, minority warfare, revolutionary and popular war are in
|
||
conformity with the essence, it is because they take war as an object all the
|
||
more necessary for being merely "supplementary": they can make war only
|
||
on the condition that they simultaneously create something else, if only new
|
||
nonorganic social relations. The difference between the two poles is great,
|
||
even, and especially, from the point of view of death: the line of flight that
|
||
creates, or turns into a line of destruction; the plane of consistency that
|
||
constitutes itself, even piece by piece, or turns into a plan(e) of organiza-
|
||
tion and domination. We are constantly reminded that there is communi-
|
||
cation between these two lines or planes, that each takes nourishment from
|
||
the other, borrows from the other: the worst of the world war machines
|
||
reconstitutes a smooth space to surround and enclose the earth. But the
|
||
earth asserts its own powers of deterritorialization, its lines of flight, its
|
||
smooth spaces that live and blaze their way for a new earth. The question is
|
||
not one of quantities but of the incommensurable character of the quanti-
|
||
ties that confront one another in the two kinds of war machine, according
|
||
to the two poles. War machines take shape against the apparatuses that
|
||
appropriate the machine and make war their affair and their object: they
|
||
bring connections to bear against the great conjunction of the apparatuses
|
||
of capture or domination.
|
||
13. 7000 B.C.: Apparatus of Capture
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
PROPOSITION X. The State and its poles.
|
||
Let us return to Dumezil's theses: (1) Political sovereignty has two poles,
|
||
the fearsome magician-emperor, operating by capture, bonds, knots, and
|
||
nets, and the jurist-priest-king, proceeding by treaties, pacts, contracts (the
|
||
couples Varuna-Mitra, Odin-Tyr, Wotan-Tiwaz, Uranus-Zeus, Romulus-
|
||
Numa . . .); (2) the war function is exterior to political sovereignty and is
|
||
equally distinct from both its poles (Indra or Thor or Tullus Hostilius. . .)•'
|
||
1. The State apparatus is thus animated by a curious rhythm, which is
|
||
first of all a great mystery: that of the Binder-Gods or magic emperors,
|
||
One-Eyed men emitting from their single eye signs that capture, tie knots at
|
||
a distance. The jurist-kings, on the other hand, are One-Armed men who
|
||
raise their single arm as an element of right and technology, the law and the
|
||
tool. In the succession of men of State, look always for the One-Eyed and
|
||
the One-Armed, Horatius Codes and Mucius Scaevola (de Gaulle and
|
||
424
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 425
|
||
|
||
Pompidou?). This is not to say that one has exclusive right to signs, the
|
||
other to tools. The fearsome emperor is already the master of large-scale
|
||
works; the wise king takes up and transforms the entire regime of signs.
|
||
What it means is that the combination, signs-tools, constitutes the differ-
|
||
ential trait of political sovereignty, or the complementarity of the State.2
|
||
2. Of course, the two men of State are always getting mixed up in affairs
|
||
of war. But either the magic emperor sends to battle warriors who are not
|
||
his own, whom he takes into his service by capture; or, more important,
|
||
when he makes his appearance on the battlefield, he suspends the use of
|
||
weapons, he throws his net over the warriors, his single eye throws them
|
||
into petrified catatonia, "he binds without combat," he encasts the war
|
||
machine (this State capture is not to be confused with the captures of war:
|
||
conquests, prisoners, spoils).3 As for the other pole, the jurist-king is a great
|
||
organizer of war; but he gives it laws, lays out a field for it, makes it princi-
|
||
pled, imposes a discipline upon it, subordinates it to political ends. He
|
||
turns the war machine into a military institution, he appropriates the war
|
||
machine for the State apparatus.4 We should not be too hasty in speaking of
|
||
a softening, a humanization: on the contrary, this is perhaps when the war
|
||
machine has only one remaining object, that of war itself. Violence is found
|
||
everywhere, but under different regimes and economies. The violence of
|
||
the magic emperor: his knot, his net, his way of "making his moves once
|
||
and for all" ... The violence of the jurist-king: his way of beginning over
|
||
again every move, always with attention to ends, alliances, and laws... All
|
||
things considered, the violence of the war machine might appear softer and
|
||
more supple than that of the State apparatus because it does not yet have
|
||
war as its "object," because it eludes both poles of the State. That is why the
|
||
man of war, in his exteriority, is always protesting the alliances and pacts of
|
||
the jurist-king, as well as severing the bonds of the magic emperor. He is
|
||
equally an unbinder and a betrayer: twice the traitor.5 He has another econ-
|
||
omy, another cruelty, but also another justice, another pity. To the signs
|
||
and tools of the State, the man of war opposes his weapons and jewelry.
|
||
Once again, who could say which is better and which is worse? It is true that
|
||
war kills, and hideously mutilates. But it is especially true after the State
|
||
has appropriated the war machine. Above all, the State apparatus makes
|
||
the mutilation, and even death, come first. It needs them preaccom-
|
||
plished, for people to be born that way, crippled and zombielike. The myth
|
||
of the zombie, of the living dead, is a work myth and not a war myth. Muti-
|
||
lation is a consequence of war, but it is a necessary condition, a presupposi-
|
||
tion of the State apparatus and the organization of work (hence the native
|
||
infirmity not only of the worker but also of the man of State himself,
|
||
whether of the One-Eyed or the One-Armed type): "The brutal exhibition
|
||
of severed flesh shocked me.... Wasn't it an integral part of technical per-
|
||
426 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
fection and the intoxication of it. . . ? Mankind has waged wars since the
|
||
world began, but I can't remember one single example in the Iliad where
|
||
the loss of an arm or a leg is reported. Mythology reserved mutilation for
|
||
monsters, for human beasts of the race of Tantalus or Procrustes.... It is an
|
||
optical illusion to attribute these mutilations to accidents. Actually, acci-
|
||
dents are the result of mutilations that took place long ago in the embryo of
|
||
our world; and the increase in amputations is one of the symptoms bearing
|
||
witness to the triumph of the morality of the scalpel. The loss occurred long
|
||
before it was visibly taken into account."6 The State apparatus needs, at its
|
||
summit as at its base, predisabled people, preexisting amputees, the still-
|
||
born, the congenitally infirm, the one-eyed and one-armed.
|
||
Thus there is a tempting three-part hypothesis: the war machine is
|
||
"between" the two poles of political sovereignty and assures the passage
|
||
from one pole to the other. It is indeed in that order, 1-2-3, that things seem
|
||
to present themselves in myth and history. Take two versions of the One-
|
||
Eyed and the One-Armed gods analyzed by Dumezil: (1) the god Odin, who
|
||
has a single eye, ties up the wolf of war and holds him in his magic bond; (2)
|
||
but the wolf is wary and has at its disposal all its power of exteriority; (3) the
|
||
god Tyr gives the wolf a legal security by leaving one of his hands in the
|
||
wolfs mouth so the wolf can bite it off if it does not succeed in extricating
|
||
itself from the bond. (1) Horatius Codes, the One-Eyed, using only his
|
||
face, his grimace and magic power, prevents the Etruscan commander
|
||
from attacking Rome; (2) the war commander then decides to lay siege; (3)
|
||
Mucius Scaevola takes a political tack, offering his hand as a security in
|
||
order to persuade the warrior that it would be best to abandon the siege and
|
||
conclude a pact.
|
||
In an entirely different, historical, context, Marcel Detienne suggests an
|
||
analogous schema in three moments for ancient Greece: (1) The magic sov-
|
||
ereign, the "Master of Truth," has at his disposal a war machine that doubt-
|
||
less does not originate with him, and which enjoys a relative autonomy
|
||
within his empire; (2) this class of warriors has its own rules, defined by
|
||
"isonomy," an isotropic space, and a "milieu" (war spoils are in the middle
|
||
[au milieu], he who speaks places himself in the middle of the assembly);
|
||
this is another space, the rules are different from those of the sovereign,
|
||
who captures and speaks from on high; (3) the hoplite reform, the ground-
|
||
work for which was laid in the warrior class, spread throughout the social
|
||
body, promoting the formation of an army of citizen-soldiers; at the same
|
||
time, the last vestiges of the imperial pole of sovereignty were replaced by
|
||
the juridical pole of the city-state (with isonomy as its law, and isotropy as
|
||
its space).7 Thus in every case, the war machine seems to intervene
|
||
"between" the two poles of the State apparatus, assuring and necessitating
|
||
the passage from one to the other.
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 427
|
||
|
||
We cannot, however, assign this schema a causal meaning (the authors
|
||
cited do not do so). In the first place, the war machine explains nothing; for
|
||
it is either exterior to the State, and directed against it; or else it already
|
||
belongs to the State, encasted and appropriated, and presupposes it. If the
|
||
war machine has a part in the evolution of the State, it is therefore necessar-
|
||
ily in conjunction with other internal factors. And this is the second point:
|
||
if there is an evolution of the State, the second pole, the evolved pole, must
|
||
be in resonance with the first, it must continually recharge it in some way,
|
||
and the State must have only one milieu of interiority; in other words, it
|
||
must have a unity of composition, in spite of all the differences in organiza-
|
||
tion and development among States. It is even necessary for each State to
|
||
have both poles, as the essential moments of its existence, even though the
|
||
organization of the two varies. Third, if we call this interior essence or this
|
||
unity of the State "capture," we must say that the words "magic capture"
|
||
describe the situation well because it always appears as preaccomplished
|
||
and self-presupposing; but how is this capture to be explained then, if it
|
||
leads back to no distinct assignable cause? That is why theses on the origin
|
||
of the State are always tautological. At times, exogenous factors, tied to war
|
||
and the war machine, are invoked; at times endogenous factors, thought to
|
||
engender private property, money, etc.; and at times specific factors,
|
||
thought to determine the formation of "public functions." All three of
|
||
these theses are found in Engels, in relation to a conception of the diversity
|
||
of the roads to Domination. But they beg the question. War produces the
|
||
State only if at least one of the two parts is a preexistent State; and the
|
||
organization of war is a State factor only if that organization is a part of the
|
||
State. Either the State has no war machine (and has policemen and jailers
|
||
before having soldiers), or else it has one, but in the form of a military insti-
|
||
tution or public function.8 Similarly, private property presupposes State
|
||
public property, it slips through its net; and money presupposes taxation. It
|
||
is even more difficult to see how public functions could have existed before
|
||
the State they imply. We are always brought back to the idea of a State that
|
||
comes into the world fully formed and rises up in a single stroke, the uncon-
|
||
ditioned Urstaat.
|
||
PROPOSITION XI. Which comes first?
|
||
We shall call the first pole of capture imperial or despotic. It corresponds
|
||
to Marx's Asiatic formation. Archaeology discovers it everywhere, often
|
||
lost in oblivion, at the horizon of all systems or States—not only in Asia,
|
||
but also in Africa, America, Greece, Rome. Immemorial Urstaat, dating as
|
||
far back as Neolithic times, and perhaps farther still. Following the Marxist
|
||
description: a State apparatus is erected upon the primitive agricultural
|
||
communities, which already have lineal-territorial codes; but it overcodes
|
||
428 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
them, submitting them to the power of a despotic emperor, the sole and
|
||
transcendent public-property owner, the master of the surplus or the stock,
|
||
the organizer of large-scale works (surplus labor), the source of public func-
|
||
tions and bureaucracy. This is the paradigm of the bond, the knot. Such is
|
||
the regime of signs of the State: overcoding, or the Signifier. It is a system of
|
||
machinic enslavement the first "megamachine" in the strict sense, to use
|
||
Mumford's term. A prodigious success in a single stroke; other States will
|
||
be mere runts measured against this model. The emperor-despot is not a
|
||
king or a tyrant; these will come into existence only as a function of private
|
||
property once it has arisen.9 In the imperial regime, everything is public:
|
||
ownership of land is communal, each individual is an owner only insofar as
|
||
he or she is a member of the community; the eminent property of the des-
|
||
pot is that of the supposed Unity of the communities; and the functionaries
|
||
themselves have land only if it comes with their position (although the
|
||
position may be hereditary). Money may exist, notably in the form of the
|
||
tax that the functionaries owe the emperor, but it is not used for buying-
|
||
selling, since land does not exist as an alienable commodity. This is the
|
||
regime of the nexum, the bond: something is lent or even given without a
|
||
transfer of ownership, without private appropriation, and the compensa-
|
||
tion for it does not come in the form of interest or profit for the donor but
|
||
rather as a "rent" that accrues to him, accompanying the lending of some-
|
||
thing for another's use or the granting of revenue.10
|
||
Marx, the historian, and Childe, the archaeologist, are in agreement on
|
||
the following point: the archaic imperial State, which steps in to overcode
|
||
agricultural communities, presupposes at least a certain level of devel-
|
||
opment of these communities' productive forces since there must be a
|
||
potential surplus capable of constituting a State stock, of supporting a spe-
|
||
cialized handicrafts class (metallurgy), and of progressively giving rise to
|
||
public functions. That is why Marx links the archaic State to a certain
|
||
"mode of production." However, the origin of these Neolithic States is still
|
||
being pushed back in time. What is at issue when the existence of near-
|
||
Paleolithic empires is conjectured is not simply the quantity of time; the
|
||
qualitative problem changes. Catal Hiiyiik, in Anatolia, makes possible a
|
||
singularly reinforced imperial paradigm: it is a stock of uncultivated seeds
|
||
and relatively tame animals from different territories that performs, and
|
||
makes it possible to perform, at first by chance, hybridizations and selec-
|
||
tions/ram which agriculture and small-scale animal raising arise.11 It is
|
||
easy to see the significance of this change in the givens of the problem. It is
|
||
no longer the stock that presupposes a potential surplus, but the other way
|
||
around. It is no longer the State that presupposes advanced agricultural
|
||
communities and developed forces of production. On the contrary, the
|
||
State is established directly in a milieu of hunter-gatherers having no prior
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 429
|
||
|
||
agriculture or metallurgy, and it is the State that creates agriculture, animal
|
||
raising, and metallurgy; it does so first on its own soil, then imposes them
|
||
upon the surrounding world. It is not the country that progressively creates
|
||
the town but the town that creates the country. It is not the State that pre-
|
||
supposes a mode of production; quite the opposite, it is the State that
|
||
makes production a "mode." The last reasons for presuming a progressive
|
||
development are invalidated. Like seeds in a sack: It all begins with a
|
||
chance intermixing. The "state and urban revolution" may be Paleolithic,
|
||
not Neolithic as Childe believed.
|
||
Evolutionism has been challenged in many different ways (zigzag move-
|
||
ments, stages skipped here or there, irreducible overall breaks). We have
|
||
seen in particular how Pierre Clastres tried to shatter the evolutionist
|
||
framework by means of the following two theses: (1) societies termed prim-
|
||
itive are not societies without a State, in the sense that they failed to reach a
|
||
certain stage, but are counter-State societies organizing mechanisms that
|
||
ward off the State-form, which make its crystallization impossible; (2)
|
||
when the State arises, it is in the form of an irreducible break, since it is not
|
||
the result of a progressive development of the forces of production (even
|
||
the "Neolithic revolution" cannot be defined in terms of an economic
|
||
infrastructure).12 However, one does not depart from evolutionism by
|
||
establishing a clean break. In the final state of his work, Clastres main-
|
||
tained the preexistence and autarky of counter-State societies, and attrib-
|
||
uted their workings to an overmysterious presentiment of what they
|
||
warded off and did not yet exist. More generally, one marvels at the bizarre
|
||
indifference that ethnology manifests for archaeology. It seems as though
|
||
ethnologists, fenced off in their respective territories, are willing to com-
|
||
pare their territories in an abstract, or structural, way, if it comes to that,
|
||
but refuse to set them against archaeological territories that would com-
|
||
promise their autarky. They take snapshots of their primitives but rule out
|
||
in advance the coexistence and superposition of the two maps, the
|
||
ethnographical and the archaeological. Catal Hiiyiik, however, would have
|
||
had a zone of influence extending two thousand miles; how can the ever-
|
||
recurring problem of the relation of coexistence between primitive socie-
|
||
ties and empires, even those of Paleolithic times, be left unattended to? As
|
||
long as archaeology is passed over, the question of the relation between eth-
|
||
nology and history is reduced to an idealist confrontation, and fails to
|
||
wrest itself from the absurd theme of society without history, or society
|
||
against history. Everything is not of the State precisely because there have
|
||
been States always and everywhere. Not only does writing presuppose the
|
||
State, but so do speech and language. The self-sufficiency, autarky, inde-
|
||
pendence, preexistence of primitive communities, is an ethnological
|
||
dream: not that these communities necessarily depend on States, but they
|
||
430 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
coexist with them in a complex network. It is plausible that "from the
|
||
beginning" primitive societies have maintained distant ties to one another,
|
||
not just short-range ones, and that these ties were channeled through
|
||
States, even if States effected only a partial and local capture of them.
|
||
Speech communities and languages, independently of writing, do not
|
||
define closed groups of people who understand one another but primarily
|
||
determine relations between groups who do not understand one another: if
|
||
there is language, it is fundamentally between those who do not speak the
|
||
same tongue. Language is made for that, for translation, not for communi-
|
||
cation. And in primitive societies there are as many tendencies that "seek"
|
||
the State, as many vectors working in the direction of the State, as there are
|
||
movements within the State or outside it that tend to stray from it or guard
|
||
themselves against it, or else to stimulate its evolution, or else already to
|
||
abolish it: everything coexists, in perpetual interaction.
|
||
Economic evolutionism is an impossibility; even a ramified evolu-
|
||
tion, "gatherers—hunters—animal breeders—farmers-industrialists," is
|
||
hardly believable. An evolutionary ethnology is no better: "nomads—
|
||
seminomads—sedentaries." Nor an ecological evolutionism: "dispersed
|
||
autarky of local groups—villages and small towns—cities—States." All we
|
||
need to do is combine these abstract evolutions to make all of evolutionism
|
||
crumble; for example, it is the city that creates agriculture, without going
|
||
through small towns. To take another example, the nomads do not precede
|
||
the sedentaries; rather, nomadism is a movement, a becoming that affects
|
||
sedentaries, just as sedentarization is a stoppage that settles the nomads.
|
||
Griaznov has shown in this connection that the most ancient nomadism
|
||
can be accurately attributed only to populations that abandoned their
|
||
semiurban sedentarity, or their primitive itineration, to set off nomadiz-
|
||
ing.13 It is under these conditions that the nomads invented the war
|
||
machine, as that which occupies or fills nomad space and opposes towns
|
||
and States, which its tendency is to abolish. Primitive peoples already had
|
||
mechanisms of war that converged to prevent the State formation; but
|
||
these mechanisms change when they gain autonomy in the form of a spe-
|
||
cific nomadism machine that strikes back against the States. We cannot,
|
||
however, infer from this even a zigzag evolution that would go from primi-
|
||
tive peoples to States, from States to nomad war machines; or at least the
|
||
zigzagging is not successive but passes through the loci of a topology that
|
||
defines primitive societies here, States there, and elsewhere war machines.
|
||
And even when the State appropriates the war machine, once again chang-
|
||
ing its nature, it is a phenomenon of transport, of transfer, and not one of
|
||
evolution. The nomad exists only in becoming, and in interaction; the
|
||
same goes for the primitive. All history does is to translate a coexistence
|
||
of becomings into a succession. And collectivities can be transhumant,
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 431
|
||
|
||
semisedentary, sedentary, or nomadic, without by the same token being
|
||
preparatory stages for the State, which is already there, elsewhere or
|
||
beside.
|
||
Can it at least be said that the hunter-gatherers are the "true" primitives
|
||
and remain in spite of it all the basis or minimal presupposition of the State
|
||
formation, however far back in time we place it? This point of view can be
|
||
maintained only at the price of a very inadequate conception of causality.
|
||
And it is true that the human sciences, with their materialist, evolutionary,
|
||
and even dialectical schemas, lag behind the richness and complexity of
|
||
causal relations in physics, or even in biology. Physics and biology present
|
||
us with reverse causalities that are without finality but testify nonetheless
|
||
to an action of the future on the present, or of the present on the past, for
|
||
example, the convergent wave and the anticipated potential, which imply
|
||
an inversion of time. More than breaks or zigzags, it is these reverse causal-
|
||
ities that shatter evolution. Similarly, in the present context, it is not ade-
|
||
quate to say that the Neolithic or even Paleolithic State, once it appeared,
|
||
reacted back on the surrounding world of the hunter-gatherers; it was
|
||
already acting before it appeared, as the actual limit these primitive socie-
|
||
ties warded off, or as the point toward which they converged but could not
|
||
reach without self-destructing. These societies simultaneously have vec-
|
||
tors moving in the direction of the State, mechanisms warding it off, and a
|
||
point of convergence that is repelled, set outside, as fast as it is approached.
|
||
To ward off is also to anticipate. Of course, it is not at all in the same way
|
||
that the State appears in existence, and that it preexists in the capacity of a
|
||
warded-off limit; hence its irreducible contingency. But in order to give a
|
||
positive meaning to the idea of a "presentiment" of what does not yet exist,
|
||
it is necessary to demonstrate that what does not yet exist is already in
|
||
action, in a different form than that of its existence. Once it has appeared,
|
||
the State reacts back on the hunter-gatherers, imposing upon them agricul-
|
||
ture, animal raising, an extensive division of labor, etc.; it acts, therefore, in
|
||
the form of a centrifugal or divergent wave. But before appearing, the State
|
||
already acts in the form of the convergent or centripetal wave of the hunter-
|
||
gatherers, a wave that cancels itself out precisely at the point of convergence
|
||
marking the inversion of signs or the appearance of the State (hence the
|
||
functional and intrinsic instability of these primitive societies).14 It is nec-
|
||
essary from this standpoint to conceptualize the contemporaneousness or
|
||
coexistence of the two inverse movements, of the two directions of
|
||
time—of the primitive peoples "before" the State, and of the State "after"
|
||
the primitive peoples—as if the two waves that seem to us to exclude or suc-
|
||
ceed each other unfolded simultaneously in an "archaeological," micropo-
|
||
litical, micrological, molecular field.
|
||
There exist collective mechanisms that simultaneously ward off and
|
||
432 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
anticipate the formation of a central power. The appearance of a central
|
||
power is thus a function of a threshold or degree beyond which what is
|
||
anticipated takes on consistency or fails to, and what is conjured away
|
||
ceases to be so and arrives. This threshold of consistency, or of constraint,
|
||
is not evolutionary but rather coexists with what has yet to cross it. More-
|
||
over, a distinction must be made between different thresholds of consis-
|
||
tency: the town and the State, however complementary, are not the same
|
||
thing. The "urban revolution" and the "state revolution" may coincide but
|
||
do not meld. In both cases, there is a central power, but it does not assume
|
||
the same figure. Certain authors have made a distinction between the pala-
|
||
tial or imperial system (temple-palace), and the urban, town system. In
|
||
both cases there is a town, but in one case the town is an outgrowth of the
|
||
palace or temple, and in the other case the palace, the temple, is a concre-
|
||
tion of the town. In one case, the town par excellence is the capital, and in
|
||
the other it is the metropolis. Sumer already attests to a town solution, as
|
||
opposed to the imperial solution of Egypt. But to an even greater extent, it
|
||
was the Mediterranean world, with the Pelasgians, Phoenicians, Greeks,
|
||
Carthaginians, that created an urban fabric distinct from the imperial
|
||
organisms of the Orient.15 Once again, the question is one not of evolution
|
||
but of two thresholds of consistency that are themselves coexistent. They
|
||
differ in several respects.
|
||
The town is the correlate of the road. The town exists only as a function
|
||
of circulation, and of circuits; it is a remarkable point on the circuits that
|
||
create it, and which it creates. It is defined by entries and exits; something
|
||
must enter it and exit from it. It imposes a frequency. It effects a polariza-
|
||
tion of matter, inert, living or human; it causes the phylum, the flow, to pass
|
||
through specific places, along horizontal lines. It is a phenomenon of
|
||
transconsistency, a network, because it is fundamentally in contact with
|
||
other towns. It represents a threshold of deterritorialization, because what-
|
||
ever the material involved, it must be deterritorialized enough to enter the
|
||
network, to submit to the polarization, to follow the circuit of urban and
|
||
road receding. The maximum deterritorialization appears in the tendency
|
||
of maritime and commercial towns to separate off from the backcountry,
|
||
from the countryside (Athens, Carthage, Venice). The commercial charac-
|
||
ter of the town has often been emphasized, but the commerce in question is
|
||
also spiritual, as in a network of monasteries or temple-cities. Towns are
|
||
circuit-points of every kind, which enter into counterpoint along horizon-
|
||
tal lines; they effect a complete but local, town-by-town, integration. Each
|
||
one constitutes a central power, but it is a power of polarization or of the
|
||
middle (milieu), of forced coordination. That is why this kind of power has
|
||
egalitarian pretensions, regardless of the form it takes: tyrannical, demo-
|
||
cratic, oligarchic, aristocratic. Town power invents the idea of the magis-
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 433
|
||
|
||
trature, which is very different from the State civil-service sector (fonction-
|
||
nariat).16 Who can say where the greatest civil violence resides?
|
||
The State indeed proceeds otherwise: it is a phenomenon of intracon-
|
||
sistency. It makes points resonate together, points that are not necessarily
|
||
already town-poles but very diverse points of order, geographic, ethnic, lin-
|
||
guistic, moral, economic, technological particularities. It makes the town
|
||
resonate with the countryside. It operates by stratification; in other words,
|
||
it forms a vertical, hierarchized aggregate that spans the horizontal lines in
|
||
a dimension of depth. In retaining given elements, it necessarily cuts off
|
||
their relations with other elements, which become exterior, it inhibits,
|
||
slows down, or controls those relations; if the State has a circuit of its own,
|
||
it is an internal circuit dependent primarily upon resonance, it is a zone of
|
||
recurrence that isolates itself from the remainder of the network, even if in
|
||
order to do so it must exert even stricter controls over its relations with that
|
||
remainder. The question is not to find out whether what is retained is natu-
|
||
ral or artificial (boundaries), because in any event there is deterritorializa-
|
||
tion. But in this case deterritorialization is a result of the territory itself
|
||
being taken as an object, as a material to stratify, to make resonate. Thus
|
||
the central power of the State is hierarchical, and constitutes a civil-service
|
||
sector; the center is not in the middle (au milieu), but on top, because the
|
||
only way it can recombine what it isolates is through subordination. Of
|
||
course, there is a multiplicity of States no less than of towns, but it is not the
|
||
same type of multiplicity: there are as many States as there are vertical
|
||
cross sections in a dimension of depth, each separated from the others,
|
||
whereas the town is inseparable from the horizontal network of towns.
|
||
Each State is a global (not local) integration, a redundancy of resonance
|
||
(not of frequency), an operation of the stratification of the territory (not of
|
||
the polarization of the milieu).
|
||
It is possible to reconstruct how primitive societies warded off both
|
||
thresholds while at the same time anticipating them. Levi-Strauss has
|
||
shown that the same villages are susceptible to two presentations, one
|
||
segmentary and egalitarian, the other encompassing and hierarchized.
|
||
These are like two potentials, one anticipating a central point common to
|
||
two horizontal segments, the other anticipating a central point external to
|
||
a straight line.17 Primitive societies do not lack formations of power; they
|
||
even have many of them. But what prevents the potential central points
|
||
from crystallizing, from taking on consistency, are precisely those mecha-
|
||
nisms that keep the formations of power both from resonating together in a
|
||
higher point and from becoming polarized at a common point: the circles
|
||
are not concentric, and the two segments require a third segment through
|
||
which to communicate.18 This is the sense in which primitive societies
|
||
have crossed neither the town-threshold nor the State-threshold.
|
||
434 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
If we now turn our attention to the two thresholds of consistency, it is
|
||
clear that they imply a deterritorialization in relation to the primitive ter-
|
||
ritorial codes. It is futile to ask which came first, the city or the State, the
|
||
urban or state revolution, because the two are in reciprocal presupposi-
|
||
tion. Both the melodic lines of the towns and the harmonic cross sections
|
||
of the States are necessary to effect the striation of space. The only ques-
|
||
tion that arises is the possibility that there may be an inverse relation at
|
||
the heart of this reciprocity. For although the archaic imperial State nec-
|
||
essarily included towns of considerable size, they remained more or less
|
||
strictly subordinated to the State, depending on how complete the State's
|
||
monopoly over foreign trade was. On the other hand, the town tended to
|
||
break free when the State's overcoding itself provoked decoded flows. A
|
||
decoding was coupled with the deterritorialization, and amplified it; the
|
||
necessary receding was then achieved through a certain autonomy of the
|
||
towns, or else directly through corporative and commercial towns freed
|
||
from the State-form. Thus towns arose that no longer had a connection to
|
||
their own land, because they assured the trade between empires, or better,
|
||
constituted on their own a free commercial network with other towns.
|
||
There is therefore an adventure specific to towns in the zones where the
|
||
most intense decoding occurs, for example, the ancient Aegean world or
|
||
the Western world of the Middle Ages and the Renaissance. Could it not
|
||
be said that capitalism is the fruit of the towns, and arises when an urban
|
||
receding tends to replace State overcoding? This, however, was not the
|
||
case. The towns did not create capitalism. The banking and commercial
|
||
towns, being unproductive and indifferent to the backcountry, did not
|
||
perform a receding without also inhibiting the general conjunction of
|
||
decoded flows. If it is true that they anticipated capitalism, they in turn
|
||
did not anticipate it without also warding it off. They do not cross this
|
||
new threshold. Thus it is necessary to expand the hypothesis of mecha-
|
||
nisms both anticipatory and inhibiting: these mechanisms are at play not
|
||
only in primitive societies but also in the conflict of towns "against" the
|
||
State and "against" capitalism. Finally, it was through the State-form and
|
||
not the town-form that capitalism triumphed; this occurred when the
|
||
Western States became models of realization for an axiomatic of decoded
|
||
flows, and in that way resubjugated the towns. As Braudel says, there were
|
||
"always two runners, the state and the town"—two forms and two speeds
|
||
of deterritorialization—and "the state usually won. . . . everywhere in
|
||
Europe, it disciplined the towns with instinctive relentlessness, whether
|
||
or not it used violence.. . . [The states] caught up with the forward gallop
|
||
of the towns."19 But the relation is a reciprocal one: if it is the modern
|
||
State that gives capitalism its models of realization, what is thus rea-
|
||
lized is an independent, worldwide axiomatic that is like a single City,
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 435
|
||
|
||
megalopolis, or "megamachine" of which the States are parts, or neigh-
|
||
borhoods.
|
||
We define social formations by machinic processes and not by modes of
|
||
production (these on the contrary depend on the processes). Thus primi-
|
||
tive societies are defined by mechanisms of prevention-anticipation; State
|
||
societies are defined by apparatuses of capture; urban societies, by instru-
|
||
ments of polarization; nomadic societies, by war machines; and finally
|
||
international, or rather ecumenical, organizations are defined by the
|
||
encompassment of heterogeneous social formations. But precisely because
|
||
these processes are variables of coexistence that are the object of a social
|
||
topology, the various corresponding formations are coexistent. And they
|
||
coexist in two fashions, extrinsically and intrinsically. Primitive societies
|
||
cannot ward off the formation of an empire or State without anticipating it,
|
||
and they cannot anticipate it without its already being there, forming part
|
||
of their horizon. And States cannot effect a capture unless what is captured
|
||
coexists, resists in primitive societies, or escapes under new forms, as
|
||
towns or war machines. . . The numerical composition of the war machine
|
||
is superposed upon the primitive lineal organization and simultaneously
|
||
opposes the geometric organization of the State and the physical organiza-
|
||
tion of the town. It is this extrinsic coexistence—interaction—that is
|
||
brought to its own expression in international aggregates. For these obvi-
|
||
ously did not wait for capitalism before forming: as early as Neolithic
|
||
times, even Paleolithic, we find traces of ecumenical organizations that tes-
|
||
tify to the existence of long-distance trade, and simultaneously cut across
|
||
the most varied of social formations (as we have seen in the case of metal-
|
||
lurgy). The problem of diffusion, or of diffusionism, is badly formulated if
|
||
one assumes a center at which the diffusion would begin. Diffusion occurs
|
||
only through the placing in communication of potentials of very different
|
||
orders: all diffusion happens in the in-between, goes between, like every-
|
||
thing that "grows" of the rhizome type. An international ecumenical
|
||
organization does not proceed from an imperial center that imposes itself
|
||
upon and homogenizes an exterior milieu; neither is it reducible to rela-
|
||
tions between formations of the same order, between States, for example
|
||
(the League of Nations, the United Nations). On the contrary, it constitutes
|
||
an intermediate milieu between the different coexistent orders. Therefore
|
||
it is not exclusively commercial or economic, but is also religious, artistic,
|
||
etc. From this standpoint, we shall call an international organization any-
|
||
thing that has the capacity to move through diverse social formations
|
||
simultaneously: States, towns, deserts, war machines, primitive societies.
|
||
The great commercial formations in history do not simply have city-poles,
|
||
but also primitive, imperial, and nomadic segments through which they
|
||
pass, perhaps issuing out again in another form. Samir Amin is totally cor-
|
||
436 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
rect in saying that there can be no economic theory of international rela-
|
||
tions, even economic ones, because they sit astride heterogeneous forma-
|
||
tions.20 The point of departure for ecumenical organization is not a State,
|
||
even an imperial one; the imperial State is only one part of it, and it consti-
|
||
tutes a part of it in its own mode, according to its own order, which consists
|
||
in capturing everything it can. It does not proceed by progressive homoge-
|
||
nization, or by totalization, but by the taking on of consistency or the con-
|
||
solidation of the diverse as such. For example, monotheistic religion is
|
||
distinguished from territorial worship by its pretension to universality. But
|
||
this pretension is not homogenizing, it makes itself felt only by spreading
|
||
everywhere; this was the case with Christianity, which became imperial
|
||
and urban, but not without giving rise to bands, deserts, war machines of
|
||
its own.21 Similarly, there is no artistic movement that does not have its
|
||
towns and empires, but also its nomads, bands, and primitives.
|
||
It might be objected that, at least in the case of capitalism, international
|
||
economic relations, and at the limit all international relations, tend toward
|
||
the homogenization of social formations. One could cite not only the cold
|
||
and concerted destruction of primitive societies but also the fall of the last
|
||
despotic formations, for example, the Ottoman Empire, which met capi-
|
||
talist demands with too much resistance and inertia. This objection, how-
|
||
ever, is only partially accurate. To the extent that capitalism constitutes an
|
||
axiomatic (production for the market), all States and all social formations
|
||
tend to become isomorphic in their capacity as models of realization: there
|
||
is but one centered world market, the capitalist one, in which even the
|
||
so-called socialist countries participate. Worldwide organization thus
|
||
ceases to pass "between" heterogeneous formations since it assures the
|
||
isomorphy of those formations. But it would be wrong to confuse
|
||
isomorphy with homogeneity. For one thing, isomorphy allows, and even
|
||
incites, a great heterogeneity among States (democratic, totalitarian, and,
|
||
especially, "socialist" States are not facades). For another thing, the
|
||
international capitalist axiomatic effectively assures the isomorphy of
|
||
the diverse formations only where the domestic market is developing and
|
||
expanding, in other words, in "the center." But it tolerates, in fact it
|
||
requires, a certain peripheral polymorphy, to the extent that it is not satu-
|
||
rated, to the extent that it actively repels its own limits;22 this explains the
|
||
existence, at the periphery, of heteromorphic social formations, which cer-
|
||
tainly do not constitute vestiges or transitional forms since they realize an
|
||
ultramodern capitalist production (oil, mines, plantations, industrial
|
||
equipment, steel, chemistry), but which are nonetheless precapitalist, or
|
||
extracapitalist, owing to other aspects of their production and to the forced
|
||
inadequacy of their domestic market in relation to the world market.23
|
||
When international organization becomes the capitalist axiomatic, it con-
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 437
|
||
|
||
tinues to imply a heterogeneity of social formations, it gives rise to and
|
||
organizes its "Third World."
|
||
There is not only an external coexistence of formations but also an
|
||
intrinsic coexistence of machinic processes. Each process can also function
|
||
at a "power" other than its own; it can be taken up by a power correspond-
|
||
ing to another process. The State as apparatus of capture has a power of
|
||
appropriation; but this power does not consist solely in capturing all that it
|
||
can, all that is possible, of a matter defined as phylum. The apparatus of
|
||
capture also appropriates the war machine, the instruments of polariza-
|
||
tion, and the anticipation-prevention mechanisms. This is to say, con-
|
||
versely, that anticipation-prevention mechanisms have a high power of
|
||
transference: they are at work not only in primitive societies, but move into
|
||
the towns that ward off the State-form, into the States that ward off capital-
|
||
ism, into capitalism itself, insofar as it wards off and repels its own limits.
|
||
And they are not satisfied to switch over to other powers but form new focal
|
||
points of resistance and contagion, as we have seen in the case of "band"
|
||
phenomena, which have their own towns, their own brand of international-
|
||
ism, etc. Similarly, war machines have a power of metamorphosis, which of
|
||
course allows them to be captured by States, but also to resist that capture
|
||
and rise up again in other forms, with other "objects" besides war (revolu-
|
||
tion?). Each power is a force of deterritorialization that can go along with
|
||
the others or go against them (even primitive societies have their vectors of
|
||
deterritorialization). Each process can switch over to other powers, but
|
||
also subordinate other processes to its own power.
|
||
PROPOSITION XII. Capture.
|
||
Is it possible to conceive of an "exchange" between separate primitive
|
||
groups, independent of any reference to such notions as stock, labor, and
|
||
commodity? It seems that a modified marginalism provides a basis for a
|
||
hypothesis. For the interest of marginalism resides not in its economic the-
|
||
ory, which is extremely weak, but in a logical power that makes Jevons, for
|
||
example, a kind of Lewis Carroll of economics. Take two abstract groups,
|
||
one of which (A) gives seeds and receives axes, while the other (B) does the
|
||
opposite. What is the collective evaluation of the objects based on? It is
|
||
based on the idea of the last objects received, or rather receivable, on each
|
||
side. By "last" or "marginal" we must understand not the most recent, nor
|
||
the final, but rather the penultimate, the next to the last, in other words, the
|
||
last one before the apparent exchange loses its appeal for the exchangers, or
|
||
forces them to modify their respective assemblages, to enter another
|
||
assemblage. We will consider that the farmer-gatherer group A, which
|
||
receives axes, has an "idea" of the number of axes that would force it to
|
||
change assemblage; and the manufacturing group B, of the quantity of
|
||
438 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
seeds that would force it to change assemblage. We may say, then, that the
|
||
seed-ax relation is determined by the last quantity of seeds (for group B)
|
||
corresponding to the last ax (for group A). The last as the object of a collec-
|
||
tive evaluation determines the value of the entire series. It marks the exact
|
||
point at which the assemblage must reproduce itself, begin a new operation
|
||
period or a new cycle, lodge itself on another territory, and beyond which
|
||
the assemblage could not continue as such. This is indeed a next-to-the-
|
||
last, a penultimate, since it comes before the ultimate. The ultimate is
|
||
when the assemblage must change its nature: B would have to plant the
|
||
excess seeds. A would have to increase the rhythm of its own plantings and
|
||
remain on the same land.
|
||
We can now posit a conceptual difference between the "limit" and the
|
||
"threshold": the limit designates the penultimate marking a necessary
|
||
rebeginning, and the threshold the ultimate marking an inevitable change.
|
||
It is an economic given of every enterprise to include an evaluation of the
|
||
limit beyond which the enterprise would have to modify its structure.
|
||
Marginalism claims to demonstrate the frequency of this penultimate
|
||
mechanism: it applies not only to the last exchangeable objects but also to
|
||
the last producible object, or the last producer him- or herself, the marginal
|
||
or limit-producer before the assemblage changes.24 This is an economics of
|
||
everyday life. For example, what does an alcoholic call the last glass? The
|
||
alcoholic makes a subjective evaluation of how much he or she can tolerate.
|
||
What can be tolerated is precisely the limit at which, as the alcoholic sees it,
|
||
he or she will be able to start over again (after a rest, a pause . . . ) . But
|
||
beyond that limit there lies a threshold that would cause the alcoholic to
|
||
change assemblage: it would change either the nature of the drinks or the
|
||
customary places and hours of the drinking. Or worse yet, the alcoholic
|
||
would enter a suicidal assemblage, or a medical, hospital assemblage, etc.
|
||
It is of little importance that the alcoholic may be fooling him- or herself, or
|
||
makes a very ambiguous use of the theme "I'm going to stop," the theme of
|
||
the last one. What counts is the existence of a spontaneous marginal crite-
|
||
rion and marginalist evaluation determining the value of the entire series
|
||
of "glasses." The same goes for having the last wordin a domestic-squabble
|
||
assemblage. Both partners evaluate from the start the volume or density of
|
||
the last word that would give them the advantage and conclude the discus-
|
||
sion, marking the end of an operation period or cycle of the assemblage,
|
||
allowing it to start all over again. Both calculate their words in accordance
|
||
with their evaluation of this last word, and the vaguely agreed time for it to
|
||
come. And beyond the last (penultimate) word there lie still other words,
|
||
this time final words that would cause them to enter another assemblage,
|
||
divorce, for example, because they would have overstepped "bounds." The
|
||
same could be said for the last love. Proust has shown how a love can be ori-
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 439
|
||
|
||
ented toward its own limit, its own margin: it repeats its own ending. A new
|
||
love follows, so that each love is serial, so that there is a series of loves.
|
||
But once again, "beyond" lies the ultimate, at the point where the assem-
|
||
blage changes, where the assemblage of love is superseded by an artis-
|
||
tic assemblage—the Work to be written, which is the problem Proust
|
||
tackles...
|
||
Exchange is only an appearance: each partner or group assesses the
|
||
value of the last receivable object (limit-object), and the apparent equiva-
|
||
lence derives from that. The equalization results from the two heterogene-
|
||
ous series, the exchange or communication results from two monologues
|
||
(palabre). There is neither exchange value nor use value but rather an eval-
|
||
uation of the last by both parties (a calculation of the risk involved in cross-
|
||
ing the limit), an anticipation-evaluation that takes into account the ritual
|
||
character as well as the utilitarian, the serial character as well as the
|
||
exchangist. The evaluation of the limit is there from the start in both
|
||
groups, and already governs the first "exchange" between them. Of course
|
||
there is groping in the dark; the evaluation is inseparable from a collective
|
||
feeling out. But it does not bear on the quantity of social labor but on the
|
||
idea of the last on both sides; the speed with which it is accomplished var-
|
||
ies, but it is always done faster than the time necessary effectively to arrive
|
||
at the last object, or even to pass from one operation to another.25 This is
|
||
the sense in which the evaluation is essentially anticipatory, that it is
|
||
already present in the first terms of the series. It can be seen that marginal
|
||
utility (pertaining to the last objects receivable on both sides) is relative not
|
||
to an abstractly posited stock but to the respective assemblages of the two
|
||
groups. Pareto was moving in this direction when he spoke of "ophelimity"
|
||
rather than of marginal utility.26 The issue is one of desirability as an assem-
|
||
blage component: every group desires according to the value of the last
|
||
receivable object beyond which it would be obliged to change assemblage.
|
||
And every assemblage has two sides, the machining of bodies or objects,
|
||
and group enunciation. The evaluation of the last is the collective enuncia-
|
||
tion to which the entire series of objects corresponds; in other words, it is an
|
||
assemblage cycle or operation period. Exchangist primitive groups thus
|
||
appear to be serial groups. Theirs is a special regime, even with respect to
|
||
violence. For even violence can be submitted to a marginal ritual treat-
|
||
ment, that is, to an evaluation of the "last violence" insofar as it impreg-
|
||
nates the entire series of blows (beyond which another regime of violence
|
||
would begin). We previously defined primitive societies by the existence of
|
||
anticipation-prevention mechanisms. Now we can see more clearly how
|
||
these mechanisms are constituted and distributed: it is the evaluation of
|
||
the last as limit that constitutes an anticipation and simultaneously wards
|
||
off the last as threshold or ultimate (a new assemblage).
|
||
440 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
The threshold comes "after" the limit, "after" the last receivable objects:
|
||
it marks the moment when the apparent exchange is no longer of interest.
|
||
We believe that it is precisely at this moment that stockpiling begins; be-
|
||
forehand, there may be exchange granaries, granaries specifically for
|
||
exchange purposes, but there is no stock in the strict sense. Exchange does
|
||
not assume a preexistent stock, it assumes only a certain "elasticity." Stock-
|
||
piling begins only once exchange has lost its interest, its desirability for
|
||
both parties. Additionally, conditions must exist giving stockpiling an
|
||
interest in its own right, a desirability of its own (otherwise, the objects
|
||
would be destroyed or depleted rather than stockpiled: depletion is the
|
||
means by which primitive groups ward off the stock and maintain their
|
||
assemblage). The stock depends on a new type of assemblage. The expres-
|
||
sions "after," "new," "to be superseded" are doubtless very ambiguous. The
|
||
threshold is in fact already there, but outside the limit, which is satisfied to
|
||
place the threshold at a distance, keep it at a distance. The problem is to
|
||
know what this other assemblage is that gives the stock an actual interest, a
|
||
desirability. The stock seems to us to have a necessary correlate: either the
|
||
coexistence of simultaneously exploited territories, or a succession of exploi-
|
||
tations on one and the same territory. It is at this point that the territories
|
||
form a Land, are superseded by a Land. This is the assemblage that neces-
|
||
sarily includes stockpiling, and which constitutes in the first case an exten-
|
||
sive system of cultivation, in the second case an intensive system of
|
||
cultivation (following Jane Jacobs's paradigm). The way in which the
|
||
stock-threshold differs from the exchange-limit is now clear: primitive
|
||
assemblages of hunter-gatherers have an operation period defined by the
|
||
exploitation of a territory; the law is one of temporal succession because
|
||
the assemblage perseveres only by switching territories at the conclusion of
|
||
each operation period (itinerancy, itineration); and within each operation
|
||
period there is a repetition or temporal series that tends toward the last
|
||
object as an "index," as the marginal or limit-object of the territory (this
|
||
iteration will govern the apparent exchange). On the other hand, in the
|
||
other assemblage, in the stock assemblage, the law is one of spatial coexis-
|
||
tence and concerns the simultaneous exploitation of different territories;
|
||
or, when the exploitation is successive, the succession of operation periods
|
||
bears on one and the same territory; and in the framework of each opera-
|
||
tion period or exploitation the force of serial iteration is superseded by a
|
||
power of symmetry, reflection, and global comparison. In solely descrip-
|
||
tive terms, we therefore distinguish between serial, itinerant, or territorial
|
||
assemblages (which operate by codes) and sedentary, global, or Land
|
||
assemblages (which operate by overcoding).
|
||
Ground rent, in its abstract model, appears precisely when a compari-
|
||
son is drawn between different simultaneously exploited territories, or
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 441
|
||
|
||
between the successive exploitations of the same territory. The worst land
|
||
(or the poorest exploitation) bears no rent, but it makes it so that the other
|
||
soils do bear rent, "produce" it in a comparative way.27 A stock is what per-
|
||
mits the yields to be compared (the same planting on different soils, or
|
||
various successive plantings on the same soil). The category of the last con-
|
||
firms once again its economic importance, but it has totally changed mean-
|
||
ing: it no longer designates the end point of a self-fulfilling movement but
|
||
the center of symmetry for two movements, one of which is descending and
|
||
the other ascending; it no longer designates the limit of an ordinal series
|
||
but the lowest element in a cardinal set, that set's threshold—the least fer-
|
||
tile land in the set of simultaneously exploited lands.28 Ground rent
|
||
homogenizes, equalizes different conditions of productivity by linking the
|
||
excess of the highest conditions of productivity over the lowest to a land-
|
||
owner: since the price (profit included) is established on the basis of the
|
||
least productive land, rent taps the surplus profit accruing to the best lands;
|
||
it taps "the difference between the product of two equal amounts of capital
|
||
and labor."29 This is the very model of an apparatus of capture, inseparable
|
||
from a process of relative deterritorialization. The land as the object of
|
||
agriculture in fact implies a deterritorialization, because instead of people
|
||
being distributed in an itinerant territory, pieces of land are distributed
|
||
among people according to a common quantitative criterion (the fertility
|
||
of plots of equal surface area). That is why the earth, unlike other elements,
|
||
forms the basis of a striation, proceeding by geometry, symmetry, and com-
|
||
parison. The other elements, water, air, wind, and subsoil, cannot be stri-
|
||
ated and for that very reason bear rent only by virtue of their emplacement,
|
||
in other words, as a function of the land.30 The land has two potentialities
|
||
of deterritorialization: (1) its differences in quality are comparable to one
|
||
another, from the standpoint of a quantity establishing a correspondence
|
||
between them and exploitable pieces of land; (2) the set of exploited lands
|
||
is appropriable, as opposed to exterior unclaimed land, from the stand-
|
||
point of a monopoly that fixes the landowner or -owners.31 The second
|
||
potentiality is the necessary condition for the first. Both were warded off
|
||
by the territory's territorialization of the earth but are now effectuated in
|
||
the agricultural assemblage thanks to stockpiling, by means of a deter-
|
||
ritorialization of the territory. Land as compared and appropriated ex-
|
||
tracts from the territories a center of convergence located outside them; the
|
||
land is an idea of the town.
|
||
Rent is not the only apparatus of capture. The stock has as its correlate
|
||
not only the land, from the double point of view of the comparison of lands
|
||
and the monopolistic appropriation of land; it has work as another corre-
|
||
late, from the double point of view of the comparison of activities and the
|
||
monopolistic appropriation of labor (surplus labor). Once again, it is by
|
||
442 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
virtue of the stock that activities of the "free action" type come to be com-
|
||
pared, linked, and subordinated to a common and homogeneous quantity
|
||
called labor. Not only does labor concern the stock—either its constitu-
|
||
tion, conservation, reconstitution, or utilization—but labor itself is stock-
|
||
piled activity, just as the worker is a stockpiled "actant." Moreover, even
|
||
when labor is clearly separated from surplus labor, they cannot be held to
|
||
be independent: there is no so-called necessary labor, and beyond that sur-
|
||
plus labor. Labor and surplus labor are strictly the same thing; the first term
|
||
is applied to the quantitative comparison of activities, the second to the
|
||
monopolistic appropriation of labor by the entrepreneur (and no longer
|
||
the landowner). As we have seen, even when they are distinct and separate,
|
||
there is no labor that is not predicated on surplus labor. Surplus labor is not
|
||
that which exceeds labor; on the contrary, labor is that which is subtracted
|
||
from surplus labor and presupposes it. It is only in this context that one
|
||
may speak of labor value, and of an evaluation bearing on the quantity of
|
||
social labor, whereas primitive groups were under a regime of free action or
|
||
activity in continuous variation. Since it depends on surplus labor and sur-
|
||
plus value, entrepreneurial profit is just as much an apparatus of capture as
|
||
proprietary rent: not only does surplus labor capture labor, and
|
||
landownership the earth, but labor and surplus labor are the apparatus of
|
||
capture of activity, just as the comparison of lands and the appropriation of
|
||
land are the apparatus of capture of the territory.32
|
||
Finally, there is a third apparatus of capture in addition to rent and
|
||
profit: taxation. To understand this third form, and its creative range, we
|
||
must first determine the internal relation upon which the commodity
|
||
depends. Edouard Will has shown, in relation to the Greek city and in par-
|
||
ticular the Corinthian tyranny, that money derived not from exchange, the
|
||
commodity, or the demands of commerce, but from taxation, which first
|
||
introduces the possibility of an equivalence money = goods or services and
|
||
which makes money a general equivalent. In effect, money is a correlate of
|
||
the stock; it is a subset of the stock in that it can be constituted by any object
|
||
that can be preserved over the long term. In the case of Corinth, metal
|
||
money was first distributed to the "poor" (in their capacity as producers),
|
||
who used it to by land rights; it thus passed into the hands of the "rich," on
|
||
the condition that it not stop there, that everyone, rich and poor, pay a tax,
|
||
the poor in goods or services, the rich in money, such that an equivalence
|
||
money-goods and services was established.33 We will return to the signifi-
|
||
cance of this reference to rich and poor in the already late case of Corinth. But
|
||
beyond the context and particularities of this example, money is
|
||
always distributed by an apparatus of power under conditions of conserva-
|
||
tion, circulation, and turnover, so that an equivalence goods-services-
|
||
money can be established. We therefore do not believe in a succession.
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 443
|
||
|
||
according to which labor rent would come first, followed by rent in kind,
|
||
followed by money rent.34 It is directly in taxation that the equivalence and
|
||
simultaneity of the three develop. As a general rule, it is taxation that
|
||
monetarizes the economy; it is taxation that creates money, and it neces-
|
||
sarily creates it in motion, in circulation, with turnover, and also in a corre-
|
||
spondence with services and goods in the current of that circulation. The
|
||
State finds in taxation the means for foreign trade, insofar as it appropri-
|
||
ates that trade. Yet it is not from trade but from taxation that the money-
|
||
form derives.35 And the money-form thus derived from taxation makes
|
||
possible a monopolistic appropriation of outside exchange by the State
|
||
(monetarized trade). Everything is different in the regime of exchanges.
|
||
We are no longer in the "primitive" situation where exchange is carried out
|
||
indirectly, subjectively, through the respective equalization of the last
|
||
receivable objects (the law of demand). Of course, exchange remains what
|
||
it is in essence, that is to say, unequal, productive of an equalization result-
|
||
ing from inequality: but this time there is direct comparison, objective
|
||
pricing, and monetary equalization (the law of supply). It is through taxa-
|
||
tion that goods and services come to be like commodities, and the com-
|
||
modity comes to be measured and equalized by money. That is why, even
|
||
today, the meaning and impact of taxation appear in what is called indirect
|
||
taxation, in other words, a tax that is included in the price and influences
|
||
the value of the commodity, independent of and outside the market.36
|
||
However, the indirect tax is not simply an additional element that is tacked
|
||
onto prices and inflates them. It is only the index or expression of a deeper
|
||
movement, in which the tax constitutes the first layer of an "objective"
|
||
price, the monetary magnet to which the other elements—price, rent, and
|
||
profit—add on and adhere, converging in the same apparatus of capture. It
|
||
was a great moment in capitalism when the capitalists realized that taxa-
|
||
tion could be productive, that it could be particularly favorable to profits
|
||
and even to rents. But as with indirect taxation, this is a favorable case; it
|
||
should not obscure an even deeper and more archaic accord, a convergence
|
||
and essential identity between three aspects of a single apparatus. A three-
|
||
headed apparatus of capture, a "trinity formula" derived from that of
|
||
Marx (although it distributes things differently):37
|
||
LAND
|
||
(as opposed to territory)
|
||
a) Direct comparison of lands, dif- Rent
|
||
ferential rent; The Landowner
|
||
b) Monopolistic appropriation of
|
||
land, absolute rent.
|
||
444 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
WORK
|
||
(as opposed to activity)
|
||
Stock a) Direct comparison of activities, Profit
|
||
labor; The Entrepreneur
|
||
b) Monopolistic appropriation of
|
||
labor, surplus labor.
|
||
|
||
MONEY
|
||
(as opposed to exchange)
|
||
a) Direct comparison of the objects
|
||
exchanged, the commodity; Taxation
|
||
b) Monopolistic appropriation of the The Banker
|
||
means of comparison, the issu-
|
||
ance of currency.
|
||
|
||
1. The stock has three simultaneous aspects: land and seeds, tools,
|
||
money. Land is stockpiled territory, the tool is stockpiled activity, and
|
||
money is stockpiled exchange. But the stock does not come from either ter-
|
||
ritories, activities, or exchanges. It marks another assemblage; it comes
|
||
from that other assemblage.
|
||
2. That assemblage is the "megamachine," or the apparatus of capture,
|
||
the archaic empire. It functions in three modes, which correspond to the
|
||
three aspects of the stock: rent, profit, taxation. And the three modes con-
|
||
verge and coincide in it, in an agency of overcoding (or signifiance): the
|
||
despot, at once the eminent landowner, entrepreneur of large-scale proj-
|
||
ects, and master of taxes and prices. This is like three capitalizations of
|
||
power, or three articulations of "capital."
|
||
3. What forms the apparatus of capture are two operations always
|
||
found in the convergent modes: direct comparison and monopolistic
|
||
appropriation. And the comparison always presupposes the appropria-
|
||
tion: labor presupposes surplus labor; differential rent presupposes abso-
|
||
lute rent; commercial money presupposes taxation. The apparatus of
|
||
capture constitutes a general space of comparison and a mobile center of
|
||
appropriation. This is a white wall/black hole system of the kind that, as we
|
||
have seen, constitutes the face of the despot. A point of resonance circu-
|
||
lates in a space of comparison and constitutes that space as it circulates.
|
||
That is what distinguishes the State apparatus from primitive mecha-
|
||
nisms, with their noncoexistent territories and nonresonating centers.
|
||
What begins with the State or the apparatus of capture is a general
|
||
semiology that overcodes the primitive semiotic systems. Instead of traits
|
||
of expression that follow a machinic phylum and wed it in a distribution of
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 445
|
||
|
||
singularities, the State constitutes a form of expression that subjugates the
|
||
phylum: the phylum or matter is no longer anything more than an equa-
|
||
lized, homogenized, compared content, while expression becomes a form
|
||
of resonance or appropriation. Apparatus of capture—the semiological
|
||
operation par excellence... (In this sense, the associationist philosophers
|
||
were not wrong in explaining political power by operations of the mind
|
||
dependent upon the association of ideas.)
|
||
Bernard Schmitt has proposed a model of the apparatus of capture that
|
||
takes into account the operations of comparison and appropriation. This
|
||
model admittedly revolves around money as a capitalist economics. But it
|
||
seems to be based on abstract principles that transcend these limits.38
|
||
A. The point of departure is an undivided flow that has yet to be ap-
|
||
propriated or compared, a "pure availability," "nonpossession and non-
|
||
wealth": this is precisely what occurs when banks create money, but taken
|
||
more generally it is the establishment of the stock, which is the creation of
|
||
an undivided flow.
|
||
B. The undivided flow becomes divided to the extent it is allocated to
|
||
the "factors," distributed to the "factors." There is only one kind of factor,
|
||
the immediate producers. We could call them the "poor" and say that the
|
||
flow is distributed among the poor. But this would be inaccurate because
|
||
there are no preexistent "rich." What counts, the important thing, is that
|
||
the producers do not yet acquire possession of what is distributed to them,
|
||
and that what is distributed to them is not yet wealth: remuneration
|
||
assumes neither comparison and appropriation, nor buying-selling; it is
|
||
much more an operation of the nexum type. There is only equality between
|
||
set B and set A, between the distributed set and the undivided set. The dis-
|
||
tributed set could be called nominal wage; nominal wages are the form of
|
||
expression of the entire undivided set ("the entire nominal expression," or
|
||
as it is often put, "the expression of total national income"). This is the
|
||
point at which the apparatus of capture becomes semiological.
|
||
C. Thus it cannot even be said that wages, conceived as distribution,
|
||
remuneration, constitute a purchase; on the contrary, purchasing power
|
||
derives from wages: "The remuneration of the producers is not a purchase,
|
||
it is the operation by which purchasing becomes possible in a second
|
||
moment, when money begins to exercise its new power." It is after it has
|
||
been distributed that set B becomes wealth, or acquires a comparative
|
||
power, in relation to something else entirely. This something else is the
|
||
determinate set of the goods that have been produced and are thus purchas-
|
||
able. At first heterogeneous to goods and products, money later becomes a
|
||
good homogeneous to the products it can buy; it acquires a purchasing
|
||
power that is extinguished with the real purchase. Or more generally,
|
||
between the two sets, the distributed set B and the set of real goods C, there
|
||
446 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
is established a correspondence, a comparison ("the power of acquisition is
|
||
created in direct conjunction with the set of real productions").
|
||
D. This is where the mystery or the magic resides, in a kind of disjunc-
|
||
tion. For if we call B' the comparative set, in other words, the set placed in
|
||
correspondence with the real goods, we see that it is necessarily smaller
|
||
than the distributed set. B' is necessarily smaller than B: even if we assume
|
||
that purchasing power has available to it all of the objects produced during
|
||
a given period, the distributed set is always greater than the set that is used
|
||
or compared, meaning that the immediate producers are able to convert
|
||
only a portion of the distributed set. Real wages are only a portion of nomi-
|
||
nal wages; similarly, "useful" labor is only a portion of labor, and "utilized"
|
||
land is only a portion of the land that has been distributed. We shall call
|
||
Capture this difference or excess constitutive of profit, surplus labor, or the
|
||
surplus product: "Nominal wages include everything, but the wage-earners
|
||
retain only the income they succeed in converting into goods; they lose the
|
||
income siphoned off by the enterprises." It can be said that the whole was in
|
||
fact distributed to the "poor"; the poor, however, find themselves extorted
|
||
of everything they do not succeed in converting in the course of this strange
|
||
race: the capture effects an inversion of the wave or of the divisible flow. It
|
||
is precisely capture that is the object of monopolistic appropriation. And
|
||
this appropriation (by the "rich") does not come after: it is included in
|
||
nominal wages, while eluding real wages. It is between the two, it inserts
|
||
itself between the distribution without possession and the conversion by
|
||
correspondence or comparison; it expresses the difference in power
|
||
between the two sets, between B' and B. In the end, there is no mystery at
|
||
all: the mechanism of capture contributes from the outset to the constitution
|
||
of the aggregate upon which the capture is effectuated.
|
||
This schema, according to its author, is very difficult to understand, and
|
||
yet it is operative. It consists in bringing into relief an abstract machine of
|
||
capture or of extortion by presenting a very specific "order of reasons." For
|
||
example, remuneration is not itself a purchase since purchasing power
|
||
derives from it. As Schmitt says, there is neither thief nor victim, for the
|
||
producer only loses what he does not have and has no chance of acquiring:
|
||
as in seventeenth-century philosophy, there are negations but not priva-
|
||
tion .. . And everything coexists in this logical apparatus of capture. Any
|
||
succession is purely logical: the capture in itself appears between B and C,
|
||
but exists as well between A and B, between C and A; it impregnates the
|
||
entire apparatus, it acts as a nonlocalizable liaison for the system. The
|
||
same goes for surplus labor: How could one specify its location since labor
|
||
presupposes it? Now the State—the archaic imperial State in any case—is
|
||
this very apparatus. It is always a mistake to appeal to a supplementary
|
||
explanation for the State: this pushes the State back behind the State, ad
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 447
|
||
|
||
infinitum. It is better to leave it where it is from the start, for it exists punc-
|
||
tually, beyond the limit of the primitive series. It is enough for this point of
|
||
comparison and appropriation to be effectively occupied in order for the
|
||
apparatus of capture to function, an apparatus that overcodes the primi-
|
||
tive codes, substitutes sets for the series, or reverses the direction of the
|
||
signs. This point is necessarily occupied, effectuated, because it already
|
||
exists in the convergent wave that moves through the primitive series and
|
||
draws them toward a threshold at which, after passing their limits, the wave
|
||
itself changes direction. Primitive peoples have always existed only as ves-
|
||
tiges, already plied by the reversible wave that carries them off (vector of
|
||
deterritorialization). What is contingent upon external circumstances is
|
||
only the place where the apparatus is effectuated—the place where the
|
||
agricultural "mode of production" was able to arise: the Orient. It is in this
|
||
sense that the apparatus is abstract. But in itself, it marks not simply an
|
||
abstract possibility of reversibility but the real existence of a point of inver-
|
||
sion as an autonomous, irreducible phenomenon.
|
||
Hence the very particular character of State violence: it is very difficult
|
||
to pinpoint this violence because it always presents itself as preaccom-
|
||
plished. It is not even adequate to say that the violence rests with the mode
|
||
of production. Marx made the observation in the case of capitalism: there
|
||
is a violence that necessarily operates through the State, precedes the capi-
|
||
talist mode of production, constitutes the "primitive accumulation," and
|
||
makes possible the capitalist mode of production itself. From a standpoint
|
||
within the capitalist mode of production, it is very difficult to say who is
|
||
the thief and who the victim, or even where the violence resides. That is
|
||
because the worker is born entirely naked and the capitalist objectively
|
||
"clothed," an independent owner. That which gave the worker and the capi-
|
||
talist this form eludes us because it operated in other modes of production.
|
||
It is a violence that posits itself as preaccomplished, even though it is reac-
|
||
tivated every day.39 This is the place to say it, if ever there was one: the muti-
|
||
lation is prior, preestablished. However, these analyses of Marx should be
|
||
enlarged upon. For the fact remains that there is a primitive accumulation
|
||
that, far from deriving from the agricultural mode of production, precedes
|
||
it: as a general rule, there is primitive accumulation whenever an apparatus
|
||
of capture is mounted, with that very particular kind of violence that cre-
|
||
ates or contributes to the creation of that which it is directed against, and
|
||
thus presupposes itself.40 The problem then becomes one of distinguishing
|
||
between regimes of violence. We can draw a distinction between struggle,
|
||
war, crime and policing as so many regimes of violence. Struggle would be
|
||
like the regime of primitive violence (including primitive "wars"); it is a
|
||
blow-by-blow violence, which is not without its code, since the value of the
|
||
blows is fixed according to the law of the series, as a function of the value of
|
||
448 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
the last exchangeable blow, or of the last woman to conquer, etc. Thus there
|
||
is a certain ritualization of violence. War, at least when linked to the war
|
||
machine, is another regime, because it implies the mobilization and
|
||
autonomization of a violence directed first and essentially against the
|
||
State apparatus (the war machine is in this sense the invention of a primary
|
||
nomadic organization that turns against the State). Crime is something
|
||
else, because it is a violence of illegality that consists in taking possession of
|
||
something to which one has no "right," in capturing something one does
|
||
not have a "right" to capture. But State policing or lawful violence is some-
|
||
thing else again, because it consists in capturing while simultaneously
|
||
constituting a right to capture. It is an incorporated, structural violence
|
||
distinct from every kind of direct violence. The State has often been
|
||
defined by a "monopoly of violence," but this definition leads back to
|
||
another definition that describes the State as a "state of Law" (Rechts-
|
||
staat). State overcoding is precisely this structural violence that defines
|
||
the law, "police" violence and not the violence of war. There is lawful vio-
|
||
lence wherever violence contributes to the creation of that which it is used
|
||
against, or as Marx says, wherever capture contributes to the creation of
|
||
that which it captures. This is very different from criminal violence. It is
|
||
also why, in contradistinction to primitive violence, State or lawful violence
|
||
always seems to presuppose itself, for it preexists its own use: the State can
|
||
in this way say that violence is "primal," that it is simply a natural phenom-
|
||
enon the responsibility for which does not lie with the State, which uses
|
||
violence only against the violent, against "criminals"—against primitives,
|
||
against nomads—in order that peace may reign.
|
||
PROPOSITION XIII. The State and its forms.
|
||
We start with the archaic imperial State: overcoding, apparatus of cap-
|
||
ture, machine of enslavement. It comprises a particular kind of property,
|
||
money, public works—a formula complete in a single stroke but one that
|
||
presupposes nothing "private" and does not even assume a preexistent
|
||
mode of production since it is what gives rise to the mode of production.
|
||
The point of departure that the preceding analyses give us is well estab-
|
||
lished by archaeology. The question now becomes: Once the State has
|
||
appeared, formed in a single stroke, how will it evolve? What are its factors
|
||
of evolution or mutation, and what is the relation between evolved States
|
||
and the archaic imperial State?
|
||
The principle of evolution is internal, whatever the external factors that
|
||
contribute to it. The archaic State does not overcode without also freeing a
|
||
large quantity ofdecodedflows that escape from it. Let us recall that "decod-
|
||
ing" does not signify the state of a flow whose code is understood (compris)
|
||
(deciphered, translatable, assimilable), but, in a more radical sense, the
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 449
|
||
|
||
state of a flow that is no longer contained in (compris dans) it own code,
|
||
that escapes it own code. On the one hand, when the primitive codes cease
|
||
to be self-regulating and are subordinated to the higher agency, flows that had
|
||
been coded in a relative way by the primitive communities find the
|
||
opportunity to escape. But on the other hand, the overcoding of the archaic
|
||
State itself makes possible and gives rise to new flows that escape from it. The
|
||
State does not created large-scale works without a flow of independent labor
|
||
escaping its bureaucracy (notably in the mines and in metallurgy). It does
|
||
not create the monetary form of the tax without flows of money escaping,
|
||
and nourishing or bringing into being other powers (notably in commerce
|
||
and banking). And above all, it does not created a system of public property
|
||
without a flow of private appropriation growing up beside it, then begin-
|
||
ning to pass beyond its grasp; this private property does not itself issue
|
||
from the archaic system but is constituted on the margins, all the more nec-
|
||
essarily and inevitably, slipping through the net of overcoding. It is
|
||
undoubtedly Tokei who has formulated the problem of an origin of private
|
||
property in the most serious way, in the context of a system that seems to
|
||
exclude it from every angle. For private property can arise neither on the
|
||
side of the emperor-despot not on the side of the peasants, whose auton-
|
||
omy is tied to communal possession, nor on the side of the functionaries
|
||
whose existence and income are based on that public communal form ("the
|
||
aristocrats can under these conditions become petty despots but not pri-
|
||
vate landowners"). Even the slaves belong to the community or the public
|
||
function. The question then becomes, Are there people who are consti-
|
||
tuted in the overcoding empire, but constituted as necessarily excluded
|
||
and decoded? Tokei's answer is the freed slaves. It is they who have no place.
|
||
It is their lamentations that are heard the length and breadth of the Chinese
|
||
Empire: the plaint (elegy) has always been a political factor. But it is also
|
||
they who form the first seeds of private property, who develop trade, and
|
||
with metallurgy invent a kind of private slavery in which they will be the
|
||
new master.41 We saw previously the role played by freed slaves in the war
|
||
machine, in the formation of the special body. It is in a different form, and
|
||
following entirely different principles, that they play an important role in
|
||
the State apparatus and in the evolution of that apparatus, this time in the
|
||
formation of a private body. The two aspects can combine, but they belong
|
||
to two different lines.
|
||
What counts is not the particular case of the freed slave.What counts is
|
||
the collective figure of the Outsider. What counts is that in one way or
|
||
another the apparatus of overcoding gives rise to flows that are themselves
|
||
decoded—flows of money, labor, property. . . These flows are the correlate
|
||
of the apparatus. And the correlation is not only social, internal to the
|
||
archaic empire, it is also geographical. This would be the place to bring up
|
||
450 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
the confrontation between the East and the West. According to V. Gordon
|
||
Childe's great archaeological thesis, the archaic imperial State implies a
|
||
stockpiled agricultural surplus, which makes possible the maintenance of a
|
||
specialized body of mercantile and metallurgical artisans. Indeed, the sur-
|
||
plus as the content proper to overcoding must be not only stockpiled but
|
||
absorbed, consumed, realized. Doubtless, this economic requirement that
|
||
the surplus be absorbed is one of the principal aspects of the appropriation
|
||
of the war machine by the imperial State: The military institution is from
|
||
the start one of the most effective means of absorbing surplus. If, however,
|
||
we assume that the bureaucratic and military institutions are not enough,
|
||
the way is cleared for this specialized body of nonagricultural artisans,
|
||
whose labor will reinforce the sedentarization of agriculture. It was in Afro-
|
||
Asia and the Orient that all of these conditions were fulfilled and that the
|
||
State apparatus was invented: in the Middle East, Egypt, and Mesopota-
|
||
mia, but also in the valley of the Indus (and in the Far East). That was where
|
||
agricultural stock and its bureaucratic, military, but also metallurgical and
|
||
commercial concomitants came into being. But this oriental or imperial
|
||
"solution" is threatened by an impasse: State overcoding keeps the metal-
|
||
lurgists, both craft and mercantile, within strict bounds, under powerful
|
||
bureaucratic control, with monopolistic appropriation of foreign trade in
|
||
the service of a ruling class, so that the peasants themselves benefit little
|
||
from the State innovations. So it is indeed true that the State-form spreads
|
||
and that archaeology discovers it everywhere on the horizon of Western
|
||
history in the Aegean world. But not under the same conditions. Minos and
|
||
Mycenae are more a caricature of an empire, Agamemnon of Mycenae is
|
||
not the Chinese emperor or Egyptian pharaoh; the Egyptian can say to the
|
||
Greeks: "You will always be like children..." That is because the Aegean
|
||
peoples were both too far away to fall into the oriental sphere and too poor
|
||
to stockpile a surplus themselves, but neither far enough away nor impov-
|
||
erished enough to ignore the markets of the Orient. Moreover, oriental
|
||
overcoding itself assigned its merchants a long-distance role. Thus the
|
||
Aegean peoples found themselves in a situation where they could take
|
||
advantage of the oriental agricultural stock without having to constitute one
|
||
for themselves: they plundered it when they could, and on a more regular
|
||
basis procured a share of it in exchange for raw materials (notably wood
|
||
and metals), coming from as far away as Central and Western Europe. Of
|
||
course, the Orient continually had to reproduce its stocks; but formally, it
|
||
had made a move "once and for all," from which the West benefited with-
|
||
out having to reproduce it. It follows that the metallurgical artisans and the
|
||
merchants assumed an entirely different status in the West, since their exis-
|
||
tence did not directly depend on a surplus accumulated by a local State
|
||
apparatus: even if the peasant suffered an exploitation as bad as or worse
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 451
|
||
|
||
than that of the Orient, the artisan and the merchant enjoyed a freer status
|
||
and a more diversified market, prefiguring a middle class. Many metallur-
|
||
gists and merchants from the Orient moved to the Aegean world, where
|
||
they were to find freer, more varied and more stable conditions. In short,
|
||
the same flows that are overcoded in the Orient tend to become decoded in
|
||
Europe, in a new situation that is like the flipside or correlate of the other.
|
||
Surplus value is no longer surplus value of code (overcoding) but becomes
|
||
surplus value of flow. It is as if two solutions were found for the same prob-
|
||
lem, the Oriental solution and then the Western one, which grafts itself
|
||
upon the first and brings it out of the impasse while continuing to presup-
|
||
pose it. The European metallurgist and merchant faced a much less thor-
|
||
oughly coded international market, one not limited to an imperial house or
|
||
class. And as Childe said, the Western and Aegean States were immersed in
|
||
a supranational economic system from the start; they bathed in it, instead
|
||
of containing it within the limits of their own net.42
|
||
It is indeed another pole of the State that arises, one that could be
|
||
defined in summary fashion as follows. The public sphere no longer charac-
|
||
terizes the objective nature of property but is instead the shared means for
|
||
a now private appropriation; this yields the public-private mixes constitu-
|
||
tive of the modern world. The bond becomes personal; personal relations of
|
||
dependence, both between owners (contracts) and between owned and
|
||
owners (conventions), parallel or replace community relations or relations
|
||
based on one's public function. Even slavery changes; it no longer defines
|
||
the public availability of the communal worker but rather private property
|
||
as applied to individual workers.43 The law in its entirety undergoes a
|
||
mutation, becoming subjective, conjunctive, "topical" law: this is because
|
||
the State apparatus is faced with a new task, which consists less in
|
||
overcoding already coded flows than in organizing conjunctions of decoded
|
||
flows as such. Thus the regime of signs has changed: in all of these respects,
|
||
the operation of the imperial "signifier" has been superseded by processes
|
||
of subjedification; machinic enslavement tends to be replaced by a regime
|
||
of social subjection. And unlike the relatively uniform imperial pole, this
|
||
second pole presents the most diverse of forms. But as varied as relations of
|
||
personal dependence are, they always mark qualified and topical conjunc-
|
||
tions. It was the evolved empires, of the East and of the West, that first
|
||
developed this new public sphere of the private, through institutions such
|
||
as the consilium and thefiscus in the Roman Empire (it was through these
|
||
institutions that freed slaves acquired a political power paralleling that of
|
||
the functionaries).44 But it was also the autonomous cities, the feudal sys-
|
||
tems. .. The question as to whether these last-mentioned formations still
|
||
answer to the concept of the State can be formulated only after certain cor-
|
||
relations have been taken into account. Every bit as much as the evolved
|
||
452 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
empires, the autonomous cities, and feudal systems presuppose an archaic
|
||
empire that served as their foundation; they were themselves in contact
|
||
with evolved empires that reacted back upon them; they actively prepared
|
||
the way for new forms of the State (for example, absolute monarchy as the
|
||
culmination of a certain kind of subjective law and a feudal process).45 In
|
||
effect, in the rich domain of personal relations, what counts is not the
|
||
capriciousness or variability of the individuals but the consistency of the
|
||
relations, and the adequation between a subjectivity that can reach the
|
||
point of delirium and qualified acts that are sources of rights and obliga-
|
||
tions. In a beautiful passage, Edgar Quinet underlines this coincidence
|
||
between "the delirium of the twelve Cesars and the golden age of Roman
|
||
law."46
|
||
The subjectifications, conjunctions, and appropriations do not prevent
|
||
the decoded flows from continuing to flow, and from ceaselessly engender-
|
||
ing new flows that escape (we saw this, for example, at the level of a
|
||
micropolitics of the Middle Ages). This is where there is an ambiguity in
|
||
these apparatuses: they can only function with decoded flows, and yet they
|
||
do not let them stream together; they perform topical conjunctions that
|
||
stand as so many knots or recodings. This accounts for the historians'
|
||
impression that capitalism "could have" developed beginning at a certain
|
||
moment, in China, in Rome, in Byzantium, in the Middle Ages, that the
|
||
conditions for it existed but were not effectuated or even capable of being
|
||
effectuated. The situation is that the pressure of the flows draws capitalism
|
||
in negative outline, but for it to be realized there must be a whole integral of
|
||
decoded flows, a whole generalized conjunction that overspills and over-
|
||
turns the preceding apparatuses. And in fact when Marx sets about defin-
|
||
ing capitalism, he begins by invoking the advent of a single unqualified and
|
||
global Subjectivity, which capitalizes all of the processes of subjectifica-
|
||
tion, "all activities without distinction": "productive activity in general,"
|
||
"the sole subjective essence of wealth . . ." And this single Subject now
|
||
expresses itself in an Object in general, no longer in this or that qualitative
|
||
state: "Along with the abstract universality of wealth-creating activity we
|
||
have now the universality of the object defined as wealth, viz. the product
|
||
in general, or labor in general, but as past, materialized labor."47 Circula-
|
||
tion constitutes capital as a subjectivity commensurate with society in its
|
||
entirety. But this new social subjectivity can form only to the extent that
|
||
the decoded flows overspill their conjunctions and attain a level of decod-
|
||
ing that the State apparatuses are no longer able to reclaim: on the one
|
||
hand, the flow of labor must no longer be determined as slavery or serfdom
|
||
but must become naked and free labor; and on the other hand, wealth must
|
||
no longer be determined as money dealing, merchant's or landed wealth,
|
||
but must become pure homogeneous and independent capital. And doubt-
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 453
|
||
|
||
less, these two becomings at least (for other flows also converge) introduce
|
||
many contingencies and many different factors on each of the lines. But it
|
||
is their abstract conjunction in a single stroke that constitutes capitalism,
|
||
providing a universal subject and an object in general for one another. Cap-
|
||
italism forms when the flow of unqualified wealth encounters the flow of
|
||
unqualified labor and conjugates with it.48 This is what the preceding con-
|
||
junctions, which were still topical or qualitative, had always inhibited (the
|
||
two principal inhibitors were the feudal organization of the countryside
|
||
and the corporative organization of the towns). This amounts to saying
|
||
that capitalism forms with a general axiomatic of decoded flows. "Capital is
|
||
a right, or, to be more precise, a relation of production that is manifested as
|
||
a right, and as such it is independent of the concrete form that it cloaks at
|
||
each moment of its productive function."49 Private property no longer
|
||
expresses the bond of personal dependence but the independence of a Sub-
|
||
ject that now constitutes the sole bond. This makes for an important differ-
|
||
ence in the evolution of private property: private property in itself relates
|
||
to rights, instead of the law relating it to the land, things, or people (this
|
||
raises in particular the famous question of the elimination of ground rent
|
||
in capitalism). A new threshold of deterritorialization. And when capital
|
||
becomes an active right in this way, the entire historical figure of the law
|
||
changes. The law ceases to be the overcoding of customs, as it was in the
|
||
archaic empire; it is no longer a set of topics, as it was in the evolved States,
|
||
the autonomous cities, and the feudal systems; it increasingly assumes the
|
||
direct form and immediate characteristics of an axiomatic, as evidenced in
|
||
our civil "code."50
|
||
When the flows reach this capitalist threshold of decoding and deterri-
|
||
torialization (naked labor, independent capital), it seems that there is no
|
||
longer a need for a State, for distinct juridical and political domination, in
|
||
order to ensure appropriation, which has become directly economic. The
|
||
economy constitutes a worldwide axiomatic, a "universal cosmopolitan
|
||
energy which overflows every restriction and bond,"51 a mobile and con-
|
||
vertible substance "such as the total value of annual production." Today we
|
||
can depict an enormous, so-called stateless, monetary mass that circulates
|
||
through foreign exchange and across borders, eluding control by the States,
|
||
forming a multinational ecumenical organization, constituting a de facto
|
||
supranational power untouched by governmental decisions.52 But what-
|
||
ever dimensions or quantities this may have assumed today, capitalism has
|
||
from the beginning mobilized a force of deterritorialization infinitely sur-
|
||
passing the deterritorialization proper to the State. For since Paleolithic
|
||
and Neolithic times, the State has been deterritorializing to the extent that
|
||
it makes the earth an object of its higher unity, a forced aggregate of coexis-
|
||
tence, instead of the free play of territories among themselves and with the
|
||
454 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
lineages. But this is precisely the sense in which the State is termed "terri-
|
||
torial." Capitalism, on the other hand, is not at all territorial, even in its
|
||
beginnings: its power of deterritorialization consists in taking as its object,
|
||
not the earth, but "materialized labor," the commodity. And private prop-
|
||
erty is no longer ownership of the land or the soil, nor even of the means of
|
||
production as such, but of convertible abstract rights.53 That is why capital-
|
||
ism marks a mutation in worldwide or ecumenical organizations, which
|
||
now take on a consistency of their own: the worldwide axiomatic, instead
|
||
of resulting from heterogeneous social formations and their relations, for
|
||
the most part distributes these formations, determines their relations,
|
||
while organizing an international division of labor. From all these stand-
|
||
points, it could be said that capitalism develops an economic order that
|
||
could do without the State. And in fact capitalism is not short on war cries
|
||
against the State, not only in the name of the market, but by virtue of its
|
||
superior deterritorialization.
|
||
This, however, is only one very partial aspect of capital. If it is true that
|
||
we are not using the word axiomatic as a simple metaphor, we must review
|
||
what distinguishes an axiomatic from all manner of codes, overcodings,
|
||
and recodings: the axiomatic deals directly with purely functional ele-
|
||
ments and relations whose nature is not specified, and which are immedi-
|
||
ately realized in highly varied domains simultaneously; codes, on the other
|
||
hand, are relative to those domains and express specific relations between
|
||
qualified elements that cannot be subsumed by a higher formal unity
|
||
(overcoding) except by transcendence and in an indirect fashion. The
|
||
immanent axiomatic finds in the domains it moves through so many mod-
|
||
els, termed models of realization. It could similarly be said that capital as
|
||
right, as a "qualitatively homogeneous and quantitatively commensurable
|
||
element," is realized in sectors and means of production (or that "unified
|
||
capital" is realized in "differentiated capital"). However, the different sec-
|
||
tors are not alone in serving as models of realization—the States do too.
|
||
Each of them groups together and combines several sectors, according to
|
||
its resources, population, wealth, industrial capacity, etc. Thus the States,
|
||
in capitalism, are not canceled out but change form and take on a new
|
||
meaning: models of realization for a worldwide axiomatic that exceeds
|
||
them. But to exceed is not at all the same thing as doing without. We have
|
||
already seen that capitalism proceeds by way of the State-form rather than
|
||
the town-form; the basis for the fundamental mechanisms described by
|
||
Marx (the colonial regime, the public debt, the modern tax system and
|
||
indirect taxation, industrial protectionism, trade wars) may be laid in the
|
||
towns, but the towns function as mechanisms of accumulation, accelera-
|
||
tion, and concentration only to the extent that they are appropriated by
|
||
States. Recent events tend to confirm this principle from another angle.
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 455
|
||
|
||
For example, NASA appeared ready to mobilize considerable capital for
|
||
interplanetary exploration, as though capitalism were riding a vector tak-
|
||
ing it to the moon; but following the USSR, which conceived of extraterres-
|
||
trial space as a belt that should circle the earth taken as the "object," the
|
||
American government cut off funds for exploration and returned capital in
|
||
this case to a more centered model. It is thus proper to State deterrito-
|
||
rialization to moderate the superior deterritorialization of capital and to
|
||
provide the latter with compensatory reterritorializations. More generally,
|
||
this extreme example aside, we must take into account a "materialist"
|
||
determination of the modern State or nation-state: a group of producers in
|
||
which labor and capital circulate freely, in other words, in which the
|
||
homogeneity and competition of capital is effectuated, in principle with-
|
||
out external obstacles. In order to be effectuated, capitalism has always
|
||
required there to be a new force and a new law of States, on the level of the
|
||
flow of labor as on the level of the flow of independent capital.
|
||
So States are not at all transcendent paradigms of an overcoding but
|
||
immanent models of realization for an axiomatic of decoded flows. Once
|
||
again, our use of the word "axiomatic" is far from a metaphor; we find liter-
|
||
ally the same theoretical problems that are posed by the models in an axio-
|
||
matic repeated in relation to the State. For models of realization, though
|
||
varied, are supposed to be isomorphic with regard to the axiomatic they
|
||
effectuate; however, this isomorphy, concrete variations considered,
|
||
accommodates itself to the greatest of formal differences. Moreover, a sin-
|
||
gle axiomatic seems capable of encompassing polymorphic models, not
|
||
only when it is not yet "saturated," but with those models as integral ele-
|
||
ments of its saturation.54 These "problems" become singularly political
|
||
when we think of modern States.
|
||
1. Are not all modern States isomorphic in relation to the capitalist axi-
|
||
omatic, to the point that the difference between democratic, totalitarian,
|
||
liberal, and tyrannical States depends only on concrete variables, and on
|
||
the worldwide distribution of those variables, which always undergo even-
|
||
tual readjustments? Even the so-called socialist States are isomorphic, to
|
||
the extent that there is only one world market, the capitalist one.
|
||
2. Conversely, does not the world capitalist axiomatic tolerate a real
|
||
polymorphy, or even a heteromorphy, of models, and for two reasons? On
|
||
the one hand, capital as a general relation of production can very easily
|
||
integrate concrete sectors or modes of production that are noncapitalist.
|
||
But on the other hand, and this is the main point, the bureaucratic socialist
|
||
States can themselves develop different modes of production that only
|
||
conjugate with capitalism to form a set whose "power" exceeds that of the
|
||
axiomatic itself (it will be necessary to try to determine the nature of this
|
||
456 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
power, why we so often think of it in apocalyptic terms, what conflicts it
|
||
spawns, what slim chances it leaves u s . . .)•
|
||
3. A typology of modern States is thus coupled with a metaeconomics:
|
||
it would be inaccurate to treat all States as "interchangeable" (even
|
||
isomorphy does not have that consequence), but it would be no less inac-
|
||
curate to privilege a certain form of the State (forgetting that polymorphy
|
||
establishes strict complementarities between the Western democracies
|
||
and the colonial or neocolonial tyrannies that they install or support in
|
||
other regions) or to equate the bureaucratic socialist States with the totali-
|
||
tarian capitalist States (neglecting the fact that the axiomatic can encom-
|
||
pass a real heteromorphy from which the higher power of the aggregate
|
||
derives, even if it is for the worse).
|
||
What is called a nation-state, in the most diverse forms, is precisely the
|
||
State as a model of realization. And the birth of nations implies many arti-
|
||
fices: Not only are they constituted in an active struggle against the imper-
|
||
ial or evolved systems, the feudal systems, and the autonomous cities, but
|
||
they crush their own "minorities," in other words, minoritarian phenom-
|
||
ena that could be termed "nationalitarian," which work from within and if
|
||
need be turn to the old codes to find a greater degree of freedom. The con-
|
||
stituents of the nation are a land and a people: the "natal," which is not nec-
|
||
essarily innate, and the "popular," which is not necessarily pregiven. The
|
||
problem of the nation is aggravated in the two extreme cases of a land with-
|
||
out a people and a people without a land. How can a people and a land be
|
||
made, in other words, a nation—a refrain? The coldest and bloodiest
|
||
means vie with upsurges of romanticism. The axiomatic is complex, and is
|
||
not without passions. The natal or the land, as we have seen elsewhere,
|
||
implies a certain deterritorialization of the territories (community land,
|
||
imperial provinces, seigneurial domains, etc.), and the people, a decoding
|
||
of the population. The nation is constituted on the basis of these flows and
|
||
is inseparable from the modern State that gives consistency to the corre-
|
||
sponding land and people. It is the flow of naked labor that makes the peo-
|
||
ple, just as it is the flow of Capital that makes the land and its industrial
|
||
base. In short, the nation is the very operation of a collective subjecti-
|
||
fication, to which the modern State corresponds as a process of subjection.
|
||
It is in the form of the nation-state, with all its possible variations, that the
|
||
State becomes the model of realization for the capitalist axiomatic. This is
|
||
not at all to say that nations are appearances or ideological phenomena; on
|
||
the contrary, they are the passional and living forms in which the qualita-
|
||
tive homogeneity and the quantitative competition of abstract capital are
|
||
first realized.
|
||
We distinguish machinic enslavement and social subjection as two sepa-
|
||
rate concepts. There is enslavement when human beings themselves are
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 457
|
||
|
||
constituent pieces of a machine that they compose among themselves and
|
||
with other things (animals, tools), under the control and direction of a
|
||
higher unity. But there is subjection when the higher unity constitutes the
|
||
human being as a subject linked to a now exterior object, which can be an
|
||
animal, a tool, or even a machine. The human being is no longer a compo-
|
||
nent of the machine but a worker, a user. He or she is subjected to the
|
||
machine and no longer enslaved by the machine. This is not to say that the
|
||
second regime is more human. But the first regime does seem to have a spe-
|
||
cial relation to the archaic imperial formation: human beings are not sub-
|
||
jects but pieces of a machine that overcodes the aggregate (this has been
|
||
called "generalized slavery," as opposed to the private slavery of antiquity,
|
||
or feudal serfdom). We believe that Lewis Mumford is right in designating
|
||
the archaic empires megamachines, and in pointing out that, once again, it
|
||
is not a question of a metaphor: "If a machine can be defined more or less in
|
||
accord with the classic definition of Reuleaux, as a combination of resist-
|
||
ant parts, each specialized in function, operating under human control to
|
||
transmit motion and to perform work, then the human machine was a real
|
||
machine."55 Of course, it was the modern State and capitalism that brought
|
||
the triumph of machines, in particular of motorized machines (whereas
|
||
the archaic State had simple machines at best); but what we are referring to
|
||
now are technical machines, which are definable extrinsically. One is not
|
||
enslaved by the technical machine but rather subjected to it. It would
|
||
appear, then, that the modern State, through technological development,
|
||
has substituted an increasingly powerful social subjection for machinic
|
||
enslavement. Ancient slavery and feudal serfdom were already procedures
|
||
of subjection. But the naked or "free" worker of capitalism takes subjection
|
||
to its most radical expression, since the processes of subjectification no
|
||
longer even enter into partial conjunctions that interrupt the flow. In
|
||
effect, capital acts as the point of subjectification that constitutes all
|
||
human beings as subjects; but some, the "capitalists," are subjects of enun-
|
||
ciation that form the private subjectivity of capital, while the others, the
|
||
"proletarians," are subjects of the statement, subjected to the technical
|
||
machines in which constant capital is effectuated. The wage regime can
|
||
therefore take the subjection of human beings to an unprecedented point,
|
||
and exhibit a singular cruelty, yet still be justified in its humanist cry: No,
|
||
human beings are not machines, we don't treat them like machines, we cer-
|
||
tainly don't confuse variable capital and constant capital.. .
|
||
Capitalism arises as a worldwide enterprise of subjectification by con-
|
||
stituting an axiomatic of decoded flows. Social subjection, as the correlate
|
||
of subjectification, appears much more in the axiomatic's models of real-
|
||
ization than in the axiomatic itself. It is within the framework of the
|
||
nation-State, or of national subjectivities, that processes of subjectifica-
|
||
458 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
tion and the corresponding subjections are manifested. The axiomatic
|
||
itself, of which the States are models of realization, restores or reinvents, in
|
||
new and now technical forms, an entire system of machinic enslavement.
|
||
This in no way represents a return to the imperial machine since we are now
|
||
in the immanence of an axiomatic, and not under the transcendence of a
|
||
formal Unity. But it is the reinvention of a machine of which human beings
|
||
are constituent parts, instead of subjected workers or users. If motorized
|
||
machines constituted the second age of the technical machine, cybernetic
|
||
and informational machines form a third age that reconstructs a gener-
|
||
alized regime of subjection: recurrent and reversible "humans-machines
|
||
systems" replace the old nonrecurrent and nonreversible relations of sub-
|
||
jection between the two elements; the relation between human and
|
||
machine is based on internal, mutual communication, and no longer on
|
||
usage or action.56 In the organic composition of capital, variable capital
|
||
defines a regime of subjection of the worker (human surplus value), the
|
||
principal framework of which is the business or factory. But with automa-
|
||
tion comes a progressive increase in the proportion of constant capital; we
|
||
then see a new kind of enslavement: at the same time the work regime
|
||
changes, surplus value becomes machinic, and the framework expands to
|
||
all of society. It could also be said that a small amount of subjectification
|
||
took us away from machinic enslavement, but a large amount brings us
|
||
back to it. Attention has recently been focused on the fact that modern
|
||
power is not at all reducible to the classical alternative "repression or ideol-
|
||
ogy" but implies processes of normalization, modulation, modeling, and
|
||
information that bear on language, perception, desire, movement, etc.,
|
||
and which proceed by way of microassemblages. This aggregate includes
|
||
both subjection and enslavement taken to extremes, as two simultaneous
|
||
parts that constantly reinforce and nourish each other. For example, one is
|
||
subjected to TV insofar as one uses and consumes it, in the very particular
|
||
situation of a subject of the statement that more or less mistakes itself for a
|
||
subject of enunciation ("you, dear television viewers, who make TV what it
|
||
is . . ."); the technical machine is the medium between two subjects. But
|
||
one is enslaved by TV as a human machine insofar as the television viewers
|
||
are no longer consumers or users, nor even subjects who supposedly
|
||
"make" it, but intrinsic component pieces, "input" and "output," feedback
|
||
or recurrences that are no longer connected to the machine in such a way as
|
||
to produce or use it. In machinic enslavement, there is nothing but trans-
|
||
formations and exchanges of information, some of which are mechanical,
|
||
others human. 57 The term "subjection," of course, should not be confined
|
||
to the national aspect, with enslavement seen as international or world-
|
||
wide. For information technology is also the property of the States that set
|
||
themselves up as humans-machines systems. But this is so precisely to the
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 459
|
||
|
||
extent that the two aspects, the axiomatic and the models of realization,
|
||
constantly cross over into each other and are themselves in communica-
|
||
tion. Social subjection proportions itself to the model of realization, just as
|
||
machinic enslavement expands to meet the dimensions of the axiomatic
|
||
that is effectuated in the model. We have the privilege of undergoing the
|
||
two operations simultaneously, in relation to the same things and the same
|
||
events. Rather than stages, subjection and enslavement constitute two
|
||
coexistent poles.
|
||
We may return to the different forms of the State, from the standpoint of
|
||
a universal history. We distinguish three major forms: (1) imperial archaic
|
||
States, which are paradigms and constitute a machine of enslavement by
|
||
overcoding already-coded flows (these States have little diversity, due to a
|
||
certain formal immutability that applies to all of them); (2) extremely
|
||
diverse States—evolved empires, autonomous cities, feudal systems,
|
||
monarchies—which proceed instead by subjectification and subjection,
|
||
and constitute qualified or topical conjunctions of decoded flows; 3) the
|
||
modern nation-States, which take decoding even further and are models of
|
||
realization for an axiomatic or a general conjugation of flows (these States
|
||
combine social subjection and the new machinic enslavement, and their
|
||
very diversity is a function of isomorphy, of the eventual heteromorphy or
|
||
polymorphy of the models in relation to the axiomatic).
|
||
There are, of course, all kinds of external circumstances that mark pro-
|
||
found breaks between these types of States, and above all submit the
|
||
archaic empires to utter oblivion, a shrouding lifted only by archaeology.
|
||
The empires disappeared suddenly, as though in an instantaneous catas-
|
||
trophe. As in the Dorian invasion, a war machine looms up and bears down
|
||
from without, killing memory. Yet things proceed quite differently on the
|
||
inside, where all the States resonate together, appropriate armies for them-
|
||
selves, and exhibit a unity of composition in spite of their differences in
|
||
organization and development. It is evident that all decoded flows, of
|
||
whatever kind, are prone to forming a war machine directed against the
|
||
State. But everything changes depending on whether these flows connect
|
||
up with a war machine or, on the contrary, enter into conjunctions or a gen-
|
||
eral conjugation that appropriates them for the State. From this stand-
|
||
point, the modern States have a kind of transspatiotemporal unity with the
|
||
archaic State. The internal correlation between 1 and 2 appears most
|
||
clearly in the fact that the fragmented forms of the Aegean world presup-
|
||
pose the great imperial form of the Orient and find in it a stock or agricul-
|
||
tural surplus, which they consequently have no need to produce or
|
||
accumulate for themselves. And to the extent that the States of the second
|
||
age are nevertheless obliged to reconstitute a stock, if only because of exter-
|
||
nal circumstances—what State can do without one?—in so doing they
|
||
460 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
always reactivate an evolved imperial form. We find the revival of this
|
||
form in the Greek, Roman, and feudal worlds: there is always an empire on
|
||
the horizon, which for the subjective States plays the role of signifier and
|
||
encompassing element. And the correlation between 2 and 3 is no less pro-
|
||
nounced, for industrial revolutions are not wanting, and the difference
|
||
between topical conjunctions and the great conjugation of decoded flows is
|
||
so thin that one is left with the impression that capitalism was continually
|
||
being born, disappearing and reviving at every crossroads of history. And
|
||
the correlation between 3 and 1 is also a necessary one: the modern States
|
||
of the third age do indeed restore the most absolute of empires, a new
|
||
"megamachine," whatever the novelty or timeliness of its now immanent
|
||
form; they do this by realizing an axiomatic that functions as much by
|
||
machinic enslavement as by social subjection. Capitalism has reawakened
|
||
the Urstaat, and given it new strength.58
|
||
Not only, as Hegel said, does every State imply "the essential moments
|
||
of its existence as a State," but there is a unique moment, in the sense of a
|
||
coupling of forces, and this moment of the State is capture, bond, knot,
|
||
nexum, magical capture. Must we speak of a second pole, which would
|
||
operate instead by pact and contract? Is this not instead that other force,
|
||
with capture as the unique moment of coupling? For the two forces are the
|
||
overcoding of coded flows, and the treatment of decoded flows. The con-
|
||
tract is a juridical expression of the second aspect: it appears as the pro-
|
||
ceeding of subjectification, the outcome of which is subjection. And the
|
||
contract must be pushed to the extreme; in other words, it is no longer con-
|
||
cluded between two people but between self and self, within the same
|
||
person—Ich = Ich—as subjected and sovereign. The extreme perversion
|
||
of the contract, reinstating the purest of knots. The knot, bond, capture,
|
||
thus travel a long history: first, the objective, imperial collective bond; then
|
||
all of the forms of subjective personal bonds; finally, the Subject that binds
|
||
itself, and in so doing renews the most magical operation, "a cosmopolitan,
|
||
universal energy which overflows every restriction and bond so as to estab-
|
||
lish itself instead as the sole bond."59 Even subjection is only a relay for the
|
||
fundamental moment of the State, namely, civil capture or machinic
|
||
enslavement. The State is assuredly not the locus of liberty, nor the agent of
|
||
a forced servitude or war capture. Should we then speak of "voluntary ser-
|
||
vitude"? This is like the expression "magical capture": its only merit is to
|
||
underline the apparent mystery. There is a machinic enslavement, about
|
||
which it could be said in each case that it presupposes itself, that it appears
|
||
as preaccomplished; this machinic enslavement is no more "voluntary"
|
||
than it is "forced."
|
||
PROPOSITION XIV. Axiomatics and thepresentday situation.
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 461
|
||
|
||
Politics is by no means an apodictic science. It proceeds by experimen-
|
||
tation, groping in the dark, injection, withdrawal, advances, retreats. The
|
||
factors of decision and prediction are limited. It is an absurdity to postu-
|
||
late a world supergovernment that makes the final decisions. No one is
|
||
even capable of predicting the growth in the money supply. Similarly, the
|
||
States are affected by all kinds of coefficients of uncertainty and unpredict-
|
||
ability. John Kenneth Galbraith and Francois Chatelet have formulated
|
||
the concept of constant and decisive errors, which make the glory of men of
|
||
State no less than their rare successful evaluations. But that is just one
|
||
more reason to make a connection between politics and axiomatics. For in
|
||
science an axiomatic is not at all a transcendent, autonomous, and
|
||
decision-making power opposed to experimentation and intuition. On the
|
||
one hand, it has its own gropings in the dark, experimentations, modes of
|
||
intuition. Axioms being independent of each other, can they be added, and
|
||
up to what point (a saturated system)? Can they be withdrawn (a "weak-
|
||
ened" system)? On the other hand, it is of the nature of axiomatics to come
|
||
up against so-called undecidable propositions, to confront necessarily
|
||
higher powers that it cannot master.60 Finally, axiomatics does not consti-
|
||
tute the cutting edge of science; it is much more a stopping point, a reorder-
|
||
ing that prevents decoded semiotic flows in physics and mathematics from
|
||
escaping in all directions. The great axiomaticians are the men of State of
|
||
science, who seal off the lines of flight that are so frequent in mathematics,
|
||
who would impose a new nexum, if only a temporary one, and who lay
|
||
down the official policies of science. They are the heirs of the theorematic
|
||
conception of geometry. When intuitionism opposed axiomatics, it was
|
||
not only in the name of intuition, of construction and creation, but also in
|
||
the name of a calculus of problems, a problematic conception of science
|
||
that was not less abstract but implied an entirely different abstract
|
||
machine, one working in the undecidable and the fugitive.61 It is the real
|
||
characteristics of axiomatics that lead us to say that capitalism and pres-
|
||
ent-day politics are an axiomatic in the literal sense. But it is precisely for
|
||
this reason that nothing is played out in advance. From this standpoint, we
|
||
may present a summary sketch of the "givens."
|
||
|
||
1. Addition, subtraction. The axioms of capitalism are obviously not
|
||
theoretical propositions, or ideological formulas, but operative statements
|
||
that constitute the semiological form of Capital and that enter as compo-
|
||
nent parts into assemblages of production, circulation, and consumption.
|
||
The axioms are primary statements, which do not derive from or depend
|
||
upon another statement. In this sense, a flow can be the object of one or
|
||
several axioms (with the set of all axioms constituting the conjugation of
|
||
the flows); but it can also lack any axioms of its own, its treatment being
|
||
462 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
only a consequence of other axioms; finally, it can remain out of bounds,
|
||
evolve without limits, be left in the state of an "untamed" variation in the
|
||
system. There is a tendency within capitalism continually to add more axi-
|
||
oms. After the end of World War I, the joint influence of the world depres-
|
||
sion and the Russian Revolution forced capitalism to multiply its axioms,
|
||
to invent new ones dealing with the working class, employment, union
|
||
organization, social institutions, the role of the State, the foreign and
|
||
domestic markets. Keynesian economics and the New Deal were axiom
|
||
laboratories. Examples of the creation of new axioms after the Second
|
||
World War: the Marshall Plan, forms of assistance and lending, transfor-
|
||
mations in the monetary system. It is not only in periods of expansion or
|
||
recovery that axioms multiply. What makes the axiomatic vary, in relation
|
||
to the States, is the distinction and relation between the foreign and domes-
|
||
tic markets. There is a multiplication of axioms most notably when an inte-
|
||
grated domestic market is being organized to meet the requirements of the
|
||
foreign market. Axioms for the young, for the old, for women, etc. A very
|
||
general pole of the State, "social democracy," can be defined by this ten-
|
||
dency to add, invent axioms in relation to spheres of investment and
|
||
sources of profit: the question is not that of freedom and constraint, nor of
|
||
centralism and decentralization, but of the manner in which one masters
|
||
the flows. In this case, they are mastered by the multiplication of directing
|
||
axioms. The opposite tendency is no less a part of capitalism: the tendency
|
||
to withdraw, subtract axioms. One falls back on a very small number of axi-
|
||
oms regulating the dominant flows, while the other flows are given a deriv-
|
||
ative, consequential status (defined by the "theorems" ensuing from the
|
||
axioms), or are left in an untamed state that does not preclude the brutal
|
||
intervention of State power, quite the contrary. The "totalitarianism" pole
|
||
of the State incarnates this tendency to restrict the number of axioms, and
|
||
operates by the exclusive promotion of the foreign sector: the appeal to for-
|
||
eign sources of capital, the rise of industries aimed at the exportation of
|
||
foodstuffs or raw materials, the collapse of the domestic market. The totali-
|
||
tarian State iS not a maximum State but rather, following Virilio's formula-
|
||
tion, the minimum State of anarcho-capitalism (cf. Chile). At the limit, the
|
||
only axioms that are retained concern the equilibrium of the foreign sector,
|
||
reserve levels and the inflation rate; "the population is no longer a given, it
|
||
has become a consequence." As for untamed evolutions, they appear
|
||
among other places in the variations in the employment level, in the phe-
|
||
nomena of exodus from the countryside, shantytown-urbanization, etc.
|
||
The case of fascism ("national socialism") is distinct from totalitarian-
|
||
ism. It coincides with the totalitarian pole in the collapse of the domestic
|
||
market and the reduction in the number of axioms. However, the promo-
|
||
tion of the foreign sector does not at all take place through an appeal to for-
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 463
|
||
|
||
eign sources of capital and through export industries, but through a war
|
||
economy, which entails an expansionism foreign to totalitarianism and an
|
||
autonomous fabrication of capital. As for the domestic market, it is effec-
|
||
tuated in a specific production of the Ersatz. This means that fascism, too,
|
||
brings a proliferation of axioms, which explains why it has often been com-
|
||
pared to a Keynesian economy. Fascism, however, is a tautological or ficti-
|
||
tious proliferation, a multiplication by subtraction; this makes it a very
|
||
special case.62
|
||
|
||
2. Saturation. Can we express the distribution of the two opposite ten-
|
||
dencies by saying that the saturation of the system marks the point of inver-
|
||
sion? No, for the saturation is itself relative. If Marx demonstrated the
|
||
functioning of capitalism as an axiomatic, it was above all in the famous
|
||
chapter on the tendency of the rate of profit to fall. Capitalism is indeed an
|
||
axiomatic, because it has no laws but immanent ones. It would like for us to
|
||
believe that it confronts the limits of the Universe, the extreme limit of
|
||
resources and energy. But all it confronts are its own limits (the periodic
|
||
depreciation of existing capital); all it repels or displaces are its own limits
|
||
(the formation of new capital, in new industries with a high profit rate).
|
||
This is the history of oil and nuclear power. And it does both at once: capi-
|
||
talism confronts its own limits and simultaneously displaces them, setting
|
||
them down again farther along. It could be said that the totalitarian ten-
|
||
dency to restrict the number of axioms corresponds to the confrontation
|
||
with the limits, whereas the social democratic tendency corresponds to the
|
||
displacement of the limits. But one does not come without the other, either
|
||
in two different but coexistent places or in two successive but closely linked
|
||
moments; they always have a hold on each other, or are even contained in
|
||
each other, constituting the same axiomatic. A typical example would be
|
||
present-day Brazil, with its ambiguous alternative "totalitarianism-social
|
||
democracy." As a general rule, the limits are all the more mobile if axioms
|
||
are subtracted in one place but added elsewhere.
|
||
It would be an error to take a disinterested stance toward struggle on the
|
||
level of the axioms. It is sometimes thought that every axiom, in capitalism
|
||
or in one of its States, constitutes a "recuperation." But this disenchanted
|
||
concept is not a good one. The constant readjustments of the capitalist axi-
|
||
omatic, in other words, the additions (the enunciation of new axioms) and
|
||
the withdrawals (the creation of exclusive axioms), are the object of strug-
|
||
gles in no way confined to the technocracy. Everywhere, the workers' strug-
|
||
gles overspill the framework of the capitalist enterprises, which imply for
|
||
the most part derivative propositions. The struggles bear directly upon the
|
||
axioms that presi de over the State's public spending, or that even concern a
|
||
specific international organization (for example, a multinational corpora-
|
||
464 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
tion can at will plan the liquidation of a factory inside a country). The
|
||
resulting danger of a worldwide labor bureaucracy or technocracy taking
|
||
charge of these problems can be warded off only to the extent that local
|
||
struggles directly target national and international axioms, at the precise
|
||
point of their insertion in the field of immanence (the potential of the rural
|
||
world in this respect). There is always a fundamental difference between
|
||
living flows and the axioms that subordinate them to centers of control and
|
||
decision making, that make a given segment correspond to them, which
|
||
measure their quanta. But the pressure of the living flows, and of the prob-
|
||
lems they pose and impose, must be exerted inside the axiomatic, as much
|
||
in order to fight the totalitarian reductions as to anticipate and precipitate
|
||
the additions, to orient them and prevent their technocratic perversion.
|
||
|
||
3. Models, isomorphy. In principle, all States are isomorphic; in other
|
||
words, they are domains of realization of capital as a function of a sole
|
||
external world market. But the first question is whether isomorphy implies
|
||
a homogeneity or even a homogenization of States. The answer is yes, as
|
||
can be seen in present-day Europe with respect to justice and the police, the
|
||
highway code, the circulation of commodities, production costs, etc. But
|
||
this is true only insofar as there is a tendency toward a single integrated
|
||
domestic market. Otherwise, isomorphy in no way implies homogeneity:
|
||
there is isomorphy, but heterogeneity, between totalitarian and social dem-
|
||
ocratic States wherever the mode of production is the same. The general
|
||
rules regarding this are as follows: the consistency, the totality (I 'ensemble),
|
||
or unity of the axiomatic are defined by capital as a "right" or relation of
|
||
production (for the market); the respective independence of the axioms in
|
||
no way contradicts this totality but derives from the divisions or sectors of
|
||
the capitalist mode of production; the isomorphy of the models, with the
|
||
two poles of addition and subtraction, depends on how the domestic and
|
||
foreign markets are distributed in each case.
|
||
But this is only a first bipolarity, applying to the States that are located
|
||
at the center and are under the capitalist mode of production. A second,
|
||
West-East, bipolarity has been imposed on the States of the center, that of
|
||
the capitalist States and the bureaucratic socialist States. Although this
|
||
new distinction may share certain traits of the first (the so-called socialist
|
||
States being assimilable to the totalitarian States), the problem lies else-
|
||
where. The numerous "convergence" theories that attempt to demon-
|
||
strate a certain homogenization of the States of the East and West are not
|
||
very convincing. Even isomorphism is not applicable: there is a real
|
||
heteromorphy, not only because the mode of production is not capitalist,
|
||
but also because the relation of production is not Capital (rather, it is the
|
||
Plan). If the socialist States are nevertheless still models of realization for
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 465
|
||
|
||
the capitalist axiomatic, it is due to the existence of a single external
|
||
world market, which remains the deciding factor here, even above and
|
||
beyond the relations of production from which it results. It can even hap-
|
||
pen that the socialist bureaucraticplan(e) takes on a parasitic function in
|
||
relation to the plan(e) of capital, which manifests a greater creativity, of
|
||
the "virus" type.
|
||
Finally, the third fundamental bipolarity is the center and the periphery
|
||
(North-South). In view of the respective independence of the axioms, we
|
||
can join Samir Amin in saying that the axioms of the periphery differ from
|
||
those of the center.63 And here again, the difference and independence of
|
||
the axioms in no way compromise the consistency of the overall axiomatic.
|
||
On the contrary, central capitalism needs the periphery constituted by the
|
||
Third World, where it locates a large part of its most modern industries; it
|
||
does not just invest capital in these industries, but is also furnished with
|
||
capital by them. The issue of the dependence of the Third World States is of
|
||
course an obvious one, but not the most important one (it was bequeathed
|
||
by the old colonialism). It is obvious that having independent axioms has
|
||
never guaranteed the independence of States; rather it ensures an interna-
|
||
tional division of labor. The important question, once again, is that of
|
||
isomorphy in relation to the worldwide axiomatic. To a large extent, there
|
||
is isomorphy between the United States and the bloodiest of the South
|
||
American tyrannies (or between France, England, and West Germany and
|
||
certain African States). The center-periphery bipolarity, States of the cen-
|
||
ter and States of the Third World, may well exhibit some of the distinguish-
|
||
ing traits of the two preceding bipolarities, but it also evades them, raising
|
||
other problems. Throughout a vast portion of the Third World, the general
|
||
relation of production is capital—even throughout the entire Third World,
|
||
in the sense that the socialized sector may utilize that relation, adopting it
|
||
in this case. But the mode of production is not necessarily capitalist, either
|
||
in the so-called archaic or transitional forms, or in the most productive,
|
||
highly industrialized sectors. This indeed represents a third case, included
|
||
in the worldwide axiomatic: when capital acts as the relation of production
|
||
but in noncapitalist modes of production. We may therefore speak of a
|
||
polymorphy of the Third World States in relation to the States of the center.
|
||
And this dimension of the axiomatic is no less necessary than the others; it
|
||
is even much more necessary, for the heteromorphy of the so-called social-
|
||
ist States was imposed upon capitalism, which digested it as best it could,
|
||
whereas the polymorphy of the Third World States is partially organized
|
||
by the center, as an axiom providing a substitute for colonization.
|
||
We are always brought back to the literal question of the models of real-
|
||
ization of a worldwide axiomatic: there is in principle an isomorphy of the
|
||
States of the center, a heteromorphy imposed by the bureaucratic socialist
|
||
466 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
State, and a polymorphy organized by the Third World States. Once again,
|
||
it would be absurd to think that the insertion of popular movements is con-
|
||
demned in advance throughout this field of immanence, and to assume
|
||
that there are either "good" States that are democratic, social democratic
|
||
or at the other extreme socialist, or that on the contrary all States are equiv-
|
||
alent and homogeneous.
|
||
|
||
4. Power (puissance). Let us suppose that the axiomatic necessarily mar-
|
||
shals a power higher than the one it treats, in other words, than that of the
|
||
aggregates serving as its models. This is like a power of the continuum, tied
|
||
to the axiomatic but exceeding it. We immediately recognize this power as
|
||
a power of destruction, of war, a power incarnated in financial, industrial,
|
||
and military technological complexes that are in continuity with one
|
||
another. On the one hand, war clearly follows the same movement as capi-
|
||
talism: In the same way as the proportion of constant capital keeps grow-
|
||
ing, war becomes increasingly a "war of materiel" in which the human
|
||
being no longer even represents a variable capital of subjection, but is
|
||
instead a pure element of machinic enslavement. On the other hand, and
|
||
this is the main point, the growing importance of constant capital in the
|
||
axiomatic means that the depreciation of existing capital and the forma-
|
||
tion of new capital assume a rhythm and scale that necessarily take the
|
||
route of a war machine now incarnated in the complexes: the complexes
|
||
actively contribute to the redistributions of the world necessary for the
|
||
exploitation of maritime and planetary resources. There is a continuous
|
||
"threshold" of power that accompanies in every instance the shifting of the
|
||
axiomatic's limits; it is as though the power of war always supersaturated
|
||
the system's saturation, and was its necessary condition.
|
||
The classical conflicts among the States of the center (as well as periph-
|
||
eral colonization) have been joined, or rather replaced, by two great
|
||
conflictual lines, between West and East and North and South; these lines
|
||
intersect and together cover everything. But the overarmament of the West
|
||
and East not only leaves the reality of local wars entirely intact and gives
|
||
them a new force and new stakes; it not only founds the "apocalyptic" pos-
|
||
sibility of a direct confrontation along the two great axes; it also seems that
|
||
the war machine takes on a specific supplementary meaning: industrial,
|
||
political, judicial, etc. It is indeed true that the States, throughout their his-
|
||
tory, have repeatedly appropriated the war machine; and it was after the
|
||
war machine was appropriated that war, its preparation and effectuation,
|
||
became the exclusive object of the machine, but as a more or less "limited"
|
||
war. As for the aim, it remained the political aim of the States. The various
|
||
factors that tended to make war a "total war," most notably the fascist fac-
|
||
tor, marked the beginning of an inversion of the movement: as though the
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 467
|
||
|
||
States, through the war they waged against one another, had after a long
|
||
period of appropriation reconstituted an autonomous war machine. But
|
||
this unchained or liberated war machine continued to have as its object war
|
||
in action, a now total, unlimited kind of war. The entire fascist economy
|
||
became a war economy, but the war economy still needed total war as its
|
||
object. For this reason, fascist war still fell under Clausewitz's formula,
|
||
"the continuation of politics by other means," even though those other
|
||
means had become exclusive, in other words, the political aim had entered
|
||
into contradiction with the object (hence Virilio's idea that the fascist State
|
||
was a "suicidal" State more than a totalitarian one). It was only after World
|
||
War II that the automatization, then automation of the war machine had
|
||
their true effect. The war machine, the new antagonisms traversing it con-
|
||
sidered, no longer had war as its exclusive object but took in charge and as
|
||
its object peace, politics, the world order, in short, the aim. This is where
|
||
the inversion of Clausewitz's formula comes in: it is politics that becomes
|
||
the continuation of war; // is peace that technologically frees the unlimited
|
||
material process of total war. War ceases to be the materialization of the war
|
||
machine; the war machine itself becomes materialized war. In this sense,
|
||
there was no longer a need for fascism. The Fascists were only child precur-
|
||
sors, and the absolute peace of survival succeeded where total war had
|
||
failed. The Third World War was already upon us. The war machine
|
||
reigned over the entire axiomatic like the power of the continuum that sur-
|
||
rounded the "world-economy," and it put all the parts of the universe in
|
||
contact. The world became a smooth space again (sea, air, atmosphere),
|
||
over which reigned a single war machine, even when it opposed its own
|
||
parts. Wars had become a part of peace. More than that, the States no
|
||
longer appropriated the war machine; they reconstituted a war machine of
|
||
which they themselves were only the parts.
|
||
Of all the authors who have developed an apocalyptic or millenarian
|
||
sense, it is to Paul Virilio's credit to have emphasized these five rigorous
|
||
points: that the war machine finds its new object in the absolute peace of
|
||
terror or deterrence; that it performs a technoscientific "capitalization";
|
||
that this war machine is terrifying not as a function of a possible war that
|
||
it promises us, as by blackmail, but, on the contrary, as a function of the
|
||
real, very special kind of peace it promotes and has already installed; that
|
||
this war machine no longer needs a qualified enemy but, in conformity
|
||
with the requirements of an axiomatic, operates against the "unspecified
|
||
enemy," domestic or foreign (an individual, group, class, people, event,
|
||
world); that there arose from this a new conception of security as materia-
|
||
lized war, as organized insecurity or molecularized, distributed, pro-
|
||
grammed catastrophe.64
|
||
468 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
5. The included middle. No one has demonstrated more convincingly
|
||
than Braudel that the capitalist axiomatic requires a center and that this
|
||
center was constituted in the North, at the outcome of a long historical
|
||
process: "There can only be a world-economy when the mesh of the net-
|
||
work is sufficiently fine, and when exchange is regular and voluminous
|
||
enough to give rise to a central zone."65 Many authors believe on this
|
||
account that the North-South, center-periphery axis is more important
|
||
today than the West-East axis, and even principally determines it. This is
|
||
expressed in a common thesis, taken up and developed by Valery Giscard
|
||
d'Estaing: the more equilibrated things become at the center between the
|
||
West and the East, beginning with the equilibrium of overarmament, the
|
||
more they become disequilibrated or "destabilized" from North to South
|
||
and destabilize the central equilibrium. It is clear that in these formulas the
|
||
South is an abstract term designating the Third World or the periphery;
|
||
and even that there are Souths or Third Worlds inside the center. It is also
|
||
clear that this destabilization is not accidental but is a (theorematic) conse-
|
||
quence of the axioms of capitalism, principally of the axiom called unequal
|
||
exchange, which is indispensable to capitalism's functioning. This for-
|
||
mula is therefore the modern version of the oldest formula, which already
|
||
obtained in the archaic empires under different conditions. The more the
|
||
archaic empire overcoded the flows, the more it stimulated decoded flows
|
||
that turned back against it and forced it to change. The more the decoded
|
||
flows enter into a central axiomatic, the more they tend to escape to the
|
||
periphery, to present problems that the axiomatic is incapable of resolving
|
||
or controlling (even by adding special axioms for the periphery).
|
||
The four principal flows that torment the representatives of the world
|
||
economy, or of the axiomatic, are the flow of matter-energy, the flow of
|
||
population, the flow of food, and the urban flow. The situation seems inex-
|
||
tricable because the axiomatic never ceases to create all of these problems,
|
||
while at the same time its axioms, even multiplied, deny it the means of
|
||
resolving them (for example, the circulation and distribution that would
|
||
make it possible to feed the world). Even a social democracy adapted to the
|
||
Third World surely does not undertake to integrate the whole poverty-
|
||
stricken population into the domestic market; what it does, rather, is to
|
||
effect the class rupture that will select the integratable elements. And the
|
||
States of the center deal not only with the Third World, each of them has
|
||
not only an external Third World, but there are internal Third Worlds that
|
||
rise up within them and work them from the inside. It could even be said in
|
||
certain respects that the periphery and the center exchange determina-
|
||
tions: a deterritorialization of the center, a decoding of the center in rela-
|
||
tion to national and territorial aggregates, cause the peripheral formations
|
||
to become true centers of investment, while the central formations
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 469
|
||
|
||
peripheralize. This simultaneously strengthens and relativizes Samir
|
||
Amin's theses. The more the worldwide axiomatic installs high industry
|
||
and highly industrialized agriculture at the periphery, provisionally
|
||
reserving for the center so-called postindustrial activities (automation,
|
||
electronics, information technologies, the conquest of space, overarma-
|
||
ment, etc.), the more it installs peripheral zones of underdevelopment
|
||
inside the center, internal Third Worlds, internal Souths. "Masses" of the
|
||
population are abandoned to erratic work (subcontracting, temporary
|
||
work, or work in the underground economy), and their official subsistence
|
||
is assured only by State allocations and wages subject to interruption. It is
|
||
to the credit of thinkers like Antonio Negri to have formulated, on the basis
|
||
of the exemplary case of Italy, the theory of this internal margin, which
|
||
tends increasingly to merge the students with the emarginati.66 These phe-
|
||
nomena confirm the difference between the new machinic enslavement
|
||
and classical subjection. For subjection remained centered on labor and
|
||
involved a bipolar organization, property-labor, bourgeoisie-proletariat.
|
||
In enslavement and the central dominance of constant capital, on the other
|
||
hand, labor seems to have splintered in two directions: intensive surplus
|
||
labor that no longer even takes the route of labor, and extensive labor that
|
||
has become erratic and floating. The totalitarian tendency to abandon axi-
|
||
oms of employment and the social democratic tendency to multiply stat-
|
||
utes can combine here, but always in order to effect class ruptures. The
|
||
opposition between the axiomatic and the flows it does not succeed in mas-
|
||
tering becomes all the more accentuated.
|
||
|
||
6. Minorities. Ours is becoming the age of minorities. We have seen sev-
|
||
eral times that minorities are not necessarily defined by the smallness of
|
||
their numbers but rather by becoming or a line of fluctuation, in other
|
||
words, by the gap that separates them from this or that axiom constituting a
|
||
redundant majority ("Ulysses, or today's average, urban European"; or as
|
||
Yann Moulier says, "the national Worker, qualified, male and over thirty-
|
||
five"). A minority can be small in number; but it can also be the largest in
|
||
number, constitute an absolute, indefinite majority. That is the situation
|
||
when authors, even those supposedly on the Left, repeat the great capitalist
|
||
warning cry: in twenty years, "whites" will form only 12 percent of the
|
||
world population. . . Thus they are not content to say that the majority will
|
||
change, or has already changed, but say that it is impinged upon by a
|
||
nondenumerable and proliferating minority that threatens to destroy the
|
||
very concept of majority, in other words, the majority as an axiom. And the
|
||
curious concept of nonwhite does not in fact constitute a denumerable set.
|
||
What defines a minority, then, is not the number but the relations internal
|
||
to the number. A minority can be numerous, or even infinite; so can a
|
||
470 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
majority. What distinguishes them is that in the case of a majority the rela-
|
||
tion internal to the number constitutes a set that may be finite or infinite,
|
||
but is always denumerable, whereas the minority is defined as a non-
|
||
denumerable set, however many elements it may have. What characterizes
|
||
the nondenumerable is neither the set nor its elements; rather, it is the con-
|
||
nection, the "and" produced between elements, between sets, and which
|
||
belongs to neither, which eludes them and constitutes a line of flight. The
|
||
axiomatic manipulates only denumerable sets, even infinite ones, whereas
|
||
the minorities constitute "fuzzy," nondenumerable, nonaxiomizable sets,
|
||
in short, "masses," multiplicities of escape and flux.
|
||
Whether it be the infinite set of the nonwhites of the periphery, or the
|
||
restricted set of the Basques, Corsicans, etc., everywhere we look we see the
|
||
conditions for a worldwide movement: the minorities recreate "nationali-
|
||
tarian" phenomena that the nation-states had been charged with control-
|
||
ling and quashing. The bureaucratic socialist sector is certainly not spared
|
||
by these movements, and as Amalrik said, the dissidents are nothing, or
|
||
serve only as pawns in international politics, if they are abstracted from the
|
||
minorities working the USSR. It matters little that the minorities are inca-
|
||
pable of constituting viable States from the point of view of the axiomatic
|
||
and the market, since in the long run they promote compositions that do
|
||
not pass by way of the capitalist economy any more than they do the State-
|
||
form. The response of the States, or of the axiomatic, may obviously be to
|
||
accord the minorities regional or federal or statutory autonomy, in short,
|
||
to add axioms. But this is not the problem: this operation consists only in
|
||
translating the minorities into denumerable sets or subsets, which would
|
||
enter as elements into the majority, which could be counted among the
|
||
majority. The same applies for a status accorded to women, young people,
|
||
erratic workers, etc. One could even imagine, in blood and crisis, a more
|
||
radical reversal that would make the white world the periphery of a yellow
|
||
world; there would doubtless be an entirely different axiomatic. But what
|
||
we are talking about is something else, something even that would not
|
||
resolve: women, nonmen, as a minority, as a nondenumerable flow or set,
|
||
would receive no adequate expression by becoming elements of the major-
|
||
ity, in other words, by becoming a denumerable finite set. Nonwhites
|
||
would receive no adequate expression by becoming a new yellow or black
|
||
majority, an infinite denumerable set. What is proper to the minority is to
|
||
assert a power of the nondenumerable, even if that minority is composed of
|
||
a single member. That is the formula for multiplicities. Minority as a uni-
|
||
versal figure, or becoming-everybody/everything (devenir tout le monde).
|
||
Woman: we all have to become that, whether we are male or female. Non-
|
||
white: we all have to become that, whether we are white, yellow, or black.
|
||
Once again, this is not to say that the struggle on the level of the axioms is
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 471
|
||
|
||
without importance; on the contrary, it is determining (at the most diverse
|
||
levels: women's struggle for the vote, for abortion, for jobs; the struggle of
|
||
the regions for autonomy; the struggle of the Third World; the struggle of
|
||
the oppressed masses and minorities in the East or West.. .)• But there is
|
||
also always a sign to indicate that these struggles are the index of another,
|
||
coexistent combat. However modest the demand, it always constitutes a
|
||
point that the axiomatic cannot tolerate: when people demand to formu-
|
||
late their problems themselves, and to determine at least the particular
|
||
conditions under which they can receive a more general solution (hold to
|
||
the Particular as an innovative form). It is always astounding to see the
|
||
same story repeated: the modesty of the minorities' initial demands, cou-
|
||
pled with the impotence of the axiomatic to resolve the slightest corre-
|
||
sponding problem. In short, the struggle around axioms is most important
|
||
when it manifests, itself opens, the gap between two types of propositions,
|
||
propositions of flow and propositions of axioms. The power of the minori-
|
||
ties is not measured by their capacity to enter and make themselves felt
|
||
within the majority system, nor even to reverse the necessarily tautolog-
|
||
ical criterion of the majority, but to bring to bear the force of the non-
|
||
denumerable sets, however small they may be, against the denumerable
|
||
sets, even if they are infinite, reversed, or changed, even they if imply new
|
||
axioms or, beyond that, a new axiomatic. The issue is not at all anarchy ver-
|
||
sus organization, nor even centralism versus decentralization, but a calcu-
|
||
lus or conception of the problems of nondenumerable sets, against the
|
||
axiomatic of denumerable sets. Such a calculus may have its own com-
|
||
positions, organizations, even centralizations; nevertheless, it proceeds
|
||
not via the States or the axiomatic process but via a pure becoming of
|
||
minorities.
|
||
|
||
7. Undecidablepropositions. It will be objected that the axiomatic itself
|
||
marshals the power of a nondenumerable infinite set: precisely that of the
|
||
war machine. It seems difficult, however, to use the war machine in the gen-
|
||
eral "treatment" of minorities without triggering the absolute war it is sup-
|
||
posed to ward off. We have seen the war machine institute quantitative and
|
||
qualitative processes, miniaturizations, and adaptations that enable it to
|
||
graduate its attacks or counterattacks, each time as a function of the nature
|
||
of the "unspecified enemy" (individuals, groups, peoples.. .). But under
|
||
these conditions, the capitalist axiomatic continually produces and repro-
|
||
duces what the war machine tries to exterminate. Even the organization of
|
||
famine multiplies the starving as much as it kills them. Even the organiza-
|
||
tion of camps, an area where the socialist sector has dreadfully distin-
|
||
guished itself, does not assure the radical solution of which power dreams.
|
||
The extermination of a minority engenders a minority of that minority.
|
||
472 D 7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE
|
||
|
||
However relentless the killing, it is relatively difficult to liquidate a people
|
||
or a group, even in the Third World, once it has enough connections with
|
||
elements of the axiomatic. In still other respects, it can be predicted that
|
||
the impending problems of the economy, which will consist in reforming
|
||
capital in relation to new resources (undersea oil, metallic nodules, food-
|
||
stuffs), will require not only a redistribution of the world that will mobilize
|
||
the worldwide war machine and train its parts on the new objectives; we
|
||
will also probably see the formation or re-formation of minoritarian aggre-
|
||
gates, in relation to the affected regions.
|
||
Generally speaking, minorities do not receive a better solution of their
|
||
problem by integration, even with axioms, statutes, autonomies, inde-
|
||
pendences. Their tactics necessarily go that route. But if they are revolu-
|
||
tionary, it is because they carry within them a deeper movement that
|
||
challenges the worldwide axiomatic. The power of minority, of particu-
|
||
larity, finds its figure or its universal consciousness in the proletariat. But
|
||
as long as the working class defines itself by an acquired status, or even by
|
||
a theoretically conquered State, it appears only as "capital," a part of cap-
|
||
ital (variable capital), and does not leave theplan(e) of capital. At best, the
|
||
plan(e) becomes bureaucratic. On the other hand, it is by leaving the
|
||
plan(e) of capital, and never ceasing to leave it, that a mass becomes
|
||
increasingly revolutionary and destroys the dominant equilibrium of the
|
||
denumerable sets.67 It is hard to see what an Amazon-State would be, a
|
||
women's State, or a State of erratic workers, a State of the "refusal" of
|
||
work. If minorities do not constitute viable States culturally, politically,
|
||
economically, it is because the State-form is not appropriate to them, nor
|
||
the axiomatic of capital, nor the corresponding culture. We have often
|
||
seen capitalism maintain and organize inviable States, according to its
|
||
needs, and for the precise purpose of crushing minorities. The minorities
|
||
issue is instead that of smashing capitalism, of redefining socialism, of
|
||
constituting a war machine capable of countering the world war machine
|
||
by other means.
|
||
If the two solutions of extermination and integration hardly seem possi-
|
||
ble, it is due to the deepest law of capitalism: it continually sets and then
|
||
repels its own limits, but in so doing gives rise to numerous flows in all
|
||
directions that escape its axiomatic. At the same time as capitalism is effec-
|
||
tuated in the denumerable sets serving as its models, it necessarily consti-
|
||
tutes nondenumerable sets that cut across and disrupt those models. It does
|
||
not effect the "conjugation" of the deterritorialized and decoded flows
|
||
without those flows forging farther ahead; without their escaping both the
|
||
axiomatic that conjugates them and the models that reterritorialize them;
|
||
without their tending to enter into "connections" that delineate a new
|
||
Land; without their constituting a war machine whose aim is neither the
|
||
7000 B.C.: APPARATUS OF CAPTURE D 473
|
||
|
||
war of extermination nor the peace of generalized terror, but revolutionary
|
||
movement (the connection of flows, the composition of nondenumerable
|
||
aggregates, the becoming-minoritarian of everybody/everything). This is
|
||
not a dispersion or a fragmentation: we are instead back at the opposition
|
||
between, on the one hand, a plane of consistency and, on the other, the plane
|
||
of organization and development of capital and the bureaucratic socialist
|
||
plane. There is in each case a constructivism, a "diagrammatism," operat-
|
||
ing by the determination of the conditions of the problem and by transver-
|
||
sal links between problems: it opposes both the automation of the capitalist
|
||
axioms and bureaucratic programming. From this standpoint, when we
|
||
talk about "undecidable propositions," we are not referring to the uncer-
|
||
tainty of the results, which is necessarily a part of every system. We are
|
||
referring, on the contrary, to the coexistence and inseparability of that
|
||
which the system conjugates, and that which never ceases to escape it fol-
|
||
lowing lines of flight that are themselves connectable. The undecidable is
|
||
the germ and locus par excellence of revolutionary decisions. Some people
|
||
invoke the high technology of the world system of enslavement; but even,
|
||
and especially, this machinic enslavement abounds in undecidable
|
||
propositions and movements that, far from belonging to a domain of
|
||
knowledge reserved for sworn specialists, provides so many weapons for
|
||
the becoming of everybody/everything, becoming-radio, becoming-
|
||
electronic, becoming-molecular.. ,68 Every struggle is a function of all of
|
||
these undecidable propositions and constructs revolutionary connections
|
||
in opposition to the conjugations of the axiomatic.
|
||
14. 1440: The Smooth and the Striated
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Quilt
|
||
|
||
Smooth space and striated space—nomad space and sedentary space—the
|
||
space in which the war machine develops and the space instituted by the
|
||
State apparatus—are not of the same nature. No sooner do we note a sim-
|
||
ple opposition between the two kinds of space than we must indicate a
|
||
much more complex difference by virtue of which the successive terms of
|
||
the oppositions fail to coincide entirely. And no sooner have we done that
|
||
than we must remind ourselves that the two spaces in fact exist only in mix-
|
||
ture: smooth space is constantly being translated, transversed into a stri-
|
||
ated space; striated space is constantly being reversed, returned to a
|
||
smooth space. In the first case, one organizes even the desert; in the second,
|
||
474
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 475
|
||
|
||
the desert gains and grows; and the two can happen simultaneously. But the
|
||
de facto mixes do not preclude a de jure, or abstract, distinction between
|
||
the two spaces. That there is such a distinction is what accounts for the fact
|
||
that the two spaces do not communicate with each other in the same way: it
|
||
is the de jure distinction that determines the forms assumed by a given de
|
||
facto mix and the direction or meaning of the mix (is a smooth space cap-
|
||
tured, enveloped by a striated space, or does a striated space dissolve into a
|
||
smooth space, allow a smooth space to develop?). This raises a number of
|
||
simultaneous questions: the simple oppositions between the two spaces;
|
||
the complex differences; the de facto mixes, and the passages from one to
|
||
another; the principles of the mixture, which are not at all symmetrical,
|
||
sometimes causing a passage from the smooth to the striated, sometimes
|
||
from the striated to the smooth, according to entirely different move-
|
||
ments. We must therefore envision a certain number of models, which
|
||
would be like various aspects of the two spaces and the relations between
|
||
them.
|
||
|
||
The Technological Model. A fabric presents in principle a certain number
|
||
of characteristics that permit us to define it as a striated space. First, it is
|
||
constituted by two kinds of parallel elements; in the simplest case, there are
|
||
vertical and horizontal elements, and the two intertwine, intersect perpen-
|
||
dicularly. Second, the two kinds of elements have different functions; one
|
||
is fixed, the other mobile, passing above and beneath the fixed. Leroi-
|
||
Gourhan has analyzed this particular figure of "supple solids" in basketry
|
||
and weaving: stake and thread, warp and woof.' Third, a striated space of
|
||
this kind is necessarily delimited, closed on at least one side: the fabric can
|
||
be infinite in length but not in width, which is determined by the frame of
|
||
the warp; the necessity of a back and forth motion implies a closed space
|
||
(circular or cylindrical figures are themselves closed). Finally, a space of
|
||
this kind seems necessarily to have a top and a bottom; even when the warp
|
||
yarn and woof yarn are exactly the same in nature, number, and density,
|
||
weaving reconstitutes a bottom by placing the knots on one side. Was it not
|
||
these characteristics that enabled Plato to use the model of weaving as the
|
||
paradigm for "royal science," in other words, the art of governing people or
|
||
operating the State apparatus?
|
||
Felt is a supple solid product that proceeds altogether differently, as an
|
||
anti-fabric. It implies no separation of threads, no intertwining, only an
|
||
entanglement of fibers obtained by fulling (for example, by rolling the
|
||
block of fibers back and forth). What becomes entangled are the
|
||
microscales of the fibers. An aggregate of intrication of this kind is in no
|
||
way homogeneous: it is nevertheless smooth, and contrasts point by point
|
||
with the space of fabric (it is in principle infinite, open, and unlimited in
|
||
476 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
every direction; it has neither top nor bottom nor center; it does not assign
|
||
fixed and mobile elements but rather distributes a continuous variation).
|
||
Even the technologists who express grave doubts about the nomads' pow-
|
||
ers of innovation at least give them credit for felt: a splendid insulator, an
|
||
ingenious invention, the raw material for tents, clothes, and armor among
|
||
the Turco-Mongols. Of course, the nomads of Africa and the Maghreb
|
||
instead treat wool as a fabric. Although it might entail displacing the oppo-
|
||
sition, do we not detect two very different conceptions or even practices of
|
||
weaving, the distinction between which would be something like the dis-
|
||
tinction between fabric as a whole and felt? For among sedentaries,
|
||
clothes-fabric and tapestry-fabric tend to annex the body and exterior
|
||
space, respectively, to the immobile house: fabric integrates the body and
|
||
the outside into a closed space. On the other hand, the weaving of the
|
||
nomad indexes clothing and the house itself to the space of the outside, to
|
||
the open smooth space in which the body moves.
|
||
There are many interfacings, mixes between felt and fabric. Can we not
|
||
displace the opposition yet again? In knitting, for example, the needles pro-
|
||
duce a striated space; one of them plays the role of the warp, the other of the
|
||
woof, but by turns. Crochet, on the other hand, draws an open space in all
|
||
directions, a space that is prolongable in all directions—but still has a cen-
|
||
ter. A more significant distinction would be between embroidery, with its
|
||
central theme or motif, and patchwork, with its piece-by-piece construc-
|
||
tion, its infinite, successive additions of fabric. Of course, embroidery's
|
||
variables and constants, fixed and mobile elements, may be of extraordi-
|
||
nary complexity. Patchwork, for its part, may display equivalents to
|
||
themes, symmetries, and resonance that approximate it to embroidery.
|
||
But the fact remains that its space is not at all constituted in the same way:
|
||
there is no center; its basic motif ("block") is composed of a single element;
|
||
the recurrence of this element frees uniquely rhythmic values distinct from
|
||
the harmonies of embroidery (in particular, in "crazy" patchwork, which
|
||
fits together pieces of varying size, shape, and color, and plays on the tex-
|
||
ture of the fabrics). "She had been working on it for fifteen years, carrying
|
||
about with her a shapeless bag of dingy, threadbare brocade containing
|
||
odds and ends of colored fabric in all possible shapes. She could never
|
||
bring herself to trim them to any pattern; so she shifted and fitted and
|
||
mused and fitted and shifted them like pieces of a patient puzzle-picture,
|
||
trying to fit them to a pattern or create a pattern out of them without using
|
||
her scissors, smoothing her colored scraps with flaccid, putty-colored fin-
|
||
gers."2 An amorphous collection of juxtaposed pieces that can be joined
|
||
together in an infinite number of ways: we see that patchwork is literally a
|
||
Riemannian space, or vice versa. That is why very special work groups
|
||
were formed for patchwork fabrication (the importance of the quilting bee
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 477
|
||
|
||
in America, and its role from the standpoint of a women's collectivity). The
|
||
smooth space of patchwork is adequate to demonstrate that "smooth" does
|
||
not mean homogeneous, quite the contrary: it is an amorphous, nonformal
|
||
space prefiguring op art.
|
||
The story of the quilt is particularly interesting in this connection. A
|
||
quilt comprises two layers of fabric stitched together, often with a filler in
|
||
between. Thus it is possible for there to be no top or bottom. If we follow
|
||
the history of the quilt over a short migration sequence (the settlers who
|
||
left Europe for the New World), we see that there is a shift from a formula
|
||
dominated by embroidery (so-called "plain" quilts) to a patchwork for-
|
||
mula ("applique quilts," and above all "pieced quilts"). The first settlers
|
||
of the seventeenth century brought with them plain quilts, embroidered
|
||
and striated spaces of extreme beauty. But toward the end of the century
|
||
patchwork technique was developed more and more, at first due to the
|
||
scarcity of textiles (leftover fabric, pieces salvaged from used clothes,
|
||
remnants taken from the "scrap bag"), and later due to the popularity of
|
||
Indian chintz. It is as though a smooth space emanated, sprang from a
|
||
striated space, but not without a correlation between the two, a recapitu-
|
||
lation of one in the other, a furtherance of one through the other. Yet the
|
||
complex difference persists. Patchwork, in conformity with migration,
|
||
whose degree of affinity with nomadism it shares, is not only named after
|
||
trajectories, but "represents" trajectories, becomes inseparable from
|
||
speed or movement in an open space.3
|
||
|
||
The Musical Model. Pierre Boulez was the first to develop a set of simple
|
||
oppositions and complex differences, as well as reciprocal nonsymmetrical
|
||
correlations, between smooth and striated space. He created these con-
|
||
cepts and words in the field of music, defining them on several levels pre-
|
||
cisely in order to account for the abstract distinction at the same time as the
|
||
concrete mixes. In the simplest terms, Boulez says that in a smooth space-
|
||
time one occupies without counting, whereas in a striated space-time one
|
||
counts in order to occupy. He makes palpable or perceptible the difference
|
||
between nonmetric and metric multiplicities, directional and dimensional
|
||
spaces. He renders them sonorous or musical. Undoubtedly, his personal
|
||
work is composed of these relations, created or recreated musically.4
|
||
At a second level, it can be said that space is susceptible to two kinds of
|
||
breaks: one is defined by a standard, whereas the other is irregular and
|
||
undetermined, and can be made wherever one wishes to place it. At yet
|
||
another level, it can be said that frequencies can be distributed either in the
|
||
intervals between breaks, or statistically without breaks. In the first case,
|
||
the principle behind the distribution of breaks and intervals is called a
|
||
"module"; it may be constant and fixed (a straight striated space), or
|
||
478 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
regularly or irregularly variable (curved striated spaces, termed focalized if
|
||
the variation of the module is regular, nonfocalized if it is irregular). When
|
||
there is no module, the distribution of frequencies is without break: it is
|
||
"statistical," however small the segment of space may be; it still has two
|
||
aspects, however, depending on whether the distribution is equal
|
||
(nondirected smooth space), or more or less rare or dense (directed smooth
|
||
space). Can we say that in the kind of smooth space that is without break or
|
||
module there is no interval? Or, on the contrary, has everything become
|
||
interval, intermezzo? The smooth is a nomos, whereas the striated always
|
||
has a logos, the octave, for example. Boulez is concerned with the commu-
|
||
nication between the two kinds of space, their alternations and superposi-
|
||
tions: how "a strongly directed smooth space tends to meld with a striated
|
||
space," how "a striated space in which the statistical distribution of the
|
||
pitches used is in fact equal tends to meld with a smooth space";5 how the
|
||
octave can be replaced by "non-octave-forming scales" that reproduce
|
||
themselves through a principle of spiraling; how "texture" can be crafted in
|
||
such a way as to lose fixed and homogeneous values, becoming a support
|
||
for slips in tempo, displacements of intervals, and son art transformations
|
||
comparable to the transformations of op art.
|
||
Returning to the simple opposition, the striated is that which inter-
|
||
twines fixed and variable elements, produces an order and succession of
|
||
distinct forms, and organizes horizontal melodic lines and vertical har-
|
||
monic planes. The smooth is the continuous variation, continuous devel-
|
||
opment of form; it is the fusion of harmony and melody in favor of the
|
||
production of properly rythmic values, the pure act of the drawing of a
|
||
diagonal across the vertical and the horizontal.
|
||
|
||
The Maritime Model. Of course, there are points, lines, and surfaces in
|
||
striated space as well as in smooth space (there are also volumes, but we will
|
||
leave this question aside for the time being). In striated space, lines or tra-
|
||
jectories tend to be subordinated to points: one goes from one point to
|
||
another. In the smooth, it is the opposite: the points are subordinated to the
|
||
trajectory. This was already the case among the nomads for the clothes-
|
||
tent-space vector of the outside. The dwelling is subordinated to the jour-
|
||
ney; inside space conforms to outside space: tent, igloo, boat. There are
|
||
stops and trajectories in both the smooth and the striated. But in smooth
|
||
space, the stop follows from the trajectory; once again, the interval takes
|
||
all, the interval is substance (forming the basis for rhythmic values).6
|
||
In smooth space, the line is therefore a vector, a direction and not a
|
||
dimension or metric determination. It is a space constructed by local oper-
|
||
ations involving changes in direction. These changes in direction may be
|
||
due to the nature of the journey itself, as with the nomads of the archipela-
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 479
|
||
|
||
goes (a case of "directed" smooth space); but it is more likely to be due to
|
||
the variability of the goal or point to be attained, as with the nomads of the
|
||
desert who head toward local, temporary vegetation (a "nondirected"
|
||
smooth space). Directed or not, and especially in the latter case, smooth
|
||
space is directional rather than dimensional or metric. Smooth space is
|
||
filled by events or haecceities, far more than by formed and perceived
|
||
things. It is a space of affects, more than one of properties. It is haptic rather
|
||
than optical perception. Whereas in the striated forms organize a matter,
|
||
in the smooth materials signal forces and serve as symptoms for them. It is
|
||
an intensive rather than extensive space, one of distances, not of measures
|
||
and properties. Intense Spatium instead of Extensio. A Body without
|
||
Organs instead of an organism and organization. Perception in it is based
|
||
on symptoms and evaluations rather than measures and properties. That is
|
||
why smooth space is occupied by intensities, wind and noise, forces, and
|
||
sonorous and tactile qualities, as in the desert, steppe, or ice.7 The creaking
|
||
of ice and the song of the sands. Striated space, on the contrary, is can-
|
||
opied by the sky as measure and by the measurable visual qualities deriv-
|
||
ing from it.
|
||
This is where the very special problem of the sea enters in. For the sea is a
|
||
smooth space par excellence, and yet was the first to encounter the
|
||
demands of increasingly strict striation. The problem did not arise in prox-
|
||
imity to land. On the contrary, the striation of the sea was a result of naviga-
|
||
tion on the open water. Maritime space was striated as a function of two
|
||
astronomical and geographical gains: bearings, obtained by a set of calcula-
|
||
tions based on exact observation of the stars and the sun; and the map,
|
||
which intertwines meridians and parallels, longitudes and latitudes, plot-
|
||
ting regions known and unknown onto a grid (like a Mendeleyev table).
|
||
Must we accept the Portuguese argument and assign 1440 as the turning
|
||
point that marked the first decisive striation, and set the stage for the great
|
||
discoveries? Rather, we will follow Pierre Chaunu when he speaks of an
|
||
extended confrontation at sea between the smooth and the striated during
|
||
the course of which the striated progressively took hold.8 For before longi-
|
||
tude lines had been plotted, a very late development, there existed a com-
|
||
plex and empirical nomadic system of navigation based on the wind and
|
||
noise, the colors and sounds of the seas; then came a directional,
|
||
preastronomical or already astronomical, system of navigation employing
|
||
only latitude, in which there was no possibility of "taking one's bearings,"
|
||
and which had only portolanos lacking "translatable generalization"
|
||
instead of true maps; finally, improvements upon this primitive astronom-
|
||
ical navigation were made under the very special conditions of the lati-
|
||
tudes of the Indian Ocean, then of the elliptical circuits of the Atlantic
|
||
(straight and curved spaces).9 It is as if the sea were not only the archetype
|
||
480 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
of all smooth spaces but the first to undergo a gradual striation gridding it
|
||
in one place, then another, on this side and that. The commercial cities par-
|
||
ticipated in this striation, and were often innovators; but only the States
|
||
were capable of carrying it to completion, of raising it to the global level of a
|
||
"politics of science."10 A dimensionality that subordinated directionality,
|
||
or superimposed itself upon it, became increasingly entrenched.
|
||
This is undoubtedly why the sea, the archetype of smooth space, was
|
||
also the archetype of all striations of smooth space: the striation of the
|
||
desert, the air, the stratosphere (prompting Virilio to speak of a "vertical
|
||
coastline," as a change in direction). It was at sea that smooth space was
|
||
first subjugated and a model found for the laying-out and imposition of
|
||
striated space, a model later put to use elsewhere. This does not contradict
|
||
Virilio's other hypothesis: in the aftermath of striation, the sea reimparts a
|
||
kind of smooth space, occupied first by the "fleet in being," then by the per-
|
||
petual motion of the strategic submarine, which outflanks all gridding and
|
||
invents a neonomadism in the service of a war machine still more disturb-
|
||
ing than the States, which reconstitute it at the limit of their striations. The
|
||
sea, then the air and the stratosphere, become smooth spaces again, but, in
|
||
the strangest of reversals, it is for the purpose of controlling striated space
|
||
more completely.11 The smooth always possesses a greater power of
|
||
deterritorialization than the striated. When examining the new profes-
|
||
sions, or new classes even, how can one fail to mention the military techni-
|
||
cians who stare into screens night and day and live for long stretches in
|
||
strategic submarines (in the future it will be on satellites), and the apoca-
|
||
lyptic eyes and ears they have fashioned for themselves, which can barely
|
||
distinguish any more between a natural phenomenon, a swarm of locusts,
|
||
and an "enemy" attack originating at any given point? All of this serves as a
|
||
reminder that the smooth itself can be drawn and occupied by diabolical
|
||
powers of organization; value judgments aside, this demonstrates above all
|
||
that there exist two nonsymmetrical movements, one of which striates the
|
||
smooth, and one of which reimparts smooth space on the basis of the stri-
|
||
ated. (Do not new smooth spaces, or holey spaces, arise as parries even in
|
||
relation to the smooth space of a worldwide organization? Virilio invokes
|
||
the beginnings of subterranean habitation in the "mineral layer," which
|
||
can take on very diverse values.)
|
||
Let us return to the simple opposition between the smooth and the stri-
|
||
ated since we are not yet at the point where we can consider the dis-
|
||
symmetrical and concrete mixes. The smooth and the striated are
|
||
distinguished first of all by an inverse relation between the point and the
|
||
line (in the case of the striated, the line is between two points, while in the
|
||
smooth, the point is between two lines); and second, by the nature of the
|
||
line (smooth-directional, open intervals; dimensional-striated, closed
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 481
|
||
|
||
intervals). Finally, there is a third difference, concerning the surface or
|
||
space. In striated space, one closes off a surface and "allocates" it according
|
||
to determinate intervals, assigned breaks; in the smooth, one "distributes"
|
||
oneself in an open space, according to frequencies and in the course of
|
||
one's crossings (logos and nomos).n As simple as this opposition is, it is not
|
||
easy to place it. We cannot content ourselves with establishing an immedi-
|
||
ate opposition between the smooth ground of the nomadic animal raiser
|
||
and the striated land of the sedentary cultivator. It is evident that the peas-
|
||
ant, even the sedentary peasant, participates fully in the space of the wind,
|
||
the space of tactile and sonorous qualities. When the ancient Greeks speak
|
||
of the open space of the nomos—nondelimited, unpartitioned; the pre-
|
||
urban countryside; mountainside, plateau, steppe—they oppose it not to
|
||
cultivation, which may actually be part of it, but to the polls, the city, the
|
||
town. When Ibn Khaldun speaks of badiya, bedouinism, the term covers
|
||
cultivators as well as nomadic animal raisers: he contrasts it to hadara, or
|
||
"city life." This clarification is certainly important, but it does not change
|
||
much. For from the most ancient of times, from Neolithic and even Paleo-
|
||
lithic times, it is the town that invents agriculture: it is through the actions of
|
||
the town that the farmers and their striated space are superposed upon the
|
||
cultivators operating in a still smooth space (the transhumant cultivator,
|
||
half-sedentary or already completely sedentary). So on this level we
|
||
reencounter the simple opposition we began by challenging, between farm-
|
||
ers and nomads, striated land and smooth ground: but only after a detour
|
||
through the town as a force of striation. Now not only the sea, desert,
|
||
steppe, and air are the sites of a contest between the smooth and the stri-
|
||
ated, but the earth itself, depending on whether there is cultivation in
|
||
nomos-space or agriculture in city-space. Must we not say the same of the
|
||
city itself? In contrast to the sea, the city is the striated space par excellence;
|
||
the sea is a smooth space fundamentally open to striation, and the city is
|
||
the force of striation that reimparts smooth space, puts it back into opera-
|
||
tion everywhere, on earth and in the other elements, outside but also inside
|
||
itself. The smooth spaces arising from the city are not only those of world-
|
||
wide organization, but also of a counterattack combining the smooth and
|
||
the holey and turning back against the town: sprawling, temporary, shifting
|
||
shantytowns of nomads and cave dwellers, scrap metal and fabric, patch-
|
||
work, to which the striations of money, work, or housing are no longer even
|
||
relevant. An explosive misery secreted by the city, and corresponding to
|
||
Thorn's mathematical formula: "retroactive smoothing."13 Condensed
|
||
force, the potential for counterattack?
|
||
In each instance, then, the simple opposition "smooth-striated" gives
|
||
rise to far more difficult complications, alternations, and superpositions.
|
||
But these complications basically confirm the distinction, precisely
|
||
482 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
because they bring dissymmetrical movements into play. For now, it suf-
|
||
fices to say that there are two kinds of voyage, distinguished by the respec-
|
||
tive role of the point, line, and space. Goethe travel and Kleist travel?
|
||
French travel and English (or American) travel? Tree travel and rhizome
|
||
travel? But nothing completely coincides, and everything intermingles, or
|
||
crosses over. This is because the differences are not objective: it is possible
|
||
to live striated on the deserts, steppes, or seas; it is possible to live smooth
|
||
even in the cities, to be an urban nomad (for example, a stroll taken by
|
||
Henry Miller in Clichy or Brooklyn is a nomadic transit in smooth space;
|
||
he makes the city disgorge a patchwork, differentials of speed, delays and
|
||
accelerations, changes in orientation, continuous variations . . . The beat-
|
||
niks owe much to Miller, but they changed direction again, they put the
|
||
space outside the cities to new use). Fitzgerald said it long ago: it is not a
|
||
question of taking off for the South Seas, that is not what determines a voy-
|
||
age. There are not only strange voyages in the city but voyages in place: we
|
||
are not thinking of drug users, whose experience is too ambiguous, but of
|
||
true nomads. We can say of the nomads, following Toynbee's suggestion:
|
||
they do not move. They are nomads by dint of not moving, not migrating, of
|
||
holding a smooth space that they refuse to leave, that they leave only in
|
||
order to conquer and die. Voyage in place: that is the name of all intensities,
|
||
even if they also develop in extension. To think is to voyage; earlier we tried
|
||
to establish a theo-noological model of smooth and striated spaces. In
|
||
short, what distinguishes the two kinds of voyages is neither a measurable
|
||
quantity of movement, nor something that would be only in the mind, but
|
||
the mode of spatialization, the manner of being in space, of being for space.
|
||
Voyage smoothly or in striation, and think the same w a y . . . But there are
|
||
always passages from one to the other, transformations of one within the
|
||
other, reversals. In his film, Kings of the Road, Wenders intersects and
|
||
superposes the paths of two characters; one of them takes a still educa-
|
||
tional, memorial, cultural, Goethean journey that is thoroughly striated,
|
||
whereas the other has already conquered smooth space, and only experi-
|
||
ments, induces amnesia in the German "desert." But oddly enough, it is the
|
||
former who opens space for himself and performs a kind of retroactive
|
||
smoothing, whereas striae reform around the latter, closing his space again.
|
||
Voyaging smoothly is a becoming, and a difficult, uncertain becoming at
|
||
that. It is not a question of returning to preastronomical navigation, nor to
|
||
the ancient nomads. The confrontation between the smooth and the stri-
|
||
ated, the passages, alternations and superpositions, are under way today,
|
||
running in the most varied directions.
|
||
|
||
The Mathematical Model. It was a decisive event when the mathemati-
|
||
cian Riemann uprooted the multiple from its predicate state and made it a
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 483
|
||
|
||
noun, "multiplicity." It marked the end of dialectics and the beginning of a
|
||
typology and topology of multiplicities. Each multiplicity was defined by n
|
||
determinations; sometimes the determinations were independent of the
|
||
situation, and sometimes they depended upon it. For example, the magni-
|
||
tude of a vertical line between two points can be compared to the magni-
|
||
tude of a horizontal line between two other points: it is clear that the
|
||
multiplicity in this case is metric, that it allows itself to be striated, and that
|
||
its determinations are magnitudes. On the other hand, two sounds of equal
|
||
pitch and different intensity cannot be compared to two sounds of equal
|
||
intensity and different pitch; in this case, two determinations can be com-
|
||
pared only "if one is a part of the other and if we restrict ourselves to the
|
||
judgment that the latter is smaller than the former, without being able to
|
||
say by how much."14 Multiplicities of this second kind are not metric and
|
||
allow themselves to be striated and measured only by indirect means,
|
||
which they always resist. They are anexact yet rigorous. Meinong and
|
||
Russell opposed the notion of distance to that of magnitude.1* Distances
|
||
are not, strictly speaking, indivisible: they can be divided precisely in cases
|
||
where the situation of one determination makes it part of another. But
|
||
unlike magnitudes, they cannot divide without changing in nature each
|
||
time. An intensity, for example, is not composed of addable and displace-
|
||
able magnitudes: a temperature is not the sum of two smaller tempera-
|
||
tures, a speed is not the sum of two smaller speeds. Since each intensity is
|
||
itself a difference, it divides according to an order in which each term of the
|
||
division differs in nature from the others. Distance is therefore a set of
|
||
ordered differences, in other words, differences that are enveloped in one
|
||
another in such a way that it is possible to judge which is larger or smaller,
|
||
but not their exact magnitudes. For example, one can divide movement
|
||
into the gallop, trot, and walk, but in such a way that what is divided
|
||
changes in nature at each moment of the division, without any one of these
|
||
moments entering into the composition of any other. Therefore these mul-
|
||
tiplicities of "distance" are inseparable from a process of continuous varia-
|
||
tion, whereas multiplicities of "magnitude" distribute constants and
|
||
variables.
|
||
That is why we consider Bergson to be of major importance (much more
|
||
so than Husserl, or even Meinong or Russell) in the development of the the-
|
||
ory of multiplicities. Beginning in Time and Free Will, he presents dura-
|
||
tion as a type of multiplicity opposed to metric multiplicity or the
|
||
multiplicity of magnitude. Duration is in no way indivisible, but is that
|
||
which cannot be divided without changing in nature at each division
|
||
(Achilles' running is not divided into steps, his steps do not compose it in
|
||
the manner of magnitudes).16 On the other hand, in a multiplicity such as
|
||
homogeneous extension, the division can be carried as far as one likes
|
||
484 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
without changing anything in the constant object; or the magnitudes can
|
||
vary with no other result than an increase or a decrease in the amount of
|
||
space they striate. Bergson thus brought to light "two very different kinds
|
||
of multiplicity," one qualitative and fusional, continuous, the other
|
||
numerical and homogeneous, discrete. It will be noted that matter goes
|
||
back and forth between the two; sometimes it is already enveloped in quali-
|
||
tative multiplicity, sometimes already developed in a metric "schema"
|
||
that draws it outside of itself. The confrontation between Bergson and
|
||
Einstein on the topic of Relativity is incomprehensible if one fails to place
|
||
it in the context of the basic theory of Riemannian multiplicities, as modi-
|
||
fied by Bergson.
|
||
We have on numerous occasions encountered all kinds of differences
|
||
between two types of multiplicities: metric and nonmetric; extensive and
|
||
qualitative; centered and acentered; arborescent and rhizomatic; numeri-
|
||
cal and flat; dimensional and directional; of masses and of packs; of magni-
|
||
tude and of distance; of breaks and of frequency; striated and smooth. Not
|
||
only is that which peoples a smooth space a multiplicity that changes in
|
||
nature when it divides—such as tribes in the desert: constantly modified
|
||
distances, packs that are always undergoing metamorphosis—but smooth
|
||
space itself, desert, steppe, sea, or ice, is a multiplicity of this type, non-
|
||
metric, acentered, directional, etc. Now it might be thought that the Num-
|
||
ber would belong exclusively to the other multiplicities, that it would
|
||
accord them the scientific status nonmetric multiplicities lack. But this is
|
||
only partially true. It is true that the number is the correlate of the metric:
|
||
magnitudes can striate space only by reference to numbers, and conversely,
|
||
numbers are used to express increasingly complex relations between mag-
|
||
nitudes, thus giving rise to ideal spaces reinforcing the striation and mak-
|
||
ing it coextensive with all of matter. There is therefore a correlation within
|
||
metric multiplicities between geometry and arithmetic, geometry and
|
||
algebra, which is constitutive of major science (the most profound authors
|
||
in this respect are those who have seen that the number, even in its simplest
|
||
forms, is exclusively cardinal in character, and the unit exclusively divisi-
|
||
ble).17 It could be said on the other hand that nonmetric multiplicities or
|
||
the multiplicities of smooth space pertain only to a minor geometry that is
|
||
purely operative and qualitative, in which calculation is necessarily very
|
||
limited, and the local operations of which are not even capable of general
|
||
translatability or a homogeneous system of location. Yet this "inferiority"
|
||
is only apparent; for the independence of this nearly illiterate, ametric
|
||
geometry is what makes possible the independence of the number, the sub-
|
||
sequent function of which is to measure magnitudes in striated space (or to
|
||
striate). The number distributes itself in smooth space; it does not divide
|
||
without changing nature each time, without changing units, each of which
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 485
|
||
|
||
represents a distance and not a magnitude. The ordinal, directional, no-
|
||
madic, articulated number, the numbering number, pertains to smooth
|
||
space, just as the numbered number pertains to striated space. So we may
|
||
say of every multiplicity that it is already a number, and still a unit. But the
|
||
number and the unit, and even the way in which the unit divides, are differ-
|
||
ent in each case. Minor science is continually enriching major science,
|
||
communicating its intuitions to it, its way of proceeding, its itinerancy, its
|
||
sense of and taste for matter, singularity, variation, intuitionist geometry
|
||
and the numbering number.
|
||
But so far we have only considered the first aspect of smooth and
|
||
nonmetric multiplicities, as opposed to metric multiplicities: how the situ-
|
||
ation of one determination can make it part of another without our being
|
||
able either to assign that situation an exact magnitude or common unit, or
|
||
to discount it. This is the enveloping or enveloped character of smooth
|
||
space. But there is a second, more important, aspect: when the situation of
|
||
the two determinations precludes their comparison. As we know, this is the
|
||
case for Riemannian spaces, or rather, Riemannian patches of space:
|
||
"Riemann spaces are devoid of any kind of homogeneity. Each is charac-
|
||
terized by the form of the expression that defines the square of the distance
|
||
between two infinitely proximate points It follows that two neighbor-
|
||
ing observers in a Riemann space can locate the points in their immediate
|
||
vicinity but cannot locate their spaces in relation to each other without a
|
||
new convention. Each vicinity is therefore like a shred of Euclidean space,
|
||
but the linkage between one vicinity and the next is not defined and can be
|
||
effected in an infinite number of ways. Riemann space at its most general
|
||
thus presents itself as an amorphous collection of pieces that are juxtaposed
|
||
but not attached to each other." It is possible to define this multiplicity
|
||
without any reference to a metrical system, in terms of the conditions of
|
||
frequency, or rather accumulation, of a set of vicinities; these conditions
|
||
are entirely different from those determining metric spaces and their
|
||
breaks (even though a relation between the two kinds of space necessarily
|
||
results).18 In short, if we follow Lautman's fine description, Riemannian
|
||
space is pure patchwork. It has connections, or tactile relations. It has
|
||
rhythmic values not found elsewhere, even though they can be translated
|
||
into a metric space. Heterogeneous, in continuous variation, it is a smooth
|
||
space, insofar as smooth space is amorphous and not homogeneous. We
|
||
can thus define two positive characteristics of smooth space in general:
|
||
when there are determinations that are part of one another and pertain to
|
||
enveloped distances or ordered differences, independent of magnitude;
|
||
when, independent of metrics, determinations arise that cannot be part of
|
||
one another but are connected by processes of frequency or accumulation.
|
||
These are the two aspects of the nomos of smooth space.
|
||
486 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
We are always, however, brought back to a dissymmetrical necessity to
|
||
cross from the smooth to the striated, and from the striated to the smooth.
|
||
If it is true that itinerant geometry and the nomadic number of smooth
|
||
spaces are a constant inspiration to royal science and striated space, con-
|
||
versely, the metrics of striated spaces (metron) is indispensable for the
|
||
translation of the strange data of a smooth multiplicity. Translating is not a
|
||
simple act: it is not enough to substitute the space traversed for the move-
|
||
ment; a series of rich and complex operations is necessary (Bergson was the
|
||
first to make this point). Neither is translating a secondary act. It is an oper-
|
||
ation that undoubtedly consists in subjugating, overcoding, metricizing
|
||
smooth space, in neutralizing it, but also in giving it a milieu of propaga-
|
||
tion, extension, refraction, renewal, and impulse without which it would
|
||
perhaps die of its own accord: like a mask without which it could neither
|
||
breathe nor find a general form of expression. Major science has a perpet-
|
||
ual need for the inspiration of the minor; but the minor would be nothing if
|
||
it did not confront and conform to the highest scientific requirements. Let
|
||
us take just two examples of the richness and necessity of translations,
|
||
which include as many opportunities for openings as risks of closure or
|
||
stoppage: first, the complexity of the means by which one translates inten-
|
||
sities into extensive quantities, or more generally, multiplicities of dis-
|
||
tance into systems of magnitudes that measure and striate them (the role of
|
||
logarithms in this connection); second, and more important, the delicacy
|
||
and complexity of the means by which Riemannian patches of smooth
|
||
space receive a Euclidean conjunction (the role of the parallelism of vectors
|
||
in striating the infinitesimal).19 The mode of connection proper to patches
|
||
of Riemannian space ("accumulation") is not to be confused with the
|
||
Euclidean conjunction of Riemann space ("parallelism"). Yet the two are
|
||
linked and give each other impetus. Nothing is ever done with: smooth
|
||
space allows itself to be striated, and striated space reimparts a smooth
|
||
space, with potentially very different values, scope, and signs. Perhaps we
|
||
must say that all progress is made by and in striated space, but all becoming
|
||
occurs in smooth space.
|
||
Is it possible to give a very general mathematical definition of smooth
|
||
spaces? Benoit Mandelbrot's "fractals" seem to be on that path. Fractals
|
||
are aggregates whose number of dimensions is fractional rather than
|
||
whole, or else whole but with continuous variation in direction. An exam-
|
||
ple would be a line segment whose central third is replaced by the angle of
|
||
an equilateral triangle; the operation is repeated for the four resulting seg-
|
||
ments, and so on ad infinitum, following a relation of similarity—such a
|
||
segment would constitute an infinite line or curve with a dimension
|
||
greater than one, but less than a surface (= 2). Similar results can be
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 487
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Sierpensky's sponge: more than a surface, less
|
||
Von Koch's curve: more than a line, less than a volume. The law according to which this
|
||
than a surface. The middle third of cube was hollowed can be understood intui-
|
||
segment AE (1) is removed and tively at a glance. Each square hole is sur-
|
||
replaced with the traingle BCD (2). In rounded by eight holes a third its size. These
|
||
(3), this operation is repeated sepa- holes are in turn surrounded by eight holes, also
|
||
rately for each of the segments/IB, AC, a third their size. And so on, endlessly. The illus-
|
||
CD, andDE. This yields an angled line trator could not represent the infinity of holes
|
||
of equal segments (4), and so on, ad of decreasing size beyond the fourth degree, but
|
||
infinitum. The end result is a "curve" it is plain to see that this cube is in the end infi-
|
||
composed of an infinite number of nitely hollow. Its total volume approaches zero,
|
||
angled points that preclude any tan- while the total lateral surface of the hollowings
|
||
gent being drawn to any of their infinitely grows. This space has a dimension of
|
||
points. The length of the curve is infi- 2.7268. It therefore lies between a surface (with
|
||
nite and its dimension is higher than a dimension of 2) and a volume (with a dimen-
|
||
one: it represents a space of 1.261859 sion of 3). "Sierpinsky's rug" is one face of this
|
||
dimensions (log 4/log 3 exactly). cube; the hollowings are then squares and the
|
||
dimension of the "surface" is 1.2618. From
|
||
Studies in Geometry by Leonard M. Blu-
|
||
menthal and Karl Menger. Copyright © 1970
|
||
W. H. Freeman and Company. Reprinted with
|
||
permission.
|
||
Concerning Benoit Mandelbrot's "Fractals"
|
||
|
||
obtained by making holes, by cutting, "windows" into a circle, instead of
|
||
adding "points" to a triangle; likewise, a cube into which holes are drilled
|
||
according to the principle of similarity becomes less than a volume but
|
||
more than a surface (this is the mathematical presentation of the affinity
|
||
between a free space and a holey space). In still other forms, Brownian
|
||
motion, turbulence, and the sky are "fractals" of this kind.20 Perhaps this
|
||
provides us with another way of defining fuzzy aggregates. But the main
|
||
thing is that it provides a general determination for smooth space that
|
||
488 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
takes into account its differences from and relations to striated space: (1)
|
||
we shall call striated or metric any aggregate with a whole number of
|
||
dimensions, and for which it is possible to assign constant directions; (2)
|
||
nonmetric smooth space is constituted by the construction of a line with a
|
||
fractional number of dimensions greater than one, or of a surface with a
|
||
fractional number of dimensions greater than two; (3) a fractional number
|
||
of dimensions is the index of a properly directional space (with continuous
|
||
variation in direction, and without tangent); (4) what defines smooth
|
||
space, then, is that it does not have a dimension higher than that which
|
||
moves through it or is inscribed in it; in this sense it is a flat multiplicity, for
|
||
example, a line that fills a plane without ceasing to be a line; (5) space and
|
||
that which occupies space tend to become identified, to have the same
|
||
power, in the anexact yet rigorous form of the numbering or nonwhole
|
||
number (occupy without counting); (6) a smooth, amorphous space of this
|
||
kind is constituted by an accumulation of proximities, and each accumula-
|
||
tion defines a zone of indiscernibility proper to "becoming" (more than a
|
||
line and less than a surface; less than a volume and more than a surface).
|
||
|
||
The Physical Model. The various models confirm a certain idea of stria-
|
||
tion: two series of parallels that intersect perpendicularly, some of which,
|
||
the verticals, are more in the role of fixed elements or constants, whereas
|
||
the others, the horizontals, are more in the role of variables. This is roughly
|
||
the case for the warp and the woof, harmony and melody, longitude and lat-
|
||
itude. The more regular the intersection, the tighter the striation, the more
|
||
homogeneous the space tends to become; it is for this reason that from the
|
||
beginning homogeneity did not seem to us to be a characteristic of smooth
|
||
space, but on the contrary, the extreme result of striation, or the limit-form
|
||
of a space striated everywhere and in all directions. If the smooth and the
|
||
homogeneous seem to communicate, it is only because when the striated
|
||
attains its ideal of perfect homogeneity, it is apt to reimpart smooth space,
|
||
by a movement that superposes itself upon that of the homogeneous but
|
||
remains entirely different from it. In each model, the smooth actually
|
||
seemed to pertain to a fundamental heterogeneity: felt or patchwork rather
|
||
than weaving, rhythmic values rather than harmony-melody, Riemannian
|
||
space rather than Euclidean space—a continuous variation that exceeds
|
||
any distribution of constants and variables, the freeing of a line that does
|
||
not pass between two points, the formation of a plane that does not proceed
|
||
by parallel and perpendicular lines.
|
||
The link between the homogeneous and the striated can be expressed in
|
||
terms of an imaginary, elementary physics. (1) You begin by striating space
|
||
with parallel gravitational verticals. (2) The resultant of these parallels or
|
||
forces is applied to a point inside the body occupying the space (center of
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 489
|
||
|
||
gravity). (3) The position of this point does not change when the direction
|
||
of the parallel forces is changed, when they become perpendicular to their
|
||
original direction. (4) You discover that gravity is a particular case of a uni-
|
||
versal attraction following straight lines or biunivocal relations between
|
||
two bodies. (5) You define a general notion of workas a force-displacement
|
||
relation in a certain direction. (6) You then have the physical basis for an
|
||
increasingly perfect striated space, running not only vertically and hori-
|
||
zontally, but in every direction subordinated to points.
|
||
It is not even necessary to invoke this Newtonian pseudophysics. The
|
||
Greeks already went from a space striated vertically, top to bottom, to a
|
||
centered space with reversible and symmetrical relations in all directions,
|
||
in other words, striated in every direction in such a way as to constitute a
|
||
homogeneity. There is no question that these are like two models of the
|
||
State apparatus, the vertical apparatus of the empire and the isotropic
|
||
apparatus of the city-state.21 Geometry lies at the crossroads of a physics
|
||
problem and an affair of the State.
|
||
It is obvious that the striation thus constituted has its limits: they are
|
||
reached not only when the infinite (either infinitely large or small) is
|
||
brought in, but also when more than two bodies are considered ("the three-
|
||
body problem"). Let us try to understand in the simplest terms how space
|
||
escapes the limits of its striation. At one pole, it escapes them by declina-
|
||
tion, in other words, by the smallest deviation, by the infinitely small devi-
|
||
ation between a gravitational vertical and the arc of a circle to which the
|
||
vertical is tangent. At the other pole, it escapes them by the spiral or vortex,
|
||
in other words, a figure in which all the points of space are simultaneously
|
||
occupied according to laws of frequency or of accumulation, distribution;
|
||
these laws are distinct from the so-called laminar distribution correspond-
|
||
ing to the striation of parallels. From the smallest deviation to the vortex
|
||
there is a valid and necessary relation of consequence: what stretches
|
||
between them is precisely a smooth space whose element is declination and
|
||
which is peopled by a spiral. Smooth space is constituted by the minimum
|
||
angle, which deviates from the vertical, and by the vortex, which overspills
|
||
striation. The strength of Michel Serres's book is that it demonstrates this
|
||
link between the clinamen as a generative differential element, and the for-
|
||
mation of vortices and turbulences insofar as they occupy an engendered
|
||
smooth space; in fact, the atom of the ancients, from Democritus to
|
||
Lucretius, was always inseparable from a hydraulics, or a generalized the-
|
||
ory of swells and flows. The ancient atom is entirely misunderstood if it is
|
||
overlooked that its essence is to course and flow. The theory of atomism is
|
||
the basis for a strict correlation between Archimedean geometry (very
|
||
different from the striated and homogeneous space of Euclid) and
|
||
Democritean physics (very different from solid or lamellar matter).22 The
|
||
490 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
same coincidence means that this aggregate is no longer tied in any way to a
|
||
State apparatus, but rather to a war machine: a physics of packs, turbu-
|
||
lences, "catastrophes," and epidemics corresponding to a geometry of war,
|
||
of the art of war and its machines. Serres states what he considers to be
|
||
Lucretius's deepest goal: to go from Mars to Venus, to place the war
|
||
machine in the service of peace.23 But this operation is not accomplished
|
||
through the State apparatus; it expresses, on the contrary, an ultimate
|
||
metamorphosis of the war machine, and occurs in smooth space.
|
||
Earlier we encountered a distinction between "free action" in smooth
|
||
space and "work" in striated space. During the nineteenth century a two-
|
||
fold elaboration was undertaken: of a physicoscientific concept of Work
|
||
(weight-height, force-displacement), and of a socioeconomic concept of
|
||
labor-power or abstract labor (a homogeneous abstract quantity applicable
|
||
to all work, and susceptible to multiplication and division). There was a
|
||
profound link between physics and sociology: society furnished an eco-
|
||
nomic standard of measure for work, and physics a "mechanical currency"
|
||
for it. The wage regime had as its correlate a mechanics of force. Physics
|
||
had never been more social, for in both cases it was a question of defining
|
||
the constant mean value of a force of lift and pull exerted in the most uni-
|
||
form way possible by a standard-man. Impose the Work-model upon every
|
||
activity, translate every act into possible or virtual work, discipline free
|
||
action, or else (which amounts to the same thing) relegate it to "leisure,"
|
||
which exists only by reference to work. We now understand why the Work-
|
||
model, in both its physical and social aspects, is a fundamental part of the
|
||
State apparatus. Standard-man began as the man of public works.24 It was
|
||
not in relation to pin manufacturing that the problems of abstract labor,
|
||
the multiplication of its results, and the division of its operations were first
|
||
formulated; it was in public construction and in the organization of armies
|
||
(not only the disciplining of men, but also the industrial production of
|
||
weapons). Nothing more normal. The war machine in itself did not imply
|
||
this normalization. But the State apparatus, in the eighteenth and nine-
|
||
teenth centuries, found a new way of appropriating the war machine: by
|
||
subjugating it before all else to the Work-model of the construction site and
|
||
factory, which were in the process of developing elsewhere, but more
|
||
slowly. The war machine was perhaps the first thing to be striated, to pro-
|
||
duce an abstract labor-time whose results could be multiplied and opera-
|
||
tions divided. That is where free action in smooth space must have been
|
||
conquered. The physicosocial model of Work pertains to the State appara-
|
||
tus, it is one of its inventions, and for two reasons. First, because labor
|
||
appears only with the constitution of a surplus, there is no labor that is not
|
||
devoted to stockpiling; in fact, labor (in the strict sense) begins only with
|
||
what is called surplus labor. Second, labor performs a generalized opera-
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 491
|
||
|
||
tion of striation of space-time, a subjection of free action, a nullification of
|
||
smooth spaces, the origin and means of which is in the essential enterprise
|
||
of the State, namely, its conquest of the war machine.
|
||
Counterdemonstration: where there is no State and no surplus labor,
|
||
there is no Work-model either. Instead, there is the continuous variation of
|
||
free action, passing from speech to action, from a given action to another,
|
||
from action to song, from song to speech, from speech to enterprise, all in a
|
||
strange chromaticism with intense but rare peak moments or moments of
|
||
effort that the outside observer can only "translate" in terms of work. It is
|
||
true that it has been said of blacks through the ages that "they don't work,
|
||
they don't know what work is." It is true that they were forced to work, and
|
||
to work more than anyone else, in terms of abstract quantity. It also seems
|
||
to be true that the Indians had no understanding of, and were unsuited
|
||
for, any organization of work, even slavery: the Americans apparently
|
||
imported so many blacks only because they could not use the Indians, who
|
||
would rather die. Certain outstanding ethnologists have raised an essential
|
||
question. They have turned the problem around: so-called primitive socie-
|
||
ties are not societies of shortage or subsistence due to an absence of work,
|
||
but on the contrary are societies of free action and smooth space that have
|
||
no use for a work-factor, anymore than they constitute a stock.25 They are
|
||
not societies of sloth, even though their differences with work may be
|
||
expressed in the form of a "right to laziness." They are not without laws,
|
||
even though their differences with the law may be expressed in the guise of
|
||
"anarchy." What they have instead is a law of the nomos regulating a con-
|
||
tinuous variation of activity with a rigor and cruelty all its own (get rid of
|
||
whatever cannot be transported, the old, children . . .).
|
||
If work constitutes a striated space-time corresponding to the State
|
||
apparatus, is this not especially true of its archaic or ancient forms? For it is
|
||
there that surplus labor is isolated, distinguished, in the form of tribute or
|
||
corvee. Consequently, it is there that the concept of labor appears at its
|
||
clearest, for example, in the large-scale works of the empires, the urban,
|
||
agricultural, or hydraulic works by which a "laminar" flow in supposedly
|
||
parallel layers (striation) is imposed upon the waters. It seems on the con-
|
||
trary that in the capitalist regime, surplus labor becomes less and less dis-
|
||
tinguishable from labor "strictly speaking," and totally impregnates it.
|
||
Modern public works have a different status from that of large-scale imper-
|
||
ial works. How could one possibly distinguish between the time necessary
|
||
for reproduction and "extorted" time, when they are no longer separated in
|
||
time? This remark certainly does not contradict the Marxist theory of sur-
|
||
plus value, for Marx shows precisely that surplus value ceases to be
|
||
localizable in the capitalist regime. That is even his fundamental contri-
|
||
bution. It gave him a sense that machines would themselves become
|
||
492 n 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
productive of surplus value and that the circulation of capital would chal-
|
||
lenge the distinction between variable and constant capital. In these new
|
||
conditions, it remains true that all labor involves surplus labor; but surplus
|
||
labor no longer requires labor. Surplus labor, capitalist organization in its
|
||
entirety, operates less and less by the striation of space-time corresponding
|
||
to the physicosocial concept of work. Rather, it is as though human aliena-
|
||
tion through surplus labor were replaced by a generalized "machinic
|
||
enslavement," such that one may furnish surplus-value without doing any
|
||
work (children, the retired, the unemployed, television viewers, etc.). Not
|
||
only does the user as such tend to become an employee, but capitalism
|
||
operates less on a quantity of labor than by a complex qualitative process
|
||
bringing into play modes of transportation, urban models, the media, the
|
||
entertainment industries, ways of perceiving and feeling—every semiotic
|
||
system. It is as though, at the outcome of the striation that capitalism was
|
||
able to carry to an unequaled point of perfection, circulating capital neces-
|
||
sarily recreated, reconstituted, a sort of smooth space in which the destiny
|
||
of human beings is recast. Striation, of course, survives in the most perfect
|
||
and severest of forms (it is not only vertical but operates in all directions);
|
||
however, it relates primarily to the state pole of capitalism, in other words,
|
||
to the role of the modern State apparatuses in the organization of capital.
|
||
On the other hand, at the complementary and dominant level of integrated
|
||
(or rather integrating) world capitalism, a new smooth space is produced in
|
||
which capital reaches its "absolute" speed, based on machinic components
|
||
rather than the human component of labor. The multinationals fabricate a
|
||
kind of deterritorialized smooth space in which points of occupation as
|
||
well as poles of exchange become quite independent of the classical paths
|
||
to striation. What is really new are always the new forms of turnover. The
|
||
present-day accelerated forms of the circulation of capital are making the
|
||
distinctions between constant and variable capital, and even fixed and cir-
|
||
culating capital, increasingly relative; the essential thing is instead the dis-
|
||
tinction between striated capital and smooth capital, and the way in which
|
||
the former gives rise to the latter through complexes that cut across terri-
|
||
tories and States, and even the different types of States.
|
||
|
||
The Aesthetic Model: Nomad Art. Several notions, both practical and the-
|
||
oretical, are suitable for defining nomad art and its successors (barbarian,
|
||
Gothic, and modern). First, "close-range" vision, as distinguished from
|
||
long-distance vision; second, "tactile," or rather "haptic" space, as distin-
|
||
guished from optical space. "Haptic" is a better word than "tactile" since it
|
||
does not establish an opposition between two sense organs but rather
|
||
invites the assumption that the eye itself may fulfill this nonoptical func-
|
||
tion. It was Alois Riegl who, in some marvelous pages, gave fundamental
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 493
|
||
|
||
aesthetic status to the couple, close vision-haptic space. But for the moment
|
||
we should set aside the criteria proposed by Riegl (then by Wilhelm
|
||
Worringer, and more recently by Henri Maldiney), and take some risks
|
||
ourselves, making free use of these notions.26 It seems to us that the Smooth
|
||
is both the object of a close vision par excellence and the element of a haptic
|
||
space (which may be as much visual or auditory as tactile). The Striated, on
|
||
the contrary, relates to a more distant vision, and a more optical space—
|
||
although the eye in turn is not the only organ to have this capacity. Once
|
||
again, as always, this analysis must be corrected by a coefficient of transfor-
|
||
mation according to which passages between the striated and the smooth
|
||
are at once necessary and uncertain, and all the more disruptive. The law of
|
||
the painting is that it be done at close range, even if it is viewed from rela-
|
||
tively far away. One can back away from a thing, but it is a bad painter who
|
||
backs away from the painting he or she is working on. Or from the "thing"
|
||
for that matter: Cezanne spoke of the need to no longer see the wheat field,
|
||
to be too close to it, to lose oneself without landmarks in smooth space.
|
||
Afterward, striation can emerge: drawing, strata, the earth, "stubborn
|
||
geometry," the "measure of the world," "geological foundations," "every-
|
||
thing falls straight down" . . . The striated itself may in turn disappear in a
|
||
"catastrophe," opening the way for a new smooth space, and another stri-
|
||
ated space...
|
||
A painting is done at close range, even if it is seen from a distance. Simi-
|
||
larly, it is said that composers do not hear: they have close-range hearing,
|
||
whereas listeners hear from a distance. Even writers write with short-term
|
||
memory, whereas readers are assumed to be endowed with long-term
|
||
memory. The first aspect of the haptic, smooth space of close vision is that
|
||
its orientations, landmarks, and linkages are in continuous variation; it
|
||
operates step by step. Examples are the desert, steppe, ice, and sea, local
|
||
spaces of pure connection. Contrary to what is sometimes said, one never
|
||
sees from a distance in a space of this kind, nor does one see it from a dis-
|
||
tance; one is never "in front of," any more than one is "in" (one is "on" ...).
|
||
Orientations are not constant but change according to temporary vegeta-
|
||
tion, occupations, and precipitation. There is no visual model for points of
|
||
reference that would make them interchangeable and unite them in an
|
||
inertial class assignable to an immobile outside observer. On the contrary,
|
||
they are tied to any number of observers, who may be qualified as "mon-
|
||
ads" but are instead nomads entertaining tactile relations among them-
|
||
selves. The interlinkages do not imply an ambient space in which the
|
||
multiplicity would be immersed and which would make distances invari-
|
||
ant; rather, they are constituted according to ordered differences that give
|
||
rise to intrinsic variations in the division of a single distance.27 These ques-
|
||
tions of orientation, location, and linkage enter into play in the most
|
||
494 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
famous works of nomad art: the twisted animals have no land beneath
|
||
them; the ground constantly changes direction, as in aerial acrobatics; the
|
||
paws point in the opposite direction from the head, the hind part of the
|
||
body is turned upside down; the "monadological" points of view can be
|
||
interlinked only on a nomad space; the whole and the parts give the eye that
|
||
beholds them a function that is haptic rather than optical. This is an
|
||
animality that can be seen only by touching it with one's mind, but without
|
||
the mind becoming a finger, not even by way of the eye. (In a much cruder
|
||
fashion, the kaleidoscope has exactly the same function: to give the eye a
|
||
digital function.) Striated space, on the contrary, is defined by the require-
|
||
ments of long-distance vision: constancy of orientation, in variance of dis-
|
||
tance through an interchange of inertial points of reference, interlinkage by
|
||
immersion in an ambient milieu, constitution of a central perspective. It is
|
||
less easy to evaluate the creative potentialities of striated space, and how it
|
||
can simultaneously emerge from the smooth and give everything a whole
|
||
new impetus.
|
||
The opposition between the striated and the smooth is not simply that of
|
||
the global and the local. For in one case, the global is still relative, whereas
|
||
in the other the local is already absolute. Where there is close vision, space
|
||
is not visual, or rather the eye itself has a haptic, nonoptical function: no
|
||
line separates earth from sky, which are of the same substance; there is nei-
|
||
ther horizon nor background nor perspective nor limit nor outline or form
|
||
nor center; there is no intermediary distance, or all distance is intermedi-
|
||
ary. Like Eskimo space.28 In a totally different way, in a totally different
|
||
context, Arab architecture constitutes a space that begins very near and
|
||
low, placing the light and the airy below and the solid and heavy above.
|
||
This reversal of the laws of gravity turns lack of direction and negation of
|
||
volume into constructive forces. There exists a nomadic absolute, as a local
|
||
integration moving from part to part and constituting smooth space in an
|
||
infinite succession of linkages and changes in direction. It is an absolute
|
||
that is one with becoming itself, with process. It is the absolute of passage,
|
||
which in nomad art merges with its manifestation. Here the absolute is
|
||
local, precisely because place is not delimited. If we now turn to the striated
|
||
and optical space of long-distance vision, we see that the relative global
|
||
that characterizes that space also requires the absolute, but in an entirely
|
||
different way. The absolute is now the horizon or background, in other
|
||
words, the Encompassing Element without which nothing would be global
|
||
or englobed. It is against this background that the relative outline or form
|
||
appears. The absolute itself can appear in the Encompassed, but only in a
|
||
privileged place well delimited as a center, which then functions to repel
|
||
beyond the limits anything that menaces the global integration. We can see
|
||
clearly here how smooth space subsists, but only to give rise to the striated.
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 495
|
||
|
||
The desert, sky, or sea, the Ocean, the Unlimited, first plays the role of an
|
||
encompassing element, and tends to become a horizon: the earth is thus
|
||
surrounded, globalized, "grounded" by this element, which holds it in
|
||
immobile equilibrium and makes Form possible. Then to the extent that
|
||
the encompassing element itself appears at the center of the earth, it
|
||
assumes a second role, that of casting into the loathesome deep, the abode
|
||
of the dead, anything smooth or nonmeasured that may have remained.29
|
||
The striation of the earth implies as its necessary condition this double
|
||
treatment of the smooth: on the one hand, it is carried or reduced to the
|
||
absolute state of an encompassing horizon, and on the other it is expelled
|
||
from the relative encompassed element. Thus the great imperial religions
|
||
need a smooth space like the desert, but only in order to give it a law that is
|
||
opposed to the nomos in every way, and converts the absolute.
|
||
This perhaps explains for us the ambiguity of the excellent analyses by
|
||
Riegl, Worringer, and Maldiney. They approach haptic space under the
|
||
imperial conditions of Egyptian art. They define it as the presence of a
|
||
horizon-background; the reduction of space to the plane (vertical and hori-
|
||
zontal, height and width); and the rectilinear outline enclosing individual-
|
||
ity and withdrawing it from change. Like the pyramid-form, every side a
|
||
plane surface, against the background of the immobile desert. On the other
|
||
hand, they show how in Greek art (then in Byzantine art, and up to the Ren-
|
||
aissance), an optical space was differentiated from haptic space, one merg-
|
||
ing background with form, setting up an interference between the planes,
|
||
conquering depth, working with cubic or voluminous extension, organiz-
|
||
ing perspective, and playing on relief and shadow, light and color. Thus at
|
||
the very beginning they encounter the haptic at a point of mutation, in con-
|
||
ditions under which it already serves to striate space. The optical makes
|
||
that striation tighter and more perfect, or rather tight and perfect in a dif-
|
||
ferent way (it is not associated with the same "artistic will"). Everything
|
||
occurs in a striated space that goes from empires to city-states, or evolved
|
||
empires. It is not by chance that Riegl tends to eliminate the specific fac-
|
||
tors of nomad or even barbarian art; or that Worringer, when he introduces
|
||
the idea of Gothic art in the broadest sense, relates it on the one hand to the
|
||
Germanic and Celtic migrations of the North, and on the other to the
|
||
empires of the East. But between the two were the nomads, who are reduci-
|
||
ble neither to empires they confronted nor the migrations they triggered.
|
||
The Goths themselves were nomads of the steppe, and with the Sarmatians
|
||
and Huns were an essential vector of communication between the East and
|
||
the North, a factor irreducible to either of these two dimensions.30 On one
|
||
side, Egypt had its Hyksos, Asia Minor its Hittites, China its Turco-
|
||
Mongols; and on the other, the Hebrews had their Habiru, the Germans,
|
||
Celts, and Romans their Goths, the Arabs their Bedouins. The nomads
|
||
496 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
have a specificity that is too hastily reduced to its consequences, by includ-
|
||
ing them in the empires or counting them among the migrants, assimilat-
|
||
ing them to one or the other, denying them their own "will" to art. Again,
|
||
there is a refusal to accept that the intermediary between the East and the
|
||
North had its own absolute specificity, that the intermediary, the interval,
|
||
played exactly this substantial role. Moreover, it does not have that role in
|
||
the guise of a "will"; it only has a becoming, it invents a "becoming-artist."
|
||
When we invoke a primordial duality between the smooth and the stri-
|
||
ated, it is in order to subordinate the differences between "haptic" and
|
||
"optic," "close vision" and "distant vision" to this distinction. Hence we
|
||
will not define the haptic by the immobile background, by the plane and
|
||
the contour, because these have to do with an already mixed state in which
|
||
the haptic serves to striate, and uses its smooth components only in order
|
||
to convert them to another kind of space. The haptic function and close
|
||
vision presuppose the smooth, which has no background, plane, or con-
|
||
tour, but rather changes in direction and local linkages between parts. Con-
|
||
versely, the developed optical function is not content to take striation to a
|
||
new level of perfection, endowing it with an imaginary universal value and
|
||
scope; it is also capable of reinstating the smooth, liberating light and mod-
|
||
ulating color, restoring a kind of aerial haptic space that constitutes the
|
||
unlimited site of intersection of the planes.31 In short, the smooth and the
|
||
striated must be defined in themselves before the relative distinctions
|
||
between haptic and optical, near and distant, can be derived.
|
||
This is where a third couple enters in: "abstract line-concrete line"
|
||
(in addition to "haptic-optical," "close-distant"). It is Worringer who
|
||
accorded fundamental importance to the abstract line, seeing it as the very
|
||
beginning of art or the first expression of an artistic will. Art as abstract
|
||
machine. Once again, it will doubtless be our inclination to voice in
|
||
advance the same objections: for Worringer, the abstract line seems to
|
||
make its first appearance in the crystalline or geometrical imperial Egyp-
|
||
tian form, the most rectilinear of forms possible. It is only afterward that it
|
||
assumes a particular avatar, constituting the "Gothic or Northern line"
|
||
understood very broadly.32 For us, on the other hand, the abstract line is
|
||
fundamentally "Gothic," or rather, nomadic, not rectilinear. Conse-
|
||
quently, we do not understand the aesthetic motivation for the abstract line
|
||
in the same way, or its identity with the beginning of art. Whereas the recti-
|
||
linear (or "regularly" rounded) Egyptian line is negatively motivated by
|
||
anxiety in the face of all that passes, flows, or varies, and erects the con-
|
||
stancy and eternity of an In-Itself, the nomad line is abstract in an entirely
|
||
different sense, precisely because it has a multiple orientation and passes
|
||
between points, figures, and contours: it is positively motivated by the
|
||
smooth space it draws, not by any striation it might perform to ward off
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 497
|
||
|
||
anxiety and subordinate the smooth. The abstract line is the affect of
|
||
smooth spaces, not a feeling of anxiety that calls forth striation. Further-
|
||
more, although it is true that art begins only with the abstract line, the rea-
|
||
son is not, as Worringer says, that the rectilinear is the first means of
|
||
breaking with the nonaesthetic imitation of nature upon which the prehis-
|
||
toric, savage, and childish supposedly depend, lacking, as he thinks they
|
||
do, a "will to art." On the contrary, if prehistoric art is fully art it is precisely
|
||
because it manipulates the abstract, though nonrectilinear, line: "Primi-
|
||
tive art begins with the abstract, and even the prefigurative.... Art is
|
||
abstract from the outset, and at its origin could not have been otherwise."33
|
||
In effect, the line is all the more abstract when writing is absent, either
|
||
because it has yet to develop or only exists outside or alongside. When writ-
|
||
ing takes charge of abstraction, as it does in empires, the line, already
|
||
downgraded, necessarily tends to become concrete, even figurative. Chil-
|
||
dren forget how to draw. But in the absence of writing, or when peoples
|
||
have no need for a writing system of their own because theirs is borrowed
|
||
from more or less nearby empires (as was the case for the nomads), the line
|
||
is necessarily abstract; it is necessarily invested with all the power of
|
||
abstraction, which finds no other outlet. That is why we believe that the dif-
|
||
ferent major types of imperial lines—the Egyptian rectilinear line, the
|
||
Assyrian (or Greek) organic line, the supraphenomenal, encompassing
|
||
Chinese line—convert the abstract line, rend it from its smooth space, and
|
||
accord it concrete values. Still, it can be argued that these imperial lines are
|
||
contemporaneous with the abstract line; the abstract line is no less at the
|
||
"beginning," inasmuch as it is a pole always presupposed by any line capa-
|
||
ble of constituting another pole. The abstract line is at the beginning as
|
||
much because of its historical abstraction as its prehistoric dating. It is
|
||
therefore a part of the originality or irreducibility of nomad art, even when
|
||
there is reciprocal interaction, influence, and confrontation with the
|
||
imperial lines of sedentary art.
|
||
The abstract is not directly opposed to the figurative. The figurative as
|
||
such is not inherent to any "will to art." In fact, we may oppose a figurative
|
||
line in art to one that is not. The figurative, or imitation and representa-
|
||
tion, is a consequence, a result of certain characteristics of the line when it
|
||
assumes a given form. We must therefore define those characteristics first.
|
||
Take a system in which transversals are subordinated to diagonals, diago-
|
||
nals to horizontals and verticals, and horizontals and verticals to points
|
||
(even when there are virtual). A system of this kind, which is rectilinear or
|
||
unilinear regardless of the number of lines, expresses the formal conditions
|
||
under which a space is striated and the line describes a contour. Such a line
|
||
is inherently, formally, representative in itself, even if it does not represent
|
||
anything. On the other hand, a line that delimits nothing, that describes no
|
||
498 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
contour, that no longer goes from one point to another but instead passes
|
||
between points, that is always declining from the horizontal and the verti-
|
||
cal and deviating from the diagonal, that is constantly changing direction,
|
||
a mutant line of this kind that is without outside or inside, form or back-
|
||
ground, beginning or end and that is as alive as a continuous variation—
|
||
such a line is truly an abstract line, and describes a smooth space. It is not
|
||
inexpressive. Yet is true that it does not constitute a stable and symmetrical
|
||
form of expression grounded in a resonance of points and a conjunction of
|
||
lines. It is nevertheless accompanied by material traits of expression, the
|
||
effects of which multiply step by step. This is what Worringer means when
|
||
he says that the Gothic line (for us, the nomadic line invested with abstrac-
|
||
tion) has the power of expression and not of form, that it has repetition as a
|
||
power, not symmetry as form. Indeed, it is through symmetry that rectilin-
|
||
ear systems limit repetition, preventing infinite progression and maintain-
|
||
ing the organic domination of a central point with radiating lines, as in
|
||
reflected or star-shaped figures. It is free action, however, which by its
|
||
essence unleashes the power of repetition as a machinic force that multi-
|
||
plies its effect and pursues an infinite movement. Free action proceeds by
|
||
disjunction and decentering, or at least by peripheral movement: dis-
|
||
joinj/ed polythetism instead of symmetrical antithetism.34 Traits of expres-
|
||
sion describing a smooth space and connecting with a matter-flow thus
|
||
should not be confused with striae that convert space and make it a form of
|
||
expression that grids and organizes matter.
|
||
Worringer's finest pages are those in which he contrasts the abstract
|
||
with the organic. The organic does not designate something represented,
|
||
but above all the form of representation, and even the feeling that unites
|
||
representation with a subject (Einfuhlung, "empathy"). "Formal processes
|
||
occur within the work of art which correspond to the natural organic ten-
|
||
dencies in man."35 But the rectilinear, the geometrical, cannot be opposed
|
||
to the organic in this sense. The Greek organic line, which subordinates
|
||
volume and spatiality, takes over from the Egyptian geometrical line,
|
||
which reduced them to the plane. The organic, with its symmetry and con-
|
||
tours inside and outside, still refers to the rectilinear coordinates of a stri-
|
||
ated space. The organic body is prolonged by straight lines that attach it to
|
||
what lies in the distance. Hence the primacy of human beings, or of the
|
||
face: We are this form of expression itself, simultaneously the supreme
|
||
organism and the relation of all organisms to metric space in general. The
|
||
abstract, on the contrary, begins only with what Worringer presents as the
|
||
"Gothic" avatar. It is this nomadic line that he says is mechanical, but in
|
||
free action and swirling; it is inorganic, yet alive, and all the more alive for
|
||
being inorganic. It is distinguished both from the geometrical and the
|
||
organic. It raises "mechanical" relations to the level of intuition. Heads
|
||
1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED D 499
|
||
|
||
(even a human being's when it is not a face) unravel and coil into ribbons in
|
||
a continuous process; mouths curl in spirals. Hair, clothes. . . This stream-
|
||
ing, spiraling, zigzagging, snaking, feverish line of variation liberates a
|
||
power of life that human beings had rectified and organisms had confined,
|
||
and which matter now expresses as the trait, flow, or impulse traversing it.
|
||
If everything is alive, it is not because everything is organic or organized
|
||
but, on the contrary, because the organism is a diversion of life. In short,
|
||
the life in question is inorganic, germinal, and intensive, a powerful life
|
||
without organs, a Body that is all the more alive for having no organs,
|
||
everything that passes between organisms ("once the natural barriers of
|
||
organic movement have been overthrown, there are no more limits").36
|
||
Many authors have wished to establish a kind of duality in nomad art
|
||
between the ornamental abstract line and animal motifs, or more subtly,
|
||
between the speed with which the line integrates and carries expressive
|
||
traits, and the slowness or fixity of the animal matter traversed, between a
|
||
line of flight without beginning or end and an almost immobile swirling.
|
||
But in the end everyone agrees that it is a question of a single will, or a single
|
||
becoming.37 This is not because the abstract engenders organic motifs, by
|
||
chance or by association. Rather, it is precisely because pure animality is
|
||
experienced as inorganic, or supraorganic, that it can combine so well with
|
||
abstraction, and even combine the slowness or heaviness of a matter with
|
||
the extreme speed of a line that has become entirely spiritual. The slowness
|
||
belongs to the same world as the extreme speed: relations of speed and
|
||
slowness between elements, which surpass in every way the movement of
|
||
an organic form and the determination of organs. The line escapes geome-
|
||
try by a fugitive mobility at the same time as life tears itself free from the
|
||
organic by a permutating, stationary whirlwind. This vital force specific to
|
||
the Abstraction is what draws smooth space. The abstract line is the affect
|
||
of smooth space, just as organic representation was the feeling presiding
|
||
over striated space. The haptic-optical, near-distant distinctions must be
|
||
subordinated to the distinction between the abstract line and the organic
|
||
line; they must find their principle in a general confrontation of spaces.
|
||
The abstract line cannot be defined as geometrical and rectilinear. What
|
||
then should be termed abstract in modern art? A line of variable direction
|
||
that describes no contour and delimits no form . . ,38
|
||
|
||
Do not multiply models. We are well aware that there are many others: a
|
||
ludic model, which would compare games according to their type of space
|
||
and found game theory on different principles (for example, the smooth
|
||
space of Go versus the striated space of chess); and a noological model con-
|
||
cerned not with thought contents (ideology) but with the form, manner or
|
||
mode, and function of thought, according to the mental space it draws and
|
||
500 D 1440: THE SMOOTH AND THE STRIATED
|
||
|
||
from the point of view of a general theory of thought, a thinking of thought.
|
||
And so on. Moreover, there are still other kinds of space that should be
|
||
taken into account, for example, holey space and the way it communicates
|
||
with the smooth and the striated in different ways. What interests us in
|
||
operations of striation and smoothing are precisely the passages or combi-
|
||
nations: how the forces at work within space continually striate it, and how
|
||
in the course of its striation it develops other forces and emits new smooth
|
||
spaces. Even the most striated city gives rise to smooth spaces: to live in the
|
||
city as a nomad, or as a cave dweller. Movements, speed and slowness, are
|
||
sometimes enough to reconstruct a smooth space. Of course, smooth
|
||
spaces are not in themselves liberatory. But the struggle is changed or dis-
|
||
placed in them, and life reconstitutes its stakes, confronts new obstacles,
|
||
invents new paces, switches adversaries. Never believe that a smooth space
|
||
will suffice to save us.
|
||
15. Conclusion: Concrete Rules and
|
||
Abstract Machines
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Computer Einstein
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
501
|
||
502 O CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES
|
||
|
||
S
|
||
|
||
Strata, stratification
|
||
The strata are phenomena of thickening on the Body of the earth,
|
||
3 simultaneously molecular and molar: accumulations, coagulations,
|
||
sedimentations, foldings. They are Belts, Pincers, or Articulations.
|
||
Summarily and traditionally, we distinguish three major strata:
|
||
physicochemical, organic, and anthropomorphic (or "alloplastic").
|
||
Each stratum, or articulation, consists of coded milieus and formed
|
||
substances. Forms and substances, codes and milieus are not really
|
||
distinct. They are the abstract components of every articulation.
|
||
A stratum obviously presents very diverse forms and substances, a
|
||
variety of codes and milieus. It thus possesses both different formal
|
||
Types of organization and different substantial Modes of develop-
|
||
ment, which divide it into parastrata and epistrata, for example, the
|
||
divisions of the organic stratum. The epistrata and parastrata subdi-
|
||
viding a stratum can be considered strata themselves (so that the list
|
||
is never exhaustive). A given stratum retains a unity of composition
|
||
in spite of the diversity in its organization and development. The
|
||
unity of composition relates to formal traits common to all of the
|
||
forms or codes of a stratum, and to substantial elements, materials
|
||
common to all of the stratum's substances or milieus.
|
||
The strata are extremely mobile. One stratum is always capable
|
||
of serving as the substratum of another, or of colliding with
|
||
another, independently of any evolutionary order. Above all, be-
|
||
ween two strata or between two stratic divisions, there are inter-
|
||
stratic phenomena: transcodings and passages between milieus,
|
||
intermixings. Rhythms pertain to these interstratic movements,
|
||
which are also acts of stratification. Stratification is like the creation
|
||
of the world from chaos, a continual, renewed creation. And the strata
|
||
constitute the Judgment of God. Classical artists are like God, they
|
||
make the world by organizing forms and substances, codes and
|
||
milieus, and rhythms.
|
||
Articulation, which is constitutive of a stratum, is always a double
|
||
articulation (double pincer). What is articulated is a content and an
|
||
expression. Whereas form and substance are not really distinct, con-
|
||
tent and expression are. Hjelmslev's net is applicable to the strata:
|
||
articulation of content and articulation of expression, with content
|
||
and expression each possessing its own form and substance. Between
|
||
them, between content and expression, there is neither a correspon-
|
||
dence nor a cause-effect relation nor a signified-signifier relation:
|
||
CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES D 503
|
||
|
||
there is real distinction, reciprocal presupposition, and only isomor-
|
||
phy. But content and expression are not distinguished from each
|
||
other in the same fashion on each stratum: the distribution of content
|
||
and expression is not the same on the three major strata (there is, for
|
||
example, a "linearization" of expression on the organic stratum, and
|
||
a "superlinearity" of the anthropomorphic strata). That is why the
|
||
molar and the molecular have very different combinations depend-
|
||
ing on the stratum considered.
|
||
3 What movement, what impulse, sweeps us outside the strata
|
||
and (metastratd)! Of course, there is no reason to think that all matter is
|
||
4 confined to the physicochemical strata: there exists a submolecular,
|
||
unformed Matter. Similarly, not all Life is confined to the organic
|
||
strata: rather, the organism is that which life sets against itself in order
|
||
to limit itself, and there is a life all the more intense, all the more pow-
|
||
erful for being anorganic. There are also nonhuman Becomings of
|
||
human beings that overspill the anthropomorphic strata in all direc-
|
||
tions. But how can we reach this "plane," or rather how can we con-
|
||
struct it, and how can we draw the "line" leading us there? For outside
|
||
the strata or in the absence of strata we no longer have forms or sub-
|
||
stances, organization or development, content or expression. We are
|
||
disarticulated; we no longer even seem to be sustained by rhythms.
|
||
How could unformed matter, anorganic life, nonhuman becoming be
|
||
anything but chaos pure and simple? Every undertaking of
|
||
destratification (for example, going beyond the organism, plunging
|
||
into a becoming) must therefore observe concrete rules of extreme
|
||
6 caution: a too-sudden destratification may be suicidal, or turn can-
|
||
cerous. In other words, it will sometimes end in chaos, the void and
|
||
destruction, and sometimes lock us back into the strata, which
|
||
become more rigid still, losing their degrees of diversity, differentia-
|
||
tion, and mobility.
|
||
|
||
A
|
||
|
||
Assemblages
|
||
Assemblages are already different from strata. They are produced in
|
||
11 the strata, but operate in zones where milieus become decoded: they
|
||
begin by extracting a territory from the milieus. Every assemblage is
|
||
basically territorial. The first concrete rule for assemblages is to dis-
|
||
cover what territoriality they envelop, for there always is one: in their
|
||
trash can or on their bench, Beckett's characters stake out a territory.
|
||
Discover the territorial assemblages of someone, human or animal:
|
||
504 D CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES
|
||
|
||
"home." The territory is made of decoded fragments of all kinds,
|
||
which are borrowed from the milieus but then assume the value of
|
||
"properties": even rhythms take on a new meaning (refrains). The ter-
|
||
ritory makes the assemblage. The territory is more than the organism
|
||
and the milieu, and the relation between the two; that is why the
|
||
assemblage goes beyond mere "behavior" (hence the importance of
|
||
the relative distinction between territorial animals and milieu
|
||
animals).
|
||
Inasmuch as they are territorial, assemblages still belong to the
|
||
strata. At least they pertain to them in one of their aspects, and it is
|
||
under this aspect that we distinguish in every assemblage content
|
||
4 from expression. It is necessary to ascertain the content and the
|
||
expression of each assemblage, to evaluate their real distinction, their
|
||
reciprocal presupposition, their piecemeal insertions. The reason
|
||
that the assemblage is not confined to the strata is that expression in it
|
||
becomes a semiotic system, a regime of signs, and content becomes a
|
||
pragmatic system, actions and passions. This is the double articula-
|
||
tion face-hand, gesture-word, and the reciprocal presupposition
|
||
between the two. This is the first division of every assemblage: it is
|
||
simultaneously and inseparably a machinic assemblage and an
|
||
assemblage of enunciation. In each case, it is necessary to ascertain
|
||
both what is said and what is done. There is a new relation between
|
||
content and expression that was not yet present in the strata: the
|
||
statements or expressions express incorporeal transformations that
|
||
are "attributed" as such (properties) to bodies or contents. In the
|
||
strata, expressions do not form signs, nor contents pragmata, so this
|
||
autonomous zone of incorporeal transformations expressed by the
|
||
former and attributed to the latter does not appear. Of course,
|
||
regimes of signs develop only in the alloplastic or anthropomorphic
|
||
strata (including territorialized animals). But this does not mean that
|
||
they do not permeate all of the strata, and overspill each of them.
|
||
Assemblages belong to the strata to the extent that the distinction
|
||
between content and expression still holds for them. We may also
|
||
think of regimes of signs and pragmatic systems as strata in their own
|
||
right, in the broad sense previously mentioned. But because the
|
||
content-expression distinction assumes a new figure, we are already
|
||
in a different element than that of the strata in the narrow sense.
|
||
The assemblage is also divided along another axis. Its territoriality
|
||
(content and expression included) is only a first aspect; the other
|
||
aspect is constituted by lines of deterritorialization that cut across it
|
||
and carry it away. These lines are very diverse: some open the territor-
|
||
ial assemblage onto other assemblages (for example, the territorial
|
||
CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES D 505
|
||
|
||
refrain of the animal becomes a courtship or group refrain). Others
|
||
operate directly upon the territoriality of the assemblage, and open it
|
||
onto a land that is eccentric, immemorial, or yet to come (for exam-
|
||
ple, the game of territory and the earth in the lied, or in the romantic
|
||
11 artist in general). Still others open assemblages onto abstract and cos-
|
||
and mic machines that they effectuate. The territoriality of the assem-
|
||
4 blage originates in a certain decoding of milieus, and is just as
|
||
necessarily extended by lines of deterritorialization. The territory is
|
||
just as inseparable from deterritorialization as the code from decod-
|
||
ing. Following these lines, the assemblage no longer presents an
|
||
expression distinct from content, only unformed matters, destrati-
|
||
fied forces, and functions. The concrete rules of assemblage thus
|
||
operate along these two axes: On the one hand, what is the territorial-
|
||
ity of the assemblage, what is the regime of signs and the pragmatic
|
||
system? On the other hand, what are the cutting edges of deterritori-
|
||
alization, and what abstract machines do they effectuate? The assem-
|
||
blage is tetravalent: (1) content and expression; (2) territoriality and
|
||
deterritorialization. That is why there were four aspects in the privi-
|
||
leged example of Kafka's assemblages.
|
||
|
||
R
|
||
|
||
Rhizome
|
||
10 Not only strata, assemblages are complexes of lines. We can identify a
|
||
first state of the line, or a first kind of line: the line is subordinated to
|
||
the point; the diagonal is subordinated to the horizontal and vertical;
|
||
the line forms a contour, whether figurative or not; the space it consti-
|
||
tutes is one of striation; the countable multiplicity it constitutes
|
||
remains subordinated to the One in an always superior or supplemen-
|
||
tary dimension. Lines of this type are molar, and form a segmentary,
|
||
9 circular, binary, arborescent system.
|
||
and The second kind is very different, molecular and of the "rhizome"
|
||
1 type. The diagonal frees itself, breaks or twists. The line no longer
|
||
forms a contour, and instead passes between things, between points. It
|
||
belongs to a smooth space. It draws a plane that has no more dimen-
|
||
sions than that which crosses it; therefore the multiplicity it consti-
|
||
tutes is no longer subordinated to the One, but takes on a consistency
|
||
2 of its own. These are multiplicities of masses or packs, not of classes;
|
||
10 anomalous and nomadic multiplicities, not normal or legal ones;
|
||
12 multiplicities of becoming, or transformational multiplicities, not
|
||
and 14 countable elements and ordered relations; fuzzy, not exact aggre-
|
||
506 D CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES
|
||
|
||
gates, etc. At the level of pathos, these multiplicities are expressed by
|
||
psychosis and especially schizophrenia. At the level of pragmatics,
|
||
they are utilized by sorcery. At the level of theory, the status of multi-
|
||
plicities is correlative to that of spaces, and vice versa: smooth spaces
|
||
of the type desert, steppe, or sea are not without people; they are not
|
||
depopulated but rather are populated by multiplicities of this second
|
||
kind (mathematics and music have gone quite far in the elaboration
|
||
of this theory of multiplicities).
|
||
It is not enough, however, to replace the opposition between the
|
||
One and the multiple with a distinction between types of multiplici-
|
||
9 ties. For the distinction between the two types does not preclude their
|
||
immanence to each other, each "issuing" from the other after its fash-
|
||
ion. It is not so much that some multiplicities are arborescent and
|
||
others not, but that there is an arborification of multiplicities. That is
|
||
what happens when the black holes scattered along a rhizome begin
|
||
to resonate together, or when the stems form segments that striate
|
||
space in all directions, rendering it comparable, divisible, homoge-
|
||
12 neous (as we saw in particular in the case of the Face). That is also
|
||
what happens when "mass" movements or molecular flows conjugate
|
||
at points of accumulation or stoppage that segment and rectify them.
|
||
But conversely, and without symmetry, the stems of the rhizome are
|
||
always taking leave of the trees, the masses and flows are constantly
|
||
escaping, inventing connections that jump from tree to tree and
|
||
uproot them: a whole smoothing of space, which in turn reacts back
|
||
upon striated space. Even, and especially, territories are perturbed by
|
||
these deep movements. Or language: the trees of language are shaken
|
||
by buddings and rhizomes. So that rhizome lines oscillate between
|
||
8 tree lines that segment and even stratify them, and lines of flight or
|
||
and rupture that carry them away.
|
||
9 We are therefore made of three lines, but each kind of line has its
|
||
dangers. Not only the segmented lines that cleave us, and impose
|
||
upon us the striations of a homogeneous space, but also the molecular
|
||
lines, already ferrying their micro-black holes, and finally the lines of
|
||
flight themselves, which always risk abandoning their creative poten-
|
||
tialities and turning into a line of death, being turned into a line of
|
||
destruction pure and simple (fascism).
|
||
|
||
C
|
||
|
||
Plane of Consistency, Body without Organs
|
||
The plane of consistency or of composition (planomenon) is opposed
|
||
CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES D 507
|
||
|
||
10 to the plane of organization and development. Organization and
|
||
development concern form and substance: at once the development
|
||
of form and the formation of substance or a subject. But the plane of
|
||
consistency knows nothing of substance and form: haecceities, which
|
||
are inscribed on this plane, are precisely modes of individuation pro-
|
||
ceeding neither by form nor by the subject. The plane consists
|
||
abstractly, but really, in relations of speed and slowness between
|
||
unformed elements, and in compositions of corresponding intensive
|
||
affects (the "longitude" and "latitude" of the plane). In another sense,
|
||
consistency concretely ties together heterogeneous, disparate ele-
|
||
11 ments as such: it assures the consolidation of fuzzy aggregates, in
|
||
other words, multiplicities of the rhizome type. In effect, consistency,
|
||
proceeding by consolidation, acts necessarily in the middle, by the
|
||
middle, and stands opposed to all planes of principle or finality.
|
||
Spinoza, Holderlin, Kleist, Nietzsche are the surveyors of such a
|
||
plane of consistency. Never unifications, never totalizations, but
|
||
rather consistencies or consolidations.
|
||
10 Inscribed on the plane of consistency are haecceities, events, incor-
|
||
poreal transformations that are apprehended in themselves; nomadic
|
||
essences, vague yet rigorous; continuums of intensities or continuous
|
||
4, 6 variations, which go beyond constants and variables; becomings,
|
||
1, 9 which have neither culmination nor subject, but draw one another
|
||
into zones of proximity or undecidability; smooth spaces, composed
|
||
from within striated space. We will say that a body without organs, or
|
||
6 bodies without organs (plateaus) comes into play in individuation by
|
||
and haecceity, in the production of intensities beginning at a degree zero,
|
||
10 in the matter of variation, in the medium of becoming or transforma-
|
||
tion, and in the smoothing of space. A powerful nonorganic life that
|
||
14 escapes the strata, cuts across assemblages, and draws an abstract line
|
||
without contour, a line of nomad art and itinerant metallurgy.
|
||
Does the plane of consistency constitute the body without organs,
|
||
or does the body without organs compose the plane? Are the Body
|
||
without Organs and the Plane the same thing? In any event, composer
|
||
and composed have the same power: the line does not have a dimen-
|
||
sion superior to that of the point, nor the surface to that of the line,
|
||
10 nor the volume to that of the surface, but always an anexact, frac-
|
||
and tional number of dimensions that constantly increase or decrease
|
||
14 with the number of its parts. The plane sections multiplicities of vari-
|
||
able dimensions. The question is, therefore, the mode of connection
|
||
between the different parts of the plane: To what extent do the bodies
|
||
without organs interconnect? How are the continuums of intensity
|
||
extended? What is the order of the transformational series? What are
|
||
508 D CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES
|
||
|
||
these alogical linkages always effected in the middle, through which
|
||
the plane is constructed piece by piece in ascending or descending
|
||
fractional order? The plane is like a row of doors. And the concrete
|
||
rules for the construction of the plane obtain to the extent that they
|
||
exercise a selective role. It is the plane, in other words, the mode of
|
||
connection, that provides the means of eliminating the empty and
|
||
cancerous bodies that rival the body without organs, of rejecting the
|
||
homogeneous surfaces that overlay smooth space, and neutraliz-
|
||
ing the lines of death and destruction that divert the line of flight.
|
||
What is retained and preserved, therefore created, what consists, is
|
||
only that which increases the number of connections at each level of
|
||
division or composition, thus in descending as well as ascending
|
||
order (that which is cannot be divided without changing in nature, or
|
||
enter into a larger composition without requiring a new criterion of
|
||
comparison...).
|
||
|
||
D
|
||
|
||
Deterritorialization
|
||
The function of deterritorialization: D is the movement by which
|
||
5 "one" leaves the territory. It is the operation of the line of flight.
|
||
There are very different cases. D may be overlaid by a compensatory
|
||
reterritorialization obstructing the line of flight: D is then said to be
|
||
negative. Anything can serve as a reterritorialization, in other
|
||
words, "stand for" the lost territory; one can reterritorialize on a
|
||
being, an object, a book, an apparatus or system.. . For example, it
|
||
is inaccurate to say that the State apparatus is territorial: it in fact
|
||
performs a D, but one immediately overlaid by reterritorializations
|
||
on property, work, and money (clearly, that landowner ship, public
|
||
or private, is not territorial but reterritorializing). Among regimes
|
||
of signs, the signifying regime certainly attains a high level of D;
|
||
but because it simultaneously sets up a whole system of reterri-
|
||
torializations on the signified, and on the signifier itself, it blocks
|
||
the line of flight, allowing only a negative D to persist. Another case
|
||
is when D becomes positive—in other words, when it prevails over
|
||
the reterritorializations, which play only a secondary role—but
|
||
nevertheless remains relative because the line of flight it draws is
|
||
segmented, is divided into successive "proceedings," sinks into
|
||
black holes, or even ends up in a generalized black hole (catastro-
|
||
phe). This is the case of the regime of subjective signs, with its
|
||
passional and consciousness-related D, which is positive but only in
|
||
CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES D 509
|
||
|
||
a relative sense. It will be noted immediately that these two major
|
||
forms of D are not in a simple evolutionary relation to each other:
|
||
the second may break away from the first, or it may lead into it (nota-
|
||
bly when the segmentations of converging lines of flight bring an
|
||
overall reterritorialization or one benefiting a particular segment,
|
||
thus arresting the movement of escape). There are all kinds of mixed
|
||
figures, assuming highly varied forms of D.
|
||
Is there absolute D, and what does "absolute" mean? We must
|
||
first have a better understanding of the relations between D, the
|
||
territory, reterritorialization, and the earth. To begin with, the terri-
|
||
tory itself is inseparable from vectors of deterritorialization work-
|
||
9 ing it from within: either because the territoriality is supple and
|
||
and "marginal," in other words, itinerant, or because the territorial
|
||
13 assemblage itself opens onto and is carried off by other types of
|
||
11 assemblages. Second, D is in turn inseparable from correlative
|
||
reterritorializations. D is never simple, but always multiple and
|
||
composite: not only because it participates in various forms at the
|
||
same time, but also because it converges distinct speeds and move-
|
||
ments on the basis of which one may assign at a given moment a
|
||
"deterritorialized element" and a "deterritorializing element."
|
||
Now, reterritorialization as an original operation does not express a
|
||
return to the territory, but rather these differential relations inter-
|
||
7 nal to D itself, this multiplicity internal to the line of flight (cf. "The-
|
||
and orems of D"). Finally, the earth is not at all the opposite of D: This
|
||
10 can already be seen in the mystery of the "natal," in which the earth
|
||
as ardent, eccentric, or intense focal point is outside the territory
|
||
11 and exists only in the movement of D. More than that, the earth, the
|
||
glacial, is Deterritorialization par excellence: that is why it belongs
|
||
3 to the Cosmos, and presents itself as the material through which
|
||
human beings tap cosmic forces. We could say that the earth, as
|
||
deterritorialized, is itself the strict correlate of D. To the point that
|
||
D can be called the creator of the earth—of a new land, a universe,
|
||
not just a reterritorialization.
|
||
This is the meaning of "absolute." The absolute expresses nothing
|
||
transcendent or undifferentiated. It does not even express a quantity
|
||
that would exceed all given (relative) quantities. It expresses only a
|
||
type of movement qualitatively different from relative movement. A
|
||
movement is absolute when, whatever its quantity and speed, it
|
||
7 relates "a" body considered as multiple to a smooth space that it
|
||
and occupies in the manner of a vortex. A movement is relative, whatever
|
||
14 its quantity and speed, when it relates a body considered as One to a
|
||
striated space through which it moves, and which it measures with
|
||
510 D CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES
|
||
|
||
straight lines, if only virtual. D is negative or relative (yet already
|
||
effective) when it conforms to the second case and operates either by
|
||
principal reterritorializations that obstruct the lines of flight, or by
|
||
secondary reterritorializations that segment and work to curtail
|
||
them. D is absolute when it conforms to the first case and brings
|
||
about the creation of a new earth, in other words, when it connects
|
||
lines of flight, raises them to the power of an abstract vital line, or
|
||
draws a plane of consistency. Now what complicates everything is
|
||
that this absolute D necessarily proceeds by way of relative D, pre-
|
||
cisely because it is not transcendent. Conversely, relative or negative
|
||
D itself requires an absolute for its operation: it makes the absolute
|
||
something "encompassing," something totalizing that overcodes the
|
||
earth and then conjugates lines of flight in order to stop them, destroy
|
||
them—rather than connecting them in order to create (it is in this
|
||
sense that we have opposed conjunction to connection, although we
|
||
have often treated them as synonyms from a very general point of
|
||
view). Thus there is a limitative absolute already at work in properly
|
||
9 negative, or even relative, D's. Above all, at this turning point the
|
||
and lines of flight are not only obstructed or segmented but turn into lines
|
||
14 of destruction or death. For the stakes here are indeed the negative
|
||
and the positive in the absolute: the earth girded, encompassed,
|
||
11 overcoded, conjugated as the object of a mortuary and suicidal
|
||
organization surrounding it on all sides, or the earth consolidated,
|
||
connected with the Cosmos, brought into the Cosmos following lines
|
||
of creation that cut across it as so many becomings (Nietzsche's
|
||
expression: Let the earth become lightness . . .). There are thus at
|
||
least four forms of D that confront and combine, and must be distin-
|
||
guished from one another following concrete rules.
|
||
|
||
M
|
||
|
||
Abstract Machines (Diagram and Phylum)
|
||
There is no abstract machine, or machines, in the sense of a Platonic
|
||
Idea, transcendent, universal, eternal. Abstract machines operate
|
||
within concrete assemblages: They are defined by the fourth aspect of
|
||
assemblages, in other words, the cutting edges of decoding and
|
||
11 deterritorialization. They draw these cutting edges. Therefore they
|
||
make the territorial assemblage open onto something else, assem-
|
||
blages of another type, the molecular, the cosmic; they constitute
|
||
becomings. Thus they are always singular and immanent. Contrary to
|
||
the strata, and the assemblages considered under their other aspects,
|
||
CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES D 511
|
||
|
||
abstract machines know nothing of forms and substances. This is
|
||
what makes them abstract, and also defines the concept of the
|
||
machine in the strict sense. They surpass any kind of mechanics.
|
||
They are opposed to the abstract in the ordinary sense. Abstract
|
||
machines consist of unformed matters and nonformal functions.
|
||
Every abstract machine is a consolidated aggregate of matters-
|
||
5 functions (phylum and diagram). This is evident on a technological
|
||
"plane": such a plane is not made up simply of formed substances
|
||
(aluminum, plastic, electric wire, etc.) or organizing forms (program,
|
||
prototypes, etc.), but of a composite of unformed matters exhibiting
|
||
only degrees of intensity (resistance, conductivity, heating, stretch-
|
||
ing, speed or delay, induction, transduction . . .) and diagrammatic
|
||
functions exhibiting only differential equations or, more generally,
|
||
"tensors." Of course, within the dimensions of the assemblage, the
|
||
abstract machine, or machines, is effectuated in forms and sub-
|
||
stances, in varying states of freedom. But the abstract machine must
|
||
first have composed itself, and have simultaneously composed a
|
||
plane of consistency. Abstract, singular, and creative, here and now,
|
||
real yet nonconcrete, actual yet noneffectuated—that is why abstract
|
||
machines are dated and named (the Einstein abstract machine, the
|
||
Webern abstract machine, but also the Galileo, the Bach, or the
|
||
Beethoven, etc.). Not that they refer to people or to effectuating
|
||
moments; on the contrary, it is the names and dates that refer to the
|
||
singularities of the machines, and to what they effectuate.
|
||
But if abstract machines know nothing of form and substance,
|
||
what happens to the other determination of strata, or even of
|
||
assemblages—content and expression? In a certain sense, it could be
|
||
said that this distinction is also irrelevant to the abstract machine,
|
||
3 precisely because it no longer has the forms and substances the dis-
|
||
tinction requires. The plane of consistency is a plane of continuous
|
||
variation; each abstract machine can be considered a "plateau" of
|
||
variation that places variables of content and expression in continu-
|
||
ity. Content and expression thus attain their highest level of relativ-
|
||
ity, becoming "functives of one and the same function" or materials
|
||
of a single matter [see 4, "November 20, 1923: Postulates of Linguis-
|
||
tics," note 21—Trans.]. But in another sense, it could be said that the
|
||
4 distinction subsists, and is even recreated, on the level of traits: there
|
||
and are traits of content (unformed matters or intensities) and traits of
|
||
5 expression (nonformal functions or tensors). Here, the distinction
|
||
has become entirely displaced, or even a different distinction, since it
|
||
now concerns cutting edges of deterritorialization. Absolute deter-
|
||
ritorialization implies a "deterritorializing element" and a "deterri-
|
||
512 D CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES
|
||
|
||
torialized element," one of which in each case is allocated to expres-
|
||
sion, the other to content, or vice versa, but always in such a way as to
|
||
convey a relative distinction between the two. Thus both content and
|
||
expression are necessarily affected by continuous variation, but it
|
||
still assigns them two dissymmetrical roles as elements of a single
|
||
becoming, or as quanta of a single flow. That is why it is impossible to
|
||
define a continuous variation that would not take in both the content
|
||
and the expression, rendering them indiscernible, while simultane-
|
||
ously proceeding by one or the other, determining the two mobile and
|
||
relative poles of that which has become indiscernible. For this reason,
|
||
one must define both traits or intensities of content and traits or ten-
|
||
1, 2 sors of expression (indefinite article, proper name, infinitive, and
|
||
4, 10 date), which take turns leading one another across the plane of con-
|
||
sistency. Unformed matter, the phylum, is not dead, brute, homo-
|
||
12 geneous matter, but a matter-movement bearing singularities or
|
||
haecceities, qualities, and even operations (itinerant technological
|
||
lineages); and the nonformal function, the diagram, is not an in-
|
||
expressive metalanguage lacking a syntax, but an expressivity-
|
||
movement always bearing a foreign tongue within each language and
|
||
4 nonlinguistic categories within language as a whole (nomad poetic
|
||
lineages). One writes, then, on the same level as the real of an
|
||
unformed matter, at the same time as that matter traverses and
|
||
extends all of nonformal language: a becoming-animal like Kafka's
|
||
10 mouse [p. 243], Hofmannsthal's rats [p. 240], Moritz's calves [p.
|
||
240]? A revolutionary machine, all the more abstract for being real. A
|
||
regime that no longer operates by the signifier or the subjective.
|
||
That covers singular and immanent abstract machines. What we
|
||
have said does not preclude the possibility of "the" abstract machine
|
||
serving as a transcendent model, under very particular conditions.
|
||
This time the concrete assemblages are related to an abstract idea of
|
||
the Machine and, depending on how they effectuate it, are assigned
|
||
coefficients taking into account their potentialities, their creativity.
|
||
The coefficients that "quantify" assemblages bear on the varying
|
||
assemblage components (territory, deterritorialization, reterritori-
|
||
alization, earth, Cosmos), the various entangled lines constituting
|
||
the "map" of an assemblage (molar lines, molecular lines, lines of
|
||
flight), and the different relations-between the assemblage and the
|
||
plane of consistency (phylum and diagram). For example, the "grass
|
||
stem" component may have different coefficients in assemblages of
|
||
11 animal species that are nevertheless closely related [p. 324-25]. As a
|
||
general rule, an assemblage is all the closer to the abstract machine
|
||
the more lines without contour passing between things it has, and the
|
||
CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES D 513
|
||
|
||
4 more it enjoys a power of metamorphosis (transformation and trans-
|
||
and substantiation) corresponding to the matter-function: cf. The Waves
|
||
10 machine [p. 252].
|
||
We have considered in particular two great alloplastic and anthro-
|
||
pomorphic assemblages, the war machine and the State apparatus.
|
||
These two assemblages not only differ in nature but are quantifiable
|
||
in relation to "the" abstract machine in different ways. They do not
|
||
have the same relation to the phylum, the diagram; they do not have
|
||
the same lines, or the same components. This analysis of the two
|
||
12 assemblages and their coefficients demonstrates that the war ma-
|
||
and chine does not in itself have warfor its object, but necessarily adopts it
|
||
13 as its object when it allows itself to be appropriated by the State appa-
|
||
ratus. At this very precise point, the line of flight and the abstract vital
|
||
line it effectuates turn into a line of death and destruction. Hence the
|
||
name war "machine," which is much closer to the abstract machine
|
||
than is the State apparatus, which divests the war machine of its
|
||
power of metamorphosis. Writing and music can be war machines.
|
||
The more an assemblage opens and multiplies connections and draws
|
||
a plane of consistency with its quantifiers of intensities and of consol-
|
||
1, 4 idation, the closer it is to the living abstract machine. But it strays
|
||
5, 9 from it to the extent that it replaces creative connections with con-
|
||
12 junctions causing blockages (axiomatics), organizations forming
|
||
and strata (stratometers), reterritorializations forming black holes
|
||
14 (segmentometers), and conversions into lines of death (deleometers).
|
||
Thus there is a whole process of selection of assemblages according to
|
||
their ability to draw a plane of consistency with an increasing number
|
||
of connections. Schizoanalysis is not only a qualitative analysis of
|
||
abstract machines in relation to the assemblages, but also a quantita-
|
||
tive analysis of the assemblages in relation to a presumably pure
|
||
abstract machine.
|
||
There is one last point of view, that of typological analysis. For
|
||
there exist general types of abstract machines. The abstract machine
|
||
or machines of the plane of consistency do not exhaust or dominate
|
||
the entirety of the operations that constitute the strata and even the
|
||
assemblages. The strata "take" on the plane of consistency itself,
|
||
forming areas of thickening, coagulations, and belts organized and
|
||
developing along the axes of another plane (substance-form, content-
|
||
3 expression). This means that each stratum has a unity of consistency
|
||
or of composition relating above all to substantial elements and for-
|
||
mal traits, and testifying to the existence of a properly stratic abstract
|
||
machine presiding over this other plane. And there is a third type: on
|
||
the alloplastic strata, which are particularly propitious for the assem-
|
||
514 D CONCLUSION: CONCRETE RULES AND ABSTRACT MACHINES
|
||
|
||
blages, there arise abstract machines that compensate for deterritori-
|
||
9 alizations with reterritorializations, and especially for decodings
|
||
with overcodings or overcoding equivalents. We have seen in particu-
|
||
lar that if abstract machines open assemblages they also close them.
|
||
4, 7 An order-word machine overcodes language, a faciality machine
|
||
and overcodes the body and even the head, a machine of enslavement
|
||
8 overcodes or axiomatizes the earth: these are in no way illusions, but
|
||
real machinic effects. We can no longer place the assemblages on a
|
||
quantitative scale measuring how close or far they are from the plane
|
||
of consistency. There are different types of abstract machines that
|
||
overlap in their operations and qualify the assemblages: abstract
|
||
machines of consistency, singular and mutant, with multiplied con-
|
||
nections; abstract machines of stratification that surround the plane
|
||
5 of consistency with another plane; and axiomatic or overcoding
|
||
and abstract machines that perform totalizations, homogenizations, con-
|
||
13 junctions of closure. Every abstract machine is linked to other
|
||
abstract machines, not only because they are inseparably political,
|
||
economic, scientific, artistic, ecological, cosmic—perceptive, affec-
|
||
tive, active, thinking, physical, and semiotic—but because their vari-
|
||
ous types are as intertwined as their operations are convergent.
|
||
Mechanosphere.
|
||
Notes
|
||
This page intentionally left blank
|
||
Notes
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Translator's Foreword
|
||
1. Gilles Deleuze, in Deleuze and Claire Parnet, Dialogues (Paris: Flammarion, 1977;
|
||
forthcoming from University of Minnesota Press), p. 10.
|
||
2. Gilles Deleuze, interview with Catherine Clement, L'Arc, no. 49 (revised ed., 1980),
|
||
p. 99.
|
||
3. Gilles Deleuze, "Nomad Thought," in The New Nietzsche, ed. Donald B. Allison
|
||
(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1985), p. 148. Semiotext(e), Nietzsche's Return 3,1 (1978),
|
||
p. 20.
|
||
4. Deleuze and Parnet, Dialogues, p. 20. On the relationship between philosophy and
|
||
the State, see also pp. 351-473 of the present work. Deleuze develops an extended critique of
|
||
rationalist philosophy in Difference et repetition (Paris: PUF, 1968); see especially, "L'Image
|
||
de la pensee," pp. 169-217.
|
||
5. Deleuze, "I Have Nothing to Admit," trans. Janis Forman, Semiotext(e), Anti-
|
||
Oedipus 2, 3 (1977), p. 12 (translation modified).
|
||
6. "What I detested more than anything else was Hegelianism and the Dialectic" (ibid).
|
||
7. Ibid.
|
||
8. See Deleuze's discussion with Michel Foucault, "Intellectuals and Power," in
|
||
Foucault, Language, Counter-Memory, Practice, ed. Donald Bouchard (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell
|
||
University Press, 1977), pp. 205-217.
|
||
9. Deleuze, "I Have Nothing to Admit," p. 113.
|
||
10. Felix Guattari, "Sur les rapports infirmiers-medecins" (1955), in Psychanalyse et
|
||
transversalite (Paris: Maspero, 1972), p. 11.
|
||
11. Guattari, Psychanalyse et transversalite, pp. 40, 173n, 288-289. The journal Re-
|
||
cherches, of which Guattari was an editor, was the mouthpiece of the institutional analysis
|
||
movement.
|
||
12. Uneasy because Guattari believed that Laing's communitarian solution reconsti-
|
||
tuted an extended Oedipal family (La Revolution moleculaire, [Paris: Editions Recherches,
|
||
517
|
||
518 D NOTES TO PP. xi-10
|
||
|
||
1977], p. 121), and because he was critical of Basaglia's assimilation of mental illness and
|
||
social alienation and his rejection of any kind of institutions for the insane (Psychanalyse et
|
||
transversalite, p. 264).
|
||
13. In 1973, Guattari was tried and fined for committing an "outrage to public decency"
|
||
by publishing an issue ofRecherches on homosexuality. All copies were ordered destroyed (La
|
||
Revolution moleculaire, p. 1 lOn).
|
||
14. Anti-Oedipus, trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane (Minneapolis:
|
||
University of Minnesota Press, 1983).
|
||
15. La Revolution moleculaire, p. 144. The disintegration of the Left into dogmatic
|
||
"groupuscules" and the amoeba-like proliferation of Lacanian schools based on personality
|
||
cults confirmed the charge of bureaucratism but belied the potency of the mix. Guattari him-
|
||
self began his political life in the early 1950s with stormy attempts at membership in two
|
||
Trotskyist splinter parties (Psychanalyse et transversalite, pp. 268-271).
|
||
16. Differenced repetition, pp. 49-55, 337-349.
|
||
17. Jean-Francois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, trans.
|
||
Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984),
|
||
pp. 32-33.
|
||
18. Jurgen Habermas's notion of "consensus" is the updated, late-modern version.
|
||
19. Interview with Gilles Deleuze, Liberation, October 23, 1980, p. 16.
|
||
20. See Foucault's essay on Blanchot, often quoted by Deleuze: "The Thought from Out-
|
||
side," in Foucault/Blanchot, trans. Brian Massumi, Maurice Blanchot, and Michel Foucault
|
||
(New York: Zone Books, 1987).
|
||
21. Deleuze's books on cinema (Cinema I: The Movement-Image [Minneapolis: Univer-
|
||
sity of Minnesota Press, 1986], and Cinema II: The Time-Image [forthcoming from Univer-
|
||
sity of Minnesota Press]) and on painting (Francis Bacon: Logique de la sensation [Paris: Ed.
|
||
de la Difference, 1981 ]) are not meant as exercises in philosophical expansionism. Their proj-
|
||
ect is not to bring these arts to philosophy, but to bring out the philosophy already in them.
|
||
22. The terms "smooth space" and "striated space" were in fact coined by Pierre Boulez.
|
||
See p. 361-62 of the present work and note 20.
|
||
23. Interview with Gilles Deleuze, Liberation, October 23, 1980, p. 17.
|
||
24. See page 158 of the present work and note.
|
||
25. On style in literature, see Deleuze, Proust and Signs, trans. Richard Howard (New
|
||
York: Braziller, 1972), pp. 142-150.
|
||
26. Deleuze and Foucault, "Intellectuals and Power," p. 208.
|
||
|
||
1. Introduction: Rhizome
|
||
1. [TRANS: U. Weinreich, W. Labov, and M. Herzog, "Empirical Foundations for a The-
|
||
ory of Language," in W. Lehmann and Y. Malkeiel, eds., Directions for Historical Linguistics
|
||
(1968), p. 125; cited by Francoise Robert, "Aspects sociaux du changement dans une
|
||
grammaire generative," Langages, no. 32 (December 1973), p. 90.]
|
||
2. Bertil Malmberg, New Trends in Linguistics, trans. Edward Garners (Stockholm:
|
||
Lund, 1964), pp. 65-67 (the example of the Castilian dialect).
|
||
3. Ernst Jiinger, Approches; drogues et ivresse (Paris: Table Ronde, 1974), p. 304,
|
||
sec. 218.
|
||
4. Remy Chauvin in Entretiens sur la sexualite, ed. Max Aron, Robert Courrier, and
|
||
Etienne Wolff (Paris: Plon, 1969), p. 205.
|
||
5. On the work of R. E. Benveniste and G. J. Todaro, see Yves Christen, "Le role des
|
||
virus dans 1'evolution," La Recherche, no. 54 (March 1975): "After integration-extraction in a
|
||
cell, viruses may, due to an error in excision, carry off fragments of their host's DNA and
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 10-17 D 519
|
||
|
||
transmit them to new cells: this in fact is the basis for what we call 'genetic engineering.' As a
|
||
result, the genetic information of one organism may be transferred to another by means of
|
||
viruses. We could even imagine an extreme case where this transfer of information would go
|
||
from a more highly evolved species to one that is less evolved or was the progenitor of the more
|
||
evolved species. This mechanism, then, would run in the opposite direction to evolution in
|
||
the classical sense. If it turns out that this kind of transferral of information has played a major
|
||
role, we would in certain cases have to substitute reticular schemas (with communications
|
||
between branches after they have become differentiated) for the bush or tree schemas currently
|
||
used to represent evolution" (p. 271).
|
||
6. Francois Jacob, The Logic of Life, trans. Betty E. Spillmann (New York: Pantheon,
|
||
1973), pp. 291-292, 311 (quote).
|
||
7. Carlos Castaneda, The Teachings of Don Juan (Berkeley: University of California
|
||
Press, 1971), p. 88.
|
||
8. Pierre Boulez, Conversations with CelestinDeIiege(London: Eulenberg Books, 1976):
|
||
"a seed which you plant in compost, and suddenly it begins to proliferate like a weed" (p. 15);
|
||
and on musical proliferation: "a music that floats, and in which the writing itself makes it
|
||
impossible for the performer to keep in with a pulsed time" (p. 69 [translation modified]).
|
||
9. See Melanie Klein, Narrative of a Child Analysis (London: Hogarth Press, 1961): the
|
||
role of war maps in Richard's activities. [TRANS: Deleuze and Guattari, with Claire Parnet and
|
||
Andre Scala, analyze Klein's Richard and Freud's Little Hans in "The Interpretation of
|
||
Utterances," in Language, Sexuality and Subversion, trans. Paul Foss and Meaghan Morris
|
||
(Sydney: Feral Publications, 1978), pp. 141-157.]
|
||
10. Fernand Deligny, Cahiers de I'immuable, vol. 1, Voix et voir, Recherches, no. 8
|
||
(April 1975).
|
||
11. See Dieter Wunderlich, "Pragmatique, situation d'enonciation et Deixis," in
|
||
Langages, no. 26 (June 1972), pp. 50ff.: MacCawley, Sadock, and Wunderlich's attempts to
|
||
integrate "pragmatic properties" into Chomskian trees.
|
||
12. Steven Rose, The Conscious Brain (New York: Knopf, 1975), p. 76; on memory, see
|
||
pp. 185-219.
|
||
13. See Julien Pacotte, Le reseau arborescent, scheme primordial de la pensee (Paris:
|
||
Hermann, 1936). This book analyzes and develops various schemas of the arborescent form,
|
||
which is presented not as a mere formalism but as the "real foundation of formal thought." It
|
||
follows classical thought through to the end. It presents all of the forms of the "One-Two," the
|
||
theory of the dipole. The set, trunk-roots-branches, yields the following schema:
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
More recently, Michel Serres has analyzed varieties and sequences of trees in the most diverse
|
||
scientific domains: how a tree is formed on the basis of a "network." La traduction (Paris:
|
||
Minuit, 1974), pp. 27ff.; Feux et signaux de brume (Paris: Grasset, 1975), pp. 35ff.
|
||
14. Pierre Rosenstiehl and Jean Petitot, "Automate asocial et systemes acentres," Com-
|
||
munications, no. 22 (1974), pp. 45-62. On the friendship theorem, see Herbert S. Wilf, The
|
||
Friendship Theorem in Combinatorial Mathematics (Welsh Academic Press); and on a simi-
|
||
lar kind of theorem, called the theorem of group indecision, see Kenneth J. Arrow, Social
|
||
Choice and Individual Values (New York: Wiley, 1963).
|
||
15. Rosenstiehl and Petitot, "Automate asocial." The principal characteristic of the
|
||
acentered system is that local initiatives are coordinated independently of a central power,
|
||
520 D NOTES TO PP. 17-24
|
||
|
||
with the calculations made throughout the network (multiplicity). "That is why the only place
|
||
files on people can be kept is right in each person's home, since they alone are capable of filling
|
||
in the description and keeping it up to date: society itself is the only possible data bank on peo-
|
||
ple. A naturally acentered society rejects the centralizing automaton as an asocial intrusion"
|
||
(p. 62). On the "Firing Squad Theorem," see pp. 51-57. It even happens that generals, dream-
|
||
ing of appropriating the formal techniques of guerrilla warfare, appeal to multiplicities "of
|
||
synchronous modules ... based on numerous but independent lightweight cells" having in
|
||
theory only a minimum of central power and "hierarchical relaying"; see Guy Brossollet,
|
||
Essai surla non-bataille (Paris: Belin, 1975).
|
||
16. On Western agriculture of grain plants and Eastern horticulture of tubers, the opposi-
|
||
tion between sowing of seeds and replanting of offshoots, and the contrast to animal raising,
|
||
see Andre Haudricourt, "Domestication des animaux, culture des plantes et traitement
|
||
d'autrui," L'Homme, vol. 2, no. 1 (January-April 1962), pp. 40-50, and "Nature et culture
|
||
dans la civilisation de 1'igname: 1'origine des clones et des clans," L'Homme, vol. 4, no. 1
|
||
(January-April 1964), pp. 93-104. Maize and rice are no exception: they are cereals "adopted
|
||
at a late date by tuber cultivators" and were treated in a similar fashion; it is probable that rice
|
||
"first appeared as a weed in taro ditches."
|
||
17. Henry Miller, in Henry Miller and Michael Fraenkel, Hamlet (New York: Carrefour,
|
||
1939), pp. 105-106.
|
||
18. See Leslie Fiedler, The Return of the Vanishing American (New York: Stein and Day,
|
||
1968). This book contains a fine analysis of geography and its role in American mythology
|
||
and literature, and of the reversal of directions. In the East, there was the search for a specifi-
|
||
cally American code and for a receding with Europe (Henry James, Eliot, Pound, etc.); in the
|
||
South, there was the overcoding of the slave system, with its ruin and the ruin of the planta-
|
||
tions during the Civil War (Faulkner, Caldwell); from the North came capitalist decoding
|
||
(Dos Passes, Dreiser); the West, however, played the role of a line of flight combining travel,
|
||
hallucination, madness, the Indians, perceptive and mental experimentation, the shifting of
|
||
frontiers, the rhizome (Ken Kesey and his "fog machine," the beat generation, etc.). Every
|
||
great American author creates a cartography, even in his or her style; in contrast to what is
|
||
done in Europe, each makes a map that is directly connected to the real social movements
|
||
crossing America. An example is the indexing of geographical directions throughout the work
|
||
of Fitzgerald.
|
||
19. [TRANS: Karl Wittfogel, Oriental Despotism (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University
|
||
Press, 1957).]
|
||
20. Gregory Bateson, Steps to an Ecology of Mind (New York: Ballantine Books, 1972), p.
|
||
113. It will be noted that the word "plateau" is used in classical studies of bulbs, tubers, and
|
||
rhizomes; see the entry for "Bulb" in M. H. Baillon, Dictionnaire de botanique (Paris:
|
||
Hachette, 1876-1892).
|
||
21. For example, Joe'lle de La Casiniere, Absolument necessaire. The Emergency Book
|
||
(Paris: Minuit, 1973), a truly nomadic book. In the same vein, see the research in progress at
|
||
the Montfaucon Research Center.
|
||
22. The Diaries of Franz Kafka, ed. Max Brod, trans. Joseph Kresh (New York: Schocken,
|
||
1948), p. 12.
|
||
23. Marcel Schwob, The Children's Crusade, trans. Henry Copley (Boston: Small,
|
||
Maynard, 1898); JersyAndrzejewski,Lesp0rtesdwparafife(Paris:Gallimard, 1959);Armand
|
||
Farrachi, La dislocation (Paris: Stock, 1974). It was in the context of Schwob's book that Paul
|
||
Alphandery remarked that literature, in certain cases, could revitalize history and impose
|
||
upon it "genuine research directions"; La chretiente et I'idee de croisade (Paris: Albin Michel,
|
||
1959), vol. 2, p. 116.
|
||
24. See Paul Virilio, "Vehiculaire," in Nomades et vagabonds, ed. Jacques Bergue (Paris:
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 24-47 D 521
|
||
|
||
Union Generale d'Editions, 1975), p. 43, on the appearance of linearity and the disruption of
|
||
perception by speed.
|
||
25. See Jean-Cristophe Bailly's description of movement in German Romanticism, in his
|
||
introduction to La legende dispers'ee. Anthologie du romantisme allemand (Paris: Union
|
||
Generale d'Editions, 1976), pp. 18ff.
|
||
|
||
2.1914: One or Several Wolves?
|
||
1. Sigmund Freud, Papers on Metapsychology, vol. 14, Standard Edition, trans. James
|
||
Strachey (London: Hogarth Press, 1957), p. 200.
|
||
2. [TRANS: Virginia Woolf, Mrs. Dalloway (New York: Harcourt, Brace and World,
|
||
1925), p. 11).]
|
||
3. E. A. Bennet, What Jung Really Said (New York: Schocken, 1967), p. 74.
|
||
4. Ruth Mack Brunswick, "A Supplement to Freud's History of an Infantile Neurosis,"
|
||
in The Wolf-Man, ed. Muriel Gardiner (New York: Basic Books, 1971), p. 268.
|
||
5. Elias Canetti, Crowds and Power, trans. Carol Stewart (New York: Viking Press, 1963),
|
||
pp. 29-30, 93ff. Some of the distinctions mentioned here are noted by Canetti.
|
||
6. [TRANS: Ibid., p. 93.]
|
||
7. Letter cited by Roland Jaccard, L'homme aux loups (Paris: Ed. Universitaires, 1973),
|
||
p. 113.
|
||
|
||
3.10,000 B.C.: The Geology of Morals
|
||
1. Roland Omnes, L'univers et ses metamorphoses (Paris: Hermann, 1973), p. 164: "A
|
||
star that has collapsed so far that its radius has fallen below the critical point becomes what is
|
||
called a black hole (an occluded star). This expression means that nothing sent in the direction
|
||
of such an object will ever come back. It is therefore perfectly black since it does not emit or
|
||
reflect any light."
|
||
2. Marcel Griaule, Dieu d'eau (Paris: Fayard, 1975), pp. 38-41.
|
||
3. For a general treatment of the two aspects of morphogenesis, see Raymod Ruyer, La
|
||
genese de formes vivantes (Paris: Flammarion, 1958), pp. 54ff., and Pierre Vendryes, Vie et
|
||
probabilite (Paris: Albin Michel, 1945). Vendryes analyzes the role of the articulatory relation
|
||
and articulated systems. On the two structural aspects of protein, see Jacques Monod, Chance
|
||
and Necessity, trans. Austryn Wainhouse (New York: Vintage, 1972), pp. 90-95.
|
||
4. Francois Jacob, The Logic of Life, trans. Betty E. Spillman (New York: Pantheon,
|
||
1973), pp. 269-270 [translation modified].
|
||
5. Francois Jacob, "Lemodelelinguistique en biologie/'Cri^He, no. 322 (March 1974),
|
||
p. 202: "Genetic material has two roles: it must be reproduced in order to be transmitted to
|
||
the following generation, and it must be expressed in order for it to determine the organism's
|
||
structures and functions."
|
||
6. Louis Hjelmslev, Prolegomena to a Theory of Language, trans. Francis J. Whitfield
|
||
(Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1969), p. 60.
|
||
7. See Geoffrey Saint-Hilaire, Principes de philosophic zoologique (Paris: Picton et
|
||
Didier, 1830), which quotes extracts from the debate with Cuvier; and Notions synth'e-
|
||
tiques, historiques et physiologiques de philosophic naturelle (Paris: Denain, 1838), in
|
||
which Geoffroy sets forth his molecular conception of combustion, electrification, and
|
||
attraction. Karl Ernest von Baer, Uber Entwicklungsgeschichte der Thiere (Konigsberg:
|
||
Beiden Gehrudern Borntrager, 1828-88), and "Biographic de Cuvier," inAnnales des sci-
|
||
ences naturelles (1908). Vialleton, Membres et ceintures des vertebr'es t'etrapodes (Paris:
|
||
Doin, 1924).
|
||
522 D NOTES TO PP. 48-62
|
||
|
||
8. Edmond Perrier deserves a place, although not a decisive one, in this long history.
|
||
He returned to the problem of unity of composition, updating the work of Geoffrey with
|
||
the aid of Darwin, and especially Lamarck. Perrier's entire work is organized around two
|
||
themes: animal colonies or multiplicities, and the speeds necessary to account for het-
|
||
erodox degrees and foldings ("tachygenesis"). For example, the brain of a vertebrate may
|
||
come to occupy the position of the mouth of an annelid, in the "fight between the mouth
|
||
and the brain." See Les colonies animates et la formation des organismes (Paris: G. Mas-
|
||
son, 1881), and "L'origine des embranchements du regne animal," Scienta (May-June
|
||
1918). Perrier wrote a history entitled Philosophic zoologique avant Darwin (Paris: Alcan,
|
||
1884), which includes excellent chapters on Geoffroy and Cuvier.
|
||
9. Georges Canguilhem et al., "Du developpement a 1'evolution au XIXe siecle," Thales
|
||
(1960), p. 34.
|
||
10. George Gaylord Simpson, The Meaning of Evolution (New Haven, Conn.: Yale Uni-
|
||
versity Press, 1950).
|
||
11. Gilbert Simondon, L'individu et sa gen'ese physico-biologique(Paris: PUF, 1964). On
|
||
the interior and exterior in the crystal and the organism, and on the role of the limit or mem-
|
||
brane, see pp. 107-114 and 259-264.
|
||
12. J. H. Rush, The Dawn of Life (Garden City, N.Y.: Hanover House, 1957), p. 165:
|
||
"Primitive organisms lived, in some sense, in a state of suffocation. Life had been born, but it
|
||
had not yet begun to breathe."
|
||
13. Jakob Johann von Uexkiill, Mondes animaux et monde humain (Paris: Gonthier, 1965).
|
||
14. See Pia Laviosa-Zambotti, Origini e diffusione della civilita (Milan: C. Marzorati,
|
||
1947): her use of the notions of strata, substratum, and parastratum (although she does not
|
||
define the last.)
|
||
15. Jacob, The Logic of Life, pp. 290-292, 310-312, and what Remy Chauvin calls
|
||
"aparallel evolution."
|
||
16. See Laviosa-Zambotti, Origini: her conception of waves and flows from center to
|
||
periphery, and of nomadism and migrations (nomadic flows).
|
||
17. On phenomena of resonance between different orders of magnitude, see Simondon,
|
||
L 'individu, pp. 16-20, 124-131, and passim.
|
||
18. Claude Popelin, Le taureau et son combat (Paris: Julliard, 1981): see chapter 4 on the
|
||
problem of human and bull territories inside the arena.
|
||
19. See Simondon, L'individu, on orders of magnitude and the establishment of reso-
|
||
nance between them; actions of the "mold," "modulation," and "modeling" types; and exte-
|
||
rior forces and intermediate states.
|
||
20. Obviously there is a multiplicity of sequences or lines. But that does not preclude the
|
||
"order of order" being unilinear (see Jacob, The Logic of Life, p. 286, and "Le modele
|
||
linguistique en biologie," pp. 199-203).
|
||
21. On the respective independence of proteins and nucleic acids, and their reciprocal
|
||
presupposition, see Jacob, The Logic of Life, pp. 304-306, and Jacques Monod, Chance and
|
||
Necessity, pp. 96-98, 107-109, 114-115, and 142-144.
|
||
22. On the notion of transduction, see Simondon, L'individu, pp. 18-21 (however, he
|
||
takes the word in its most general sense and uses it to refer to the entire system). On the mem-
|
||
brane, see pp. 259ff.
|
||
23. Andre Leroi-Gourhan, Le geste et la parole, vol. 1, of Technique et langage (Paris:
|
||
Albin Michel, 1964), p. 161.
|
||
24. On all of these problems (the free hand, the supple larynx, the lips, and the role of the
|
||
steppe as factors of deterritorialization), see Emile Devaux's fine book, Trois problemes:
|
||
I'espece, I'instinct, I'homme (Paris: Le Francois, 1933), part 3 (chapter 7: "The anthropoid,
|
||
severed from the forest, retarded in its development, infantilized, had to acquire free hands
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 62-77 D 523
|
||
|
||
and a supple larynx"; and chapter 9: "The forest made the monkey, the cave and the steppe
|
||
made the human").
|
||
25. Jacob, The Logic of Life, pp. 278,289-290,298. Jacob and Monod sometimes use the
|
||
word "translation" for the genetic code, but only for reasons of convenience. As Monod points
|
||
out, "The code can be translated only by products of translation."
|
||
26. Leroi-Gourhan, Le geste et la parole, pp. 269-275.
|
||
27. [TRANS: A reference to the work of Julia Kristeva. On the chora, see Kristeva, Revolu-
|
||
tion in Poetic Language, trans. Margaret Waller (New York: Columbia University Press,
|
||
1984), pp. 25-30.]
|
||
28. That is why we consider Hjelmslev, despite his own reservations and vacillations, to
|
||
be the only linguist to have actually broken with the signifier and the signified. Many other lin-
|
||
guists seem to make this break deliberately and without reservations, but retain the implicit
|
||
presuppositions of the signifier.
|
||
29. Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New York: Vin-
|
||
tage, 1975). Already in The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New
|
||
York: Pantheon, 1982), Foucault outlines his theory of the two kinds of multiplicities, multi-
|
||
plicities of expression or statements and multiplicities of contents or objects. He shows that
|
||
they are irreducible to the signifier-signified couple. He also explains why the title of one of
|
||
his earlier books, Les mots et les chases [Words and Things, translated as The Order of Things
|
||
(New York: Vintage, 1970)], must be understood negatively (pp. 48-49).
|
||
30. [TRANS: Foucault, The Order of Things, p. 9.]
|
||
31. Simondon, L'individu, pp. 139-141.
|
||
32. H. P. Lovecraft, "Through the Gates of the Silver Key," in The Dream-Quest of
|
||
Unknown Kadath (New York: Ballantine Books, 1970), pp. 168, 217-218.
|
||
|
||
4. November 20,1923: Postulates of Linguistics
|
||
1. [TRANS: Mot d'ordre: in standard French, "slogan," (military) "password." Deleuze
|
||
and Guattari are also using the term literally: "word of order," in the double sense of a word or
|
||
phrase constituting a command and a word or phrase creative of order.]
|
||
2. GeorgesDarien, L'epaulette(Paris: 10/18, l973),p.435.OrZo\a,LaBeteHumaine,
|
||
trans. Leonard Tancock (New York: Penguin, 1977), p. 148: "She was saying this not to con-
|
||
vince him, but solely to warn him that she had to be innocent in the eyes of the world at large."
|
||
This type of phrase seems to us to be much more characteristic of the novel in general than the
|
||
informational phrase, "the marquess went out at five o'clock."
|
||
3. Oswald Spengler, Man and Technics, trans. Charles Francis Atkinson (New York:
|
||
Knopf, 1932), p. 54 [translation modified].
|
||
4. Brice Parain, Sur la dialectique (Paris: Gallimard, 1953). Parain develops a theory of
|
||
"supposition" or the presupposed in language in relation to the orders given to life; but he sees
|
||
this less as a power in the political sense than a duty in the moral sense.
|
||
5. Two authors in particular have brought out the importance of indirect discourse, espe-
|
||
cially in its so-called free form, from the viewpoint of a theory of enunciation that goes beyond
|
||
the traditional categories of linguistics: V. N. Volosinov (for Russian, German, and French),
|
||
Marxism and the Philosophy of Language [attributed to Mikhail Bakhtin in the French edi-
|
||
tion cited by the authors—TRANS], trans. Ladislav Matejka and I. R. Titunik. (Cambridge,
|
||
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986), Part 3, "Toward a History of Forms and Utterance in
|
||
Language Constructions," pp. 109-200; Pier Paolo Pasolini (for Italian), L'experience
|
||
heretique (Paris: Payot, 1976), part 1. We have also referred to an unpublished study by J.-P.
|
||
Bamberger, "Les formes du discours indirect dans le cinema, muet et parlant."
|
||
6. Emile Benveniste, Problems in General Linguistics, trans. Mary Elizabeth Meek
|
||
524 D NOTES TO PP. 77-82
|
||
|
||
(Coral Gables, Fla.: University of Miami Press, 1971), p. 53: "There is no indication, for
|
||
example, that a bee goes off to another hive with the message it has received in its own hive.
|
||
This would constitute a kind of transmission or relay."
|
||
7. William Labov has clearly shown the contradiction, or at least paradox, created by the
|
||
distinction between language and speech: language is defined as the "social part" of language,
|
||
and speech is consigned to individual variations; but since the social part is self-enclosed, it
|
||
necessarily follows that a single individual would be enough to illustrate the principles of lan-
|
||
guage, without reference to any outside data, whereas speech could only be studied in a social
|
||
context. The same paradox recurs from Saussure to Chomsky: "The social aspect of language
|
||
is studied by observing any one individual, but the individual aspect only by observing lan-
|
||
guage in its social context"; Labov, SociolinguisticPatterns (Philadelphia: University of Penn-
|
||
sylvania Press, 1972), p. 186.
|
||
8. Benveniste, Problems in General Linguistics, part 4 ("Man and Language"); on the
|
||
elimination of the illocutionary, see pp. 237-238.
|
||
9. Oswald Ducrot, Dire et nepas dire (Paris: Hermann, 1972), pp. 70-80, and "De Saus-
|
||
sure a la philosophic du langage," preface to the French translation of S. R. Searle's Speech
|
||
Acts, Actes de langage (Paris: Hermann, 1972). Ducrot challenges the notions of linguistic
|
||
information and code, and communication and subjectivity. He develops a theory of "linguis-
|
||
tic presupposition" or nondiscursive implicitness, as opposed to concluded and discursive
|
||
implicitness still referring to a code. He constructs a pragmatics covering all of linguistics and
|
||
moves toward a study of assemblages of enunciation, considered from a "juridical," "polemi-
|
||
cal," or "political" point of view.
|
||
10. Bakhtin and Labov have stressed the social character of enunciation, in different
|
||
ways. They are consequently in opposition not only to subjectivism but also to structuralism,
|
||
to the extent that the latter ties the system of language to the understanding of an ideal indi-
|
||
vidual, and social factors to actual individuals as speakers.
|
||
11. Ducrot, Dire et nepas dire, p.11'. "To qualify an action as criminal (theft, fraud, black-
|
||
mail, etc.) is not, in our sense of the term, to present it as an act since the legal situation of guilt,
|
||
which defines a crime, is supposed to derive from other given consequences of the activity
|
||
described: the activity is considered punishable because it is harmful to another person, to
|
||
order, to society, etc. The judge's statement of a sentence can, on the other hand, be consid-
|
||
ered a juridical act because there is no intervening effect between the speech of the judge and
|
||
the transformation of the accused into a convict."
|
||
12. John Kenneth Galbraith, Money (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1975), chapter 12, "The
|
||
Ultimate Inflation": "On November 20, 1923, the curtain was rolled down. As in Austria a
|
||
year earlier, the end came suddenly. As with the milder French inflation, the end came with
|
||
astonishing ease. Perhaps it ended simply because it could not go on. On November 20, the
|
||
old reichsmark was declared to be no longer money. A new currency, the rentenmark, was
|
||
introduced . . . . The new rentenmark was declared to be backed by a first mortgage on all the
|
||
land and other physical assets of the Reich. This idea had its ancestry in the assignats; it was,
|
||
however, appreciably more fraudulent [Galbraith means to say 'deterritorialized'—Au.]. In
|
||
France in 1789, there was extant, visible land freshly taken from the church for which cur-
|
||
rency initially could be exchanged; any German seeking to exercise rights of foreclosure on
|
||
German property with his rentenmarks would have been thought mentally unstable. Never-
|
||
theless, it worked. Circumstances helped.... If, after 1923, the previous claims on the Ger-
|
||
man budget had continued—the reparations claims and the cost of passive resistance—
|
||
nothing would have saved the mark and [the head of the Reichsbank's] reputation"; pp. 159,
|
||
161.
|
||
13. Volosinov [Bakhtin], Marxism and the Philosophy of Language, p. 110. And on
|
||
"symbolic relations of force" as variables internal to enunciation, see Pierre Bourdieu,
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 82-91 D 525
|
||
|
||
"L'economie des echanges linguistiques," in Linguistique et sociolinguistlque, Langue
|
||
Francaise, May 1977, pp. 18-21.
|
||
14. The very notion of the proletarian class hinges on the question, Does the proletariat
|
||
already exist at a given moment, and if so as a body? (Or, does it still exist?) It is evident that
|
||
Marxists use it in an anticipatory sense, as, for example, when they speak of an "embryonic
|
||
proletariat."
|
||
15. [TRANS: V. I. Lenin, "On Slogans," Selected Works (Moscow: Progress Publishers,
|
||
1975), vol. 3, p. 148.]
|
||
16. Quoted by David Cooper, The Language of Madness (London: Allen Lane, 1978), p.
|
||
34. Cooper comments that "the language of 'hearing voices' . . . means that one becomes
|
||
aware of something that exceeds the consciousness of normal [i.e., direct] discourse and
|
||
which therefore must be experienced as 'other'" (p. 34).
|
||
17. Elias Canetti is one of the rare authors who has dealt with the psychological mode of
|
||
action of the order-word, or "command": Crowds and Power, trans. Carol Stewart (New
|
||
York: Viking Press, 1963), pp. 303-333. He hypothesizes that an order inflicts a kind of sting
|
||
on the soul, which forms a cyst, a hardening that never goes away. When this happens, the
|
||
only way to find relief is to pass it on to others as quickly as possible, to "massify," even
|
||
though the mass may turn back against the emitter of the order-word. In addition, the fact
|
||
that the order-word is like a foreign body within the body, an indirect discourse within
|
||
speech, explains the extraordinary forgetting that occurs: "The person who carries out a
|
||
command. . . does not accuse himself, but the sting: this is the true culprit, whom he carries
|
||
with him everywhere.... It is his permanent witness that it was not he himself who perpe-
|
||
trated a given wrong. He sees himself as its victim and thus has no feeling left for the real vic-
|
||
tim. It is true, therefore, that people who have acted on orders can feel entirely guiltless,"
|
||
making it all the easier for them to move on to other order-words (p. 332). This provides a
|
||
profound explanation for the Nazis' feeling of innocence, or for the capacity of forgetfulness
|
||
displayed by old Stalinists, whose amnesia worsens the more they invoke their memory and
|
||
past in order to claim the right to follow new and even more insidious order-words—"sting
|
||
mania." In this respect, Canetti's analysis seems essential. However, it presupposes the exis-
|
||
tence of a very particular psychic faculty in the absence of which the order-word would not
|
||
have this mode of action. The whole classical rationalist theory—of "common sense," of
|
||
universally shared good sense based on information and communication—is a way to cover
|
||
up or hide, and to justify in advance, a much more disturbing faculty, that of order-words.
|
||
This singularly irrational faculty is best safeguarded by gracing it with the name of pure rea-
|
||
son, by saying that it is nothing but pure reason . . .
|
||
18. See Emile Brehier's classic study, La theorie des incorporels dans I'ancien stoicisme
|
||
(Paris: Vrin, 1970). On "the knife cuts the flesh" and "the tree turns green," see pp. 12 and 20.
|
||
19. [TRANS: Kafka, The Castle, trans. Willa and Edwin Muir (New York: Knopf, 1976),
|
||
P- 12.]
|
||
20. [TRANS: Kafka, "The Stoker," chapter 1 of Amerika, trans. Edwin Muir (Norfolk,
|
||
Conn.: New Directions, 1940.]
|
||
21. Stalin, in his famous text on linguistics [Marxism and Linguistics (New York: Inter-
|
||
national Publishers, 1951)—Trans.], claims to identify two neutral forms serving all of soci-
|
||
ety, all classes, and all regimes equally: instruments and machines as pure means of
|
||
production of goods, and language as a pure means of information and communication.
|
||
Even Bakhtin defines language as the form of ideology, but he specifies that the form of ide-
|
||
ology is not itself ideological.
|
||
22. On these problems, see J. M. Sadock, "Hypersentences" (Diss. University of Illinois,
|
||
1968); Dieter Wunderlich, "Pragmatique, situation d'enonciation et Deixis," Langages, no.
|
||
36 (June 1972), pp. 34-58; and especially S. K. Saumjan, "Aspects algebriques de la gram-
|
||
526 D NOTES TO PP. 91-99
|
||
|
||
maire applicative," Langages, no. 33 (March 1974), pp. 95-122. Saumjan proposes a model of
|
||
abstract objects based on the operation of application called AGM (applicative generative
|
||
model). He cites Hjelmslev as an influence; Hjelmslev's strength is to have conceived of the
|
||
form of expression and the form of content as two entirely relative variables on one and the
|
||
same plane, as "functives of one and the same function," Hjelmslev, Prolegomena to a Theory
|
||
of Language, trans. Francis J. Whitfield (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1969).
|
||
This advance toward a diagrammatic conception of the abstract machine is, however, coun-
|
||
teracted by the fact that Hjelmslev still conceives the distinction between expression and con-
|
||
tent in the signifier-signified mode and therefore retains the subordination of the abstract
|
||
machine to linguistics.
|
||
23. See Herbert Brekle, Semantique (Paris: A. Colin, 1974), pp. 94-104, on the idea of a
|
||
universal pragmatics and of "universals of dialogue."
|
||
24. On this budding and various representations of it, see Wunderlich, "Pragmatique, sit-
|
||
uation d'enonciation et Deixis."
|
||
25. Noam Chomsky, Language and Responsibility. Based on Conversations with Mitsou
|
||
Ronat, trans. John Viertel (New York: Pantheon, 1979), pp. 53-55.
|
||
26. William Labov, Sociolinguistic Patterns, especially pp. 187-190. It will be noted that
|
||
Labov at times limits himself to statements that have approximately the same meaning and at
|
||
other times disregards this condition in order to follow a sequence of complementary but het-
|
||
erogeneous statements.
|
||
27. [TRANS: This is a phrase from Proust's Time Regained in Remembrance of Things
|
||
Past, trans. C. K. Scott Moncrieff, Terence Kilmartin, and Andreas Mayor (New York: Ran-
|
||
dom House, 1981), vol. 3, p. 905 (vol. 3, p. 872, in the French "Pleiade" edition). See Deleuze,
|
||
Proust and Signs, trans. Richard Howard (New York: Braziller, 1972), pp. 59-60.]
|
||
28. This is indeed how Labov tends to define his notion of "optional or variable rules," as
|
||
opposed to constant rules: not simply an observed frequency, but a specific quantity express-
|
||
ing the probability of the frequency or the application of the rule. See Language in the Inner
|
||
City (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1972), pp. 94ff.
|
||
29. See Gilbert Rouget's article, "Un chromatisme africain," in L'Homme, vol. 1, no. 3
|
||
(September-December 1961), pp. 32-46 (this issue comes with a recording of ritual chants of
|
||
Dahomey).
|
||
30. Gherasim Luca, Le chant de la carpe (Paris: Soleil Noir, 1973), and the recording put
|
||
out by Givaudan, on which Luca recites the poem "Passionnement."
|
||
31. [TRANS: See Carmelo Bene and Gilles Deleuze, Superpositions (Paris: Minuit, 1979).
|
||
Forthcoming in English translation from Semiotext(e).]
|
||
32. "And" has an especially important role in English literature, as a function not only of
|
||
the Old Testament but also of the "minorities" at work on the language: one case in point is J.
|
||
M. Synge (see Francois Regnault's remarks on coordination in Anglo-Irish in the French
|
||
translation of Playboy of the Western World, Baladin du monde occidental [Paris: Biblio-
|
||
theque du Graphe]). It should not be thought adequate to analyze the "and" as a conjunction;
|
||
rather, "and" is a special form of every possible conjunction and brings into play a logic of lan-
|
||
guage. Jean Wahl's works contain profound reflections on this sense of "and," on the way it
|
||
challenges the primacy of the verb "to be."
|
||
33. Hjelmslev, Language: An Introduction, trans. Francis J. Whitfield (Madison: Univer-
|
||
sity of Wisconsin Press, 1970), pp. 39ff.
|
||
34. Nicolas Ruwet, "Parallelisme et deviations en poesie," in Langue, discours, societe.
|
||
Pour Emile Benveniste, ed. Julia Kristeva, Nicolas Ruwet, and Jean-Claude Milner (Paris:
|
||
Seuil, 1975). Ruwet analyzes Poem 29 in Cummings's Fifty Poems (New York: Duell, Sloan
|
||
and Pearce, 1940); he gives a restricted and structuralist interpretation of this phenomenon of
|
||
variation, invoking the notion of parallelism; in other texts, he minimizes the importance of
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 99-106 D 527
|
||
|
||
these variations, treating them as marginal exercises irrelevant to true changes in language;
|
||
still, his comments seem to us to transcend all of these interpretive restrictions.
|
||
35. See Vidal Sephiha, "Introduction a 1'etude de 1'intensif," Langages, no. 29 (March
|
||
1973). This is one of the first studies of the atypical tensions and variations of language, par-
|
||
ticularly as they appear in so-called minor languages.
|
||
36. On the expansion and diffusion of states of language, in the "patch of oil" mode or the
|
||
"paratrooper" mode, see Bertil Malmberg, New Trends in Linguistics, trans. Edward Garners
|
||
(Stockholm: Lund, 1964), chapter 3 (which uses N. Lindqvist's important studies on dialect).
|
||
What are needed now are comparative studies of how homogenizations and centralizations of
|
||
given major languages take place. In this respect, the linguistic history of French is not at all
|
||
the same as that of English; neither is their relation to writing as a form of homogenization the
|
||
same. For French, the centralized language par excellence, one may refer to the analysis of
|
||
Michel de Certeau, Dominique Julia, and Jacques Revel, Une politique de la langue (Paris:
|
||
Gallimard, 1975). The analysis covers a very brief period at the end of the eighteenth century,
|
||
focusing on Abbot Gregory, and notes two distinct periods: one in which the central language
|
||
opposed the rural dialects, just as the town opposed the countryside, and the capital the prov-
|
||
inces; and another in which it opposed "feudal idioms," as well as the language of the emigres,
|
||
just as the Nation opposes everything that is foreign to it, an enemy of it (pp. 160ff.: "It is also
|
||
obvious that the rejection of the dialects resulted from a technical inability to grasp stable
|
||
laws in regional speech patterns").
|
||
37. See Michel Lalonde, Change, no. 30 (March 1977), pp. 100-122, where the poem,
|
||
"Speak White," quoted in text, appears, along with a manifesto on the Quebecois language
|
||
("La deffense et illustration de la langue quebecqoyse").
|
||
38. On the complex situation of Afrikaans, see Breyten Breytenbach's fine book, Feu
|
||
Froid (Paris: Bourgois, 1976); G. M. Lory's study (pp. 101-107) elucidates Breytenbach's
|
||
project, the violence of his poetic treatment of the language, and his will to be a "bastard, with
|
||
a bastard language."
|
||
39. On the double aspect of minor language, poverty-ellipsis, and overload-variation, one
|
||
may refer to a certain number of exemplary studies: Klauss Wagenbach's study of the German
|
||
of Prague at the beginning of the twentieth century (Franz Kafka. Eine Biographic seiner
|
||
Jugend [Bern: Francke, 1958]); Pasolini's study demonstrating that Italian was not con-
|
||
structed on the basis of a new standard or mean, but exploded in two simultaneous directions,
|
||
"upward and downward," in other words, toward simplified material and expressive exagger-
|
||
ation (L'experience her'etique, pp. 46-47); J. L. Dillard's study bringing out the double ten-
|
||
dency of Black English on the one hand to omit, lose, disencumber, and on the other to
|
||
overload, to develop "fancy talk" (Black English [New York: Random House, 1972]). As
|
||
Dillard notes, there is no inferiority to the standard language; instead there is a correlation
|
||
between two movements that necessarily escape from the standard level of language. Still on
|
||
the topic of Black English, LeRoi Jones shows the extent to which the two conjoined direc-
|
||
tions approximate language to music (Blues People [New York: William Morrow, 1963], pp.
|
||
30-31 and all of chapter 3). On a more general level, one will recall Pierre Boulez's analysis of a
|
||
double movement in music, dissolution of form, and dynamic overload or proliferation: Con-
|
||
versations with Celestin Deliege, (London: Eulenberg Books, 1976), pp. 20-22.
|
||
40. Yann Moulier, preface to Mario Tronti, Owners et Capital (Paris: Bourgois, 1977),
|
||
p. 6.
|
||
41. Pasolini, L 'experience her'etique, p. 62
|
||
42. See the "Strategy Collective" manifesto on the Quebecois language in Change, no. 30
|
||
(March 1977): it denounces the "myth of subversive language," which implies that simply
|
||
being in a minority is enough to make one a revolutionary ("this mechanist equation derives
|
||
from a populist conception of language.... Speaking the language of the working class is not
|
||
528 D NOTES TO PP. 106-120
|
||
|
||
what links an individual to the positions of that class.... The argument that Joual has a sub-
|
||
versive, countercultural force is entirely idealistic"; p. 188).
|
||
43. Elias Canetti, Crowds and Power (see the two essential chapters corresponding to the
|
||
two aspects of the order-word, "The Command" and "Transformation"; especially pp. 313-
|
||
314, describing the pilgrimage to Mecca and its two coded aspects, mortifying petrification
|
||
and panicked flight).
|
||
44. [TRANS: Translated as "prohibitions of transformation" in the English version of
|
||
Crowds and Power. Enantio- is from the Greek, "to oppose."]
|
||
45. [TRANS: Canetti, Crowds and Power, pp. 378, 380.]
|
||
46. As we have seen, Hjelmslev imposes a restrictive condition, that of assimilating the
|
||
plane of content to a kind of "signified." Certain authors are therefore correct in objecting
|
||
that the analysis of content he proposes has less to do with linguistics than other disciplines,
|
||
such as zoology (for example, Andre Martinet, with the collaboration of Jeanne Martinet and
|
||
HenrietteWalter,Lalinguistique. Guidealphabetique[Paris: Danoel, 1969],p. 353).Itseems
|
||
to us, however, that this objection applies only to Hjelmslev's restrictive condition.
|
||
47. [TRANS: See 12, "1227: Treatise on Nomadology," pp. 351-423.]
|
||
48. See the details of the text of Hugo von Hofmannsthal, Lettres du voyageur a son retour,
|
||
trans. Jean-Claude Schneider (Paris: Mercure de France, 1969), letter of May 9, 1901.
|
||
|
||
5. 587 B.C.-A.D. 70: On Several Regimes of Signs
|
||
1. Claude Levi-Strauss, "Introduction a 1'oeuvre de Marcel Mauss," in Marcel Mauss,
|
||
Sociologie et anthropologie (Paris: PUF, 1973), pp. 48-49 (later in this text Levi-Strauss brings
|
||
out another aspect of the signified). On this first aspect of the atmospheric continuum, see the
|
||
Binswanger's and Arieti's psychiatric descriptions.
|
||
2. See Levi-Strauss, The Savage Mind (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1966), pp.
|
||
209ff. (an analysis of the two cases).
|
||
3. Levi-Strauss, preface to Don C. Talayesva, SoleilHopi (Paris: Plon, 1968), p. vi [trans-
|
||
lation of Sun Chief, ed. Leo W. Simmons (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1942)].
|
||
4. For example, in Bantu myth the first founder of the State shows his face and eats and
|
||
drinks in public, whereas the hunter, subsequently the warrior, invents the art of secrecy. See
|
||
Luc de Heusch, Le roi ivre ou I'origine de I'Etat (Paris: Gallimard, 1972), pp. 20-25. Heusch
|
||
sees the second moment as proof of a more "refined" civilization; to us, on the other hand, it is
|
||
a different semiotic system, that of war rather than public works.
|
||
5. Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New York: Vin-
|
||
tage, 1975), p. 29 [translation modified].
|
||
6. See A. J. Greimas, "Pratiques et langagesgestuels," in Conditions d'une semiotique du
|
||
monde naturel, Langages, no. 10 (June 1968), pp. 3-35. Greimas, however, relates this
|
||
semiotic to categories such as "the subject of the statement" and the "subject of enunciation,"
|
||
which seem to us to belong to other regimes of signs.
|
||
7. On cannibalism as a way of protecting against the souls or names of the dead, and on
|
||
its semiotic function as "calendar," see Pierre Clastres, Chronique des Indiens Guayaki (Paris:
|
||
Plon, 1972), pp. 332-340.
|
||
8. The foregoing expressions concerning the number are borrowed from Julia Kristeva.
|
||
Kristeva, however, uses them in an analysis of literary texts based on the hypothesis of the
|
||
"signifier": Semiotike. Recherches pour une semanalyse (Paris: Seuil, 1969), pp. 294ff., 317.
|
||
9. See Paul Serieux and Joseph Capgras, Lesfolies raisonnantes (Paris: Alcan, 1909), and
|
||
Gatian Clerambault, Oeuvre psychiatrique, rpt. (Paris: PUF, 1942). Capgras believes in an
|
||
essentially mixed or polymorphous semiotic; Clerambault abstractly analyzes two pure
|
||
semiotics, although he does recognize that they form de facto mixes. The principal texts on
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 120-125 D 529
|
||
|
||
the origin of the distinction between two groups of delusions are Jean Esquirol, Des maladies
|
||
mentales(Brussels: J. B. Tircher, 1838) (to what extent is "monomania" distinguishable from
|
||
mania?); and Emil Kraepelin, Psychiatric. Ein Lehrbuch fur Studierende undArtze, 8th ed.
|
||
(Leipzig: J. A. Barth, 1920) [English translation, Lectures on Clinical Psychiatry, rpt., ed.
|
||
Thomas Johnstone (New York: Hafner, 1968)] (to what extent is "querulous delusion" distin-
|
||
guishable from paranoia?). The question of the second group of delusions, or the passional
|
||
delusions, was broached and analyzed historically by Jacques Lacan, De la psychose
|
||
parandiaque (Paris: Seuil, 1975), and by Daniel Lagache, La jalousie amoureuse (Paris: PUF,
|
||
1947).
|
||
10. See Serieux and Capgras, Lesfolies raisonnantes, pp. 340ff., and Clerambault, Oeuvre
|
||
psychiatrigue, pp. 369ff.: people with passional delusion are overlooked, even in the asylum,
|
||
because they are calm and cunning, "suffering from a limited enough delusion that they know
|
||
how we judge them." This makes it all the more necessary to keep them confined; "such
|
||
patients must not be questioned, but rather maneuvered, and the only way to maneuver them
|
||
is to move them emotionally."
|
||
11. Esquirol suggests that monomania is a "disease of civilization" and has a social evolu-
|
||
tion: it begins religious but tends to become more and more political, tracked by the police
|
||
(Des maladies mentales, vol. 1, p. 400). See also the remarks of Emmanuel Regis, Les regicides
|
||
dans I'histoire et dans le present (Lyons: A. Storck, 1890).
|
||
12. Deuteronomy 1:12. In the "Pleiade" edition of the Bible (Paris: Gallimard, 1959), vol.
|
||
1, p. 510, editor Edouard Dhorme specifies: "Your grievance, literally your proceeding."
|
||
13. D. H. Lawrence, Apocalypse (New York: Viking, 1932), pp. 93-94.
|
||
14. See Edouard Dhorme, La religion des Hebreux nomades (Brussels: Nouvelle
|
||
Societe d'Editions, 1937), and Zecharia Mayani, Les Hyksos et le monde de la Bible (Paris:
|
||
Payot, 1956). The author emphasizes the connections between the Hebrews and the Ha-
|
||
biru (nomadic warriors) and Kenites (nomadic metal workers); what is specific to Moses is
|
||
not the principle of numerical organization, which was borrowed from the nomads, but
|
||
the idea of an always revocable convention-proceeding, contract-proceeding. This idea,
|
||
according to Mayani, derives neither from the rooted farmers nor from the nomadic warri-
|
||
ors, nor even from the migrants, but from a tribe on the march that thinks of itself in terms
|
||
of subjective destiny.
|
||
15. See Franz Kafka, The Trial, trans. Willa and Edwin Muir (New York: Schocken,
|
||
1968). The painter Titorelli originates the theory of indefinite postponement. Aside from def-
|
||
inite acquittal, which does not exist, Titorelli differentiates the two juridical regimes of
|
||
"ostensible acquittal" and "indefinite postponement"; the first is circular and linked to a
|
||
semiotic of the signifier, whereas the second is linear and segmentary, linked to the passional
|
||
semiotic(pp. 152-162).
|
||
16. [TRANS: The King James Bible reads "to flee . . . from the presence of the Lord."
|
||
Jonah 1:3.]
|
||
17. Jerome Lindon was the first to analyze the relation between Jewish prophetism and
|
||
betrayal, in the exemplary case of Jonah. Jonas (Paris: Minuit, 1955).
|
||
18. Friedrich Holderlin, Remarques sur Oedipe (Paris: Union Generate d'Edition, 1965).
|
||
Holderlin already puts limits on the character of this "slow and difficult" death; see Jean
|
||
Beaufret's fine discussion of the nature of this death and its relation to betrayal: "Man must
|
||
match the categorical turning away of the god, now no more than Time, by himself turning
|
||
away as a traitor."
|
||
19. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vin-
|
||
tage, 1967), sec. 9.
|
||
20. [TRANS: See 10, "1730: Becoming-Intense ...," note 10.]
|
||
21. [TRANS: "Buggers," from the Middle French for "Bulgarians," originally referred to a
|
||
530 D NOTES TO PP. 125-141
|
||
|
||
sect of heretics from Bulgaria suspected of 'unnatural' practices, and later became a general
|
||
term for heretics before taking on its modern meaning.]
|
||
22. On the nature of the epic "library" (its imperial character, the role of priests, the circu-
|
||
lation between sanctuaries and cities), see Charles Autran, Homere et les origines sacerdotales
|
||
de I'epop'ee grecque, 3 vols. (Paris: Denoel, 1938-1944).
|
||
23. See the techniques for the interpretation of books in the Middle Ages, and the extreme
|
||
attempt by Joachim de Flore, who, on the basis of similarities between the two Testaments,
|
||
induces from within a third state or proceeding. L 'Evangile eternel (Paris: Rieder, 1928).
|
||
24. For example, Exodus 19:2: "For they were departed from Rephidim, and were come to
|
||
the desert of Sinai, and had pitched in the wilderness, and there Israel camped before the
|
||
mount."
|
||
25. Henry Miller, Sexus (New York: Grove Press, 1965), p. 250.
|
||
26. Louis Althusser, "Ideologic et appareils ideologiques d'Etat," La pensee, no. 151
|
||
(May-June 1970), pp. 29-35.
|
||
27. In Problems of General Linguistics, trans Mary Elizabeth Meek (Coral Gables, Fla.:
|
||
University of Florida Press, 1971), pp. 217-222, Emile Benveniste speaks of a proceeding, or
|
||
process (proces).
|
||
28. One aspect of Strindberg's genius was to elevate the couple, and the domestic squab-
|
||
ble, to an intense semiotic level, and to make it a creative factor in the regime of signs. This was
|
||
not the case with Jouhandeau. Klossowski, on the other hand, was able to invent new sources
|
||
and conflicts for the passional cogito for two, from the standpoint of a general theory of signs;
|
||
Les lots de I'hospitalite (Paris: Gallimard, 1965).
|
||
29. See also Dostoyevsky's The Double.
|
||
30. On these two forms of redundancy, see the entry on "Redondance" in Andre Martinet,
|
||
La linguistique. Guide alphab'etique (Paris: Danoel, 1969), pp. 331-333.
|
||
31. Henry Miller, Sexus, p. 229. The theme of the idiot is itself quite diverse. It is an
|
||
explicit part of the cogito according to Descartes, and feeling according to Rousseau. Russian
|
||
literature, however, takes it down other paths, beyond consciousness or passion.
|
||
32. Gherasim Luca, Le chant de la carpe (Paris: Soleil Noir, 1973), pp. 87-94.
|
||
33. For example, when the whites introduced money to the Siane of New Guinea, the lat-
|
||
ter started off by translating the bills and coins into two categories of nonconvertible goods.
|
||
See Maurice Godelier, "Economic politique et anthropologie economique," L'Homme, vol.
|
||
14, no. 3 (September-December 1964), p. 123.
|
||
34. On these translations-transformations, see LeRoi Jones, Blues People (New York:
|
||
Morrow, 1963), chapters 3-7.
|
||
35. Miller, Sexus, pp. 479-480.
|
||
36. Mary Barnes and Joseph Berke, Mary Barnes: Two Accounts of a Journey through
|
||
Madness (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1971), p. 233. The failure of the antipsychi-
|
||
atry experiment of Kingsley Hall apparently was due as much to these internal factors as to
|
||
external circumstances.
|
||
37. Carlos Castaneda, Journey to Ixtlan (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1973), p. 14.
|
||
38. "Generative" and "transformational" are Chomsky's terms. For him, the transforma-
|
||
tional is precisely the best and most profound way of realizing the generative; we, however, are
|
||
using the terms in a different sense.
|
||
39. Michel Foucault has developed, in successive levels, a theory of statements addressing
|
||
all of these problems. (1) In The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New
|
||
York: Pantheon, 1982), Foucault distinguishes two kinds of "multiplicities," of content and of
|
||
expression, which are not reducible to relations of correspondence or causality, but are in
|
||
reciprocal presupposition. (2) In Discipline and Punish, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New
|
||
York: Vintage, 1975), he looks for an agency capable of accounting for the two imbricated,
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 141-153 D 531
|
||
|
||
heterogeneous forms, and finds it in assemblages of power, or micropowers. (3) But these col-
|
||
lective assemblages (school, army, factory, hospital, prison, etc.) are only degrees or singulari-
|
||
ties in an abstract "diagram," which for its part has only matter and function (the unspecified
|
||
multiplicity of human beings to be controlled). (4) TheHistory of Sexuality. Vol. LAnlntro-
|
||
duction, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Pantheon, 1978), takes yet another direction since
|
||
assemblages are no longer related to and contrasted with a diagram, but rather to a "biopoli-
|
||
tics of population" as an abstract machine. Our only points of disagreement with Foucault are
|
||
the following: (1) to us the assemblages seem fundamentally to be assemblages not of power
|
||
but of desire (desire is always assembled), and power seems to be a stratified dimension of the
|
||
assemblage; (2) the diagram and abstract machine have lines of flight that are primary, which
|
||
are not phenomena of resistance or counterattack in an assemblage, but cutting edges of cre-
|
||
ation and deterritorialization.
|
||
40. Louis Hjelmslev proposed a very important conception of "matter" or "purport"
|
||
(sens) as unformed, amorphous, or formless: Prolegomena to a Theory of Language, trans.
|
||
Francis J. Whitfield (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1969), sec. 13, pp. 47-60, and
|
||
Essais linguistiques (Paris: Minuit, 1971), pp. 58ff. (see also the preface by Francois Rastier,
|
||
p. 9).
|
||
41. The distinction between indexes, icons, and symbols comes from C. S. Peirce, Col-
|
||
lected Papers, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
|
||
Press, 1931-1958). But his distinctions are based on signifier-signified relations (contiguity
|
||
for the index, similitude for the icon, conventional rule for the symbol); this leads him to make
|
||
the "diagram" a special case of the icon (the icon of relation). Peirce is the true inventor of
|
||
semiotics. That is why we can borrow his terms, even while changing their connotations. First,
|
||
indexes, icons, and symbols seem to us to be distinguished by territoriality-deterritorializa-
|
||
tion relations, not signifier-signified relations. Second, the diagram as a result seems to have a
|
||
distinct role, irreducible to either the icon or the symbol. On Peirce's fundamental distinc-
|
||
tions and the complex status of the diagram, one may refer to Jakobson's analysis, "A la
|
||
recherche de 1'essence du langage," in Problemes du langage, ed. Emile Benveniste (Paris:
|
||
Gallimard, 1966).
|
||
|
||
6. November 28,1947: How to Make Yourself a Body without Organs
|
||
1. [TRANS: Antonin Artaud, "To Have Done With the Judgement of God," Selected Writ-
|
||
ings, ed. Susan Sontag (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1976), p. 571.]
|
||
2. [TRANS: Jules Cotard, Etard sur les maladies cerebrates et mentales (Paris: Brail-
|
||
liere, 1891).]
|
||
3. [TRANS: Dr. Schreber's Memoirs, quoted by Sigmund Freud, Notes on a Case ofPara-
|
||
noia,vo\. 12, Standard Edition, trans. James Strachey (London: Hogarth Press, 1957), p. 17.]
|
||
4. William Burroughs, Naked Lunch (New York: Grove Press, 1966), p. 131.
|
||
5. The opposition program-phantasy appears clearly in the work of Michel de M'uzan,
|
||
in relation to a case of masochism. See M'uzan in La sexualit'e perverse, ed. Isle and Robert
|
||
Barande et al. (Paris: Payot, 1972), p. 36. Although he does not specifically discuss this
|
||
opposition, M'uzan uses the notion of the program to question the themes of Oedipus, anxi-
|
||
ety, and castration.
|
||
6. See Kurt Lewin's description of the flow of meat in the American family, "Psychologi-
|
||
cal Ecology," Field Theory in Social Science, ed. Dorwin Cartwright (New York: Harper and
|
||
Brothers, 1951), pp. 170-187.
|
||
7. Albert Dalcq, L'oeufet son dynamisme organisateur (Paris: Albin Michel, 1941), p.
|
||
95: "Forms are contingent upon kinematic dynamism. It is secondary whether or not an ori-
|
||
fice forms in the germ. All that counts is the process of immigration itself; what yields an ori-
|
||
532 D NOTES TO PP. 153-170
|
||
|
||
fice fissure or primitive line is not invagination, but pure chronological and quantitative
|
||
variations."
|
||
8. Burroughs, Naked Lunch, p. 8.
|
||
9. Ibid., pp. xlv-xlvi.
|
||
10. [TRANS: Jouissance: "pleasure, enjoyment, orgasm." In Lacanian psychoanalysis, the
|
||
object of desire is irrevocably lost and the subject eternally split. Jouissance is doubly impossi-
|
||
ble: life is a manque-a-jouir, read as "lack of enjoyment," because the true object of desire is
|
||
unattainable; and it is a manque-a-jouir, read as "a lack to be enjoyed," because Jouissance as
|
||
the orgasmic plenitude of union with a substitute object means the annulment of the constitu-
|
||
tionally split subject. One of the necessary terms, the subject or the object, is always missing.]
|
||
11. Roger Dupouy, "Du masochisme," Annales medico-psychologiques, series 12, vol. 2
|
||
(1929), p. 405.
|
||
12. Ibid.
|
||
13. On courtly love, and its radical immanence rejecting both religious transcendence
|
||
and hedonist exteriority, see Rene Nelli, L'erotique des troubadours (Paris: Union Generate
|
||
d'Editions, 1974), in particular, vol. l,pp. 267, 316, 358, and 370, and vol. 2, pp. 47, 53, and
|
||
75. (Also vol. 1, p. 128: one of the major differences between chivalric love and courtly love is
|
||
that for "knights the valor by which one merits love is always external to love," whereas in the
|
||
system of courtly love, the test is essentially internal to love; war valor is replaced by "senti-
|
||
mental heroism." This is a mutation in the war machine.)
|
||
14. Robert Van Gulik, Sexual Life in Ancient China (Leiden: Brill, 1961); and Jean-
|
||
Francois Lyotard's discussion of it, Economie libidinale (Paris: Minuit, 1974), pp. 241 -251.
|
||
15. Gregory Bateson, Steps to an Ecology of Mind (New York: Ballantine Books, 1972),
|
||
p. 113.
|
||
16. Artaud, H'eliogabale, in Oeuvres Completes (Paris: Gallimard), pp. 50-51. It is true
|
||
that Artaud still presents the identity of the One and the Multiple as a dialectical unity, one
|
||
that reduces the multiple by gathering it into the One. He makes Heliogabalus a kind of
|
||
Hegelian. But that is a manner of speaking, for from the beginning multiplicity surpasses all
|
||
opposition and does away with dialectical movement.
|
||
17. [TRANS: Artaud, "The Body Is the Body," trans. Roger McKeon, Semiotext(e), Anti-
|
||
Oedipus, vol. 2, no. 3 (1977), p. 59.]
|
||
18. Artaud, The Peyote Dance (translation of Les Tarahumaras), trans. Helen Weaver
|
||
(New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1976), pp. 38-39 [translation modified].
|
||
19. [TRANS: Carlos Castaneda, Tales of Power (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1974),
|
||
p. 125.]
|
||
20. [TRANS: Ibid., p. 183.]
|
||
21. [TRANS: Ibid., p. 161.]
|
||
22. See Cause commune, no. 3 (October 1972).
|
||
|
||
7. Year Zero: Faciality
|
||
1. Josef von Sternberg, Fw«/« a Chinese Laundry (New York: MacMillan, 1965), p. 324.
|
||
[TRANS: The English version of this phrase reads "merciful darkness."]
|
||
2. [TRANS: "Blumfeld. An Elderly Gentleman." The Complete Stories of Franz Kafka, ed.
|
||
Nahum N. Glazer (New York: Schocken, 1983), pp. 183-205.]
|
||
3. On this ballet, see Jean Barraque's Debussy (Paris: Seuil, 1977), which cites the text of
|
||
the argument, pp. 166-171.
|
||
4. See Otto Isakower, "Contribution a la psychopathologie des phenomenes associes a
|
||
rendormissement," Nouve/le revue de psychanalyse, no. 5 (Spring 1972), pp. 197-210;
|
||
Bertram D. Lewin, "Le sommeil, la bouche et 1'ecran du reve," ibid., pp. 211-224; and Rene
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 170-183 D 533
|
||
|
||
Spitz, with the collaboration of W. Godfrey Cobliner, The First Year of Life (New York: Inter-
|
||
national Publishers, 1965), pp. 75-82.
|
||
5. Henry Miller, Tropic of Capricorn (New York: Grove Press, 1961), pp. 121-123.
|
||
6. Klaatsch, "L'evolution du genre humain," in Kreomer, L'Univers et I'humanite, vol.
|
||
2: "In vain, we tried to find a trace of red edging around the lips of live, young chimpanzees,
|
||
which resemble man so closely in all other respects.... How would the face of the most gra-
|
||
cious young woman look if her mouth was a stripe between two white borders?... In addition,
|
||
the pectoral region of the anthropoid possesses the two nipples of the mammary glands, but
|
||
folds of fat comparable to the breasts never form." And Emile Devaux's formula in Trois
|
||
problemes: I'espece, {'instinct, l'homme(Pa.m: Le Francois, 1933), p. 264: "The child made the
|
||
woman's breast, and the mother the child's lips."
|
||
7. Face exercises play an essential role in the pedagogical principles of J.-B. de la Salle.
|
||
Even Ignacio de Loyola integrated his teaching landscape exercises or "compositions of
|
||
place" relative to the life of Christ, hell, the world, etc. As Barthes points out, this involves
|
||
skeletal images subordinated to a language, but also active schemas to be completed, colored
|
||
in, like those found in catechisms and devotional handbooks [Sade, Fourier, Loyola, trans.
|
||
Richard Miller (New York: Hill and Wang, 1976)—Trans.]
|
||
8. Chretien de Troyes, The Story of the Grail, trans. Robert White Linker (Chapel Hill:
|
||
University of North Carolina Press, 1952), pp. 88-89. A similar scene, dominated by the
|
||
"machinery" of the boat, is found in Malcolm Lowry's novel Ultramarine (Philadelphia:
|
||
Lippincott, 1962), pp. 159-172: a pigeon drowns in waters infested by sharks, "as if a red leaf
|
||
should fall on a white torrent" (p. 170), and this inevitably evokes the image of a bloody face.
|
||
Lowry's scene is imbedded in such different elements and is so particularly organized that
|
||
there can be no question of influence by Chretien de Troyes's scene, only confluence with it.
|
||
This makes it an even better confirmation of the existence of a veritable black hole or red
|
||
mark-white wall abstract machine (snow or water).
|
||
9. [TRANS: Continued in 10, "1730: Becoming-Intense ...," pp. 232-309]
|
||
10. Sergei Eisenstein, Film Form and Film Sense, trans. Jay Leyda (New York: Meridian
|
||
Books, 1957), p. 195-199: "'The kettle began i t . . . " Thus Dickens opens his Cricket on the
|
||
Hearth. ... What could be further from films!... But, strange as it may seem, movies also
|
||
were boiling in that kettle.... As soon as we recognize this kettle as a typical close-up, we
|
||
exclaim:'... of course this is the purest Griffith.'... Certainly, this kettle is a typical Griffith-
|
||
esque close-up. A close-up saturated, we now become aware, with typically Dickens-esque
|
||
'atmosphere,' with which Griffith, with equal mastery, can envelop the severe face of life in
|
||
Way Down East, and the icy cold moral face of his characters, who push the guilty Anna onto
|
||
the shifting surface of a swirling ice-break" (the white wall again).
|
||
11. Jacques Lizot, Le cercle desfeux (Paris: Seuil, 1976), pp. 34ff.
|
||
12. On the stranger grasped as Other, see Andre Haudricourt, "Nature et culture dans la
|
||
civilisation de 1'igname: 1'origine des clones et des clans," L'Homme vol. 4, no. 1 (January-
|
||
April 1964), pp. 98-102. And Robert Jaulin, Gens de soi, gens de I'autre (Paris: Union
|
||
Generate d'Editions, 1973), preface, p. 20.
|
||
13. Maurice Ronai demonstrates that the landscape, the reality as well as the notion, is
|
||
tied to a very particular semiotic system and very particular apparatuses of power: this is one
|
||
of the sources of geography, as well as a principle behind its political subordination (the land-
|
||
scape as "the face of the fatherland or nation"). See "Paysages," in Herodote, no. 1 (January-
|
||
March 1976), pp. 125-159.
|
||
14. See Jacques Mercier, Ethiopian Magic Scrolls, trans. Richard Pevear (New York:
|
||
Braziller, 1979). And "Les peintures des rouleaux protecteurs ethiopiens," Journal of Ethio-
|
||
pian Studies, vol. 14, fasc. 2 (Summer 1974), pp. 89-106 ("The eye stands for the face which
|
||
stands for the body.... The pupils are drawn in the inner spaces.... That is why we must
|
||
534 D NOTES TO PP. 183-197
|
||
|
||
speak of directions of magic meaning based on eyes and faces, with the use of traditional
|
||
decorative motifs such as cross-hatching, check patterns, four-pointed stars, etc."). The power
|
||
of Negus, with his ancestry going back to Solomon and his court of magicians, was based on
|
||
his ember-eyes, operating like a black hole, angelic or demonic. Mercier's analyses in their
|
||
entirety constitute an essential contribution to the analysis of facial functions.
|
||
15. For Eisenstein's own distinction between his conception of the close-up and
|
||
Griffith's, see Film Form and Film Sense.
|
||
16. This is a recurring theme in horror novels and science fiction: the eyes are in the black
|
||
hole, not the opposite ("I see a luminous disk emerging from the black hole, resembling eyes").
|
||
Comic books, Circus No. 2, for example, depict black holes populated by faces and eyes, and
|
||
the traversing of that black hole. On the relation of eyes to holes and walls, see the texts and
|
||
drawing of Jean-Luc Parant, in particular, Les yeux MMDVI (Paris: Bourgois, 1976).
|
||
17. See Jean Paris's analyses, L'espace et le regard (Paris: Seuil, 1965), vol. 1, chapter 1
|
||
(also, the evolution of the Virgin and the variation in the relations between her face and that of
|
||
the infant Jesus: vol. 2, chapter 2).
|
||
18. D. H. Lawrence, "Melville's 'Typee' and 'Omoo,'" Studies in Classic American Litera-
|
||
ture (New York: Thomas Seltzer, 1923), p. 197. Lawrence's essay begins with a lovely distinc-
|
||
tion between terrestrial and maritime eyes.
|
||
19. Miller, Tropic of Capricorn, p. 239.
|
||
20. Ibid., p. 63.
|
||
21. Ibid., pp. 63-64.
|
||
22. Wilhelm Reich's Character-Analysis, trans. Theodore P. Wolfe (New York: Farrar,
|
||
Straus and Giroux, 1970), considers the face and faciality traits to be among the first pieces
|
||
of character "armor" and the first ego resistances (the "occular ring," followed by the "oral
|
||
ring"). The organization of these rings occurs on planes perpendicular to the "orgonotic
|
||
streaming" and oppose the free movement of this streaming throughout the body. Hence the
|
||
importance of eliminating the armor and "dissolving the rings." See pp. 370ff.
|
||
23. Lawrence, Studies in Classic American Literature, p. 200.
|
||
24. D. H. Lawrence, Kangaroo (London: William Heinemann, 1964), p. 339.
|
||
|
||
8.1874: Three Novellas, or "What Happened?"
|
||
1. See Jules Amedee Barbey d'Aurevilly, The Diaboliques, trans. Ernest Boyd (New
|
||
York: Knopf, 1925). Of course, the work of Maupassant is not limited to tales; he also wrote
|
||
novellas, or novels containing elements of the novellas. For example, the episode of Lison in
|
||
chapter 4 of Une vie: "It was at the time of Aunt Lison's sudden impulse It was never spo-
|
||
ken of again, and remained as though enveloped in fog. One evening, Lise, then twenty, threw
|
||
herself into the water without anyone having an inkling why. Nothing in her life or manners,
|
||
could have allowed one to predict this act of madness."
|
||
2. Vladimir Propp, Morphology of the Folktale, 2nd ed., trans. Laurence Scott (Austin:
|
||
University of Texas Press, 1968).
|
||
3. Marcel Arland, Le Promeneur (Paris: Pavois, 1944).
|
||
4. [TRANS: "In the Cage," The Novels and Tales of Henry James (Fairiield, N. J.: Augustus
|
||
M. Kelley, 1979), vol. 11, p. 469.]
|
||
5. Nathalie Sarraute, in "Conversation and Sub-conversation," The Age of Suspicion,
|
||
trans. Maria Jolas (New York: Braziller, 1963), shows how Proust analyzes the smallest move-
|
||
ments, glances, or intonations. However, he apprehends them through memory, he assigns
|
||
them a "position," he thinks of them as a sequence of causes and effects; "he rarely... tried to
|
||
relive them and make them relive for the reader in the present, while they were forming and
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 197-211 D 535
|
||
|
||
developing, like so many tiny dramas, each one of which has its adventures, its mystery and its
|
||
unforeseeable ending" (p.92).
|
||
6. [TRANS: The French translation consulted by the authors reversed the meaning of this
|
||
passage. The original reads: "She knew at last so much that she had quite lost her earlier sense
|
||
of merely guessing. There were no different shades of distinctions—it all bounded out." In the
|
||
Cage, The Novels and Tales of Henry James, vol. 11, p. 472.]
|
||
7. S0ren Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling, trans. Walter Lowrie (Princeton, N.J.:
|
||
Princeton University Press, 1954), pp. 46ff.
|
||
8. [TRANS: Scott Fitzgerald, "The Crack-up," in The Crack-up. With Other Uncollected
|
||
Pieces, ed. Edmund Wilson (New York: New Directions, 1956), p.69.]
|
||
9. [TRANS: Ibid., pp. 82, 84.]
|
||
10. Pierrette Fleutiaux, Histoire du gouffre et de la lunette et autres nouvelles (Paris: Jul-
|
||
liard, 1976), pp. 9-50.
|
||
11. In another novella in the same collection, "Le dernier angle de transparence" (The
|
||
last angle of transparency). Fleutiaux distinguishes three lines of perception, but without
|
||
applying a preestablished schema. The hero has molar perception, which takes in overall
|
||
aggregates and clear-cut elements, well-distributed areas of fullness and emptiness (this per-
|
||
ception is coded, inherited, and overcoded by the walls: Don't miss you chair, etc.). But he
|
||
is also caught up in a molecular perception composed of fine and shifting segmentations and
|
||
autonomous traits, where holes appear in what is full and microforms in emptiness, between
|
||
two things, where everything "teems and stirs" with a thousand cracks. The hero's problem
|
||
is that he cannot make up his mind between the two lines and constantly jumps from one to
|
||
the other. Will he be saved by a third line of perception, the perception of escape, a "hypothet-
|
||
ical direction barely hinted at" by the angle of the two others, the "angle of transparency"
|
||
opening a new space?
|
||
12. Fernand Deligny, Cahiers de I'immuable, vol. 1, Voix et voir, Recherches, no. 8
|
||
(April 1975).
|
||
13. Henri Laborit wrote a book "in praise of flight," Eloge de lafuite (Paris: Laffont,
|
||
1976). In it, he demonstrates the biological importance of lines of flight among animals, but
|
||
his approach is too formalistic; among human beings, he thinks flight is associated with val-
|
||
ues of the imaginary functioning to increase one's "information" about the world.
|
||
14. [TRANS: See pp. 188-89.]
|
||
15. Leon Shestov, Chekhov and Other Essays (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1966),
|
||
pp. 8-9 [translation modified to agree with the French edition cited by the authors—Trans].
|
||
|
||
9.1933: Micropolitics and Segmentarity
|
||
1. Jacques Lizot, Le cercle des Feux (Paris: Seuil, 1976), p. 118
|
||
2. Claude Levi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, trans. Claire Jacobson and Brooke
|
||
Grundfest Schoeft (New York: Basic Books, 1963): "Do Dual Organizations Exist?" pp.
|
||
132-163.
|
||
3. See two exemplary studies in African Political Systems, ed. Meyer Frotes and E. E.
|
||
Evans-Pritchard (New York: Oxford University Press, 1978): Fortes, "The Political System of
|
||
the Tellensi of the Northern Territories of the Gold Coast," pp. 239-271, and Evans-
|
||
Pritchard, "The Nuer of the Southern Sudan," pp. 272-296.
|
||
4. Georges Balandier analyzes the ways in which ethnologists and sociologists define
|
||
this opposition: Political Anthropology, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New York: Pantheon,
|
||
1970), pp. 137-143.
|
||
5. On the initiation of a shaman and the role of the tree among the Yanomami Indians, see
|
||
Jacques Lizot, Le cercle des feux, pp. 127-135: "Between his legs a hole is hastily dug in
|
||
536 D NOTES TO PP. 211-217
|
||
|
||
which they place the base of the pole they erect there. Turaewe draws imaginary lines on the
|
||
ground radiating in all directions. He says, 'These are the roots.' "
|
||
6. The State, therefore, is not defined solely by the type of public powers it has, but also
|
||
as a resonance chamber for private as well as public powers. It is for this reason that Althusser
|
||
says: "The distinction between public and private is a distinction internal to bourgeois law,
|
||
and valid in the subordinate domains where bourgeois law exercises its powers. The domain
|
||
of the State eludes it because it is beyond Law.... It is on the contrary the foundation for any
|
||
distinction between the public and the private." "Ideologic et appareils ideologiques d'Etat,"
|
||
LaPens'ee, no. 151 (June 1970), pp. 29-35.
|
||
7. Jean-Pierre Vernant, Mythe etpens'ee chez les Grecs (Paris: Maspero, 1971-1974), vol.
|
||
1, part 3 ("When it becomes communal, when it is erected in the public and open space of the
|
||
agora and no longer inside private residences.. . the hearth [foyer: also, focus, focal point—
|
||
Trans.] expresses the center as common denominator of all of the houses constituting the
|
||
polis";p. 210).
|
||
8. Paul Virilio, L'insecurit'e du territoire (Paris: Stock, 1975), pp. 120, 174-175. On
|
||
"castrametation": "Geometry is the necessary foundation for a calculated expansion of
|
||
State power in space and time; conversely, this supplies the State with an ideal, sufficient fig-
|
||
ure, provided that the figure is ideally geometrical. . .. But Fenelon, voicing his opposition
|
||
to the State policies of Louis XIV, exclaimed: 'Beware the bewitchments and diabolical
|
||
attributes of geometry!"'
|
||
9. Meyer Fortes analyzes the difference among the Tellensi between "guardians of the
|
||
earth" and chiefs. This distinction between powers is fairly widespread among primitive soci-
|
||
eties; but the important thing is that it is organized in such a way as to prevent the powers from
|
||
resonating. For example, according to Louis Berthe's analysis of the Baduj of Java, the power
|
||
of the guardian of the earth, on the one hand, is considered to be passive and feminine but, on
|
||
the other hand, is assigned to the eldest son: this is not an "intrusion of kinship into the politi-
|
||
cal order" but on the contrary "a requirement of a political order translated in kinship terms"
|
||
in order to prevent the establishment of a resonance leading to private property. See Berthe,
|
||
"Aines et cadets, 1'alliance et la hierarchic chez les Baduj," L'Homme, vol. 5, nos. 3/4 (July-
|
||
December 65), pp. 189-223.
|
||
10. Franz Kafka, The Castle, trans. Willa and Edwin Muir (New York: Knopf, 1976),
|
||
especially chapter 15 (Barnabas's statements [the phrase quoted is on p. 228—Trans]). The
|
||
parable of the two offices—molar and molecular—does not just have a physical interpreta-
|
||
tion, as in Eddington, but a properly bureaucratic one as well.
|
||
11. The strength of Jean-Pierre Faye's book, Langages totalitaires (Paris: Hermann,
|
||
1972), is that it illustrates the multiplicity of these focuses, both practical and semiotic, on the
|
||
basis of which Nazism was constituted. That is why Faye is the first both to do a rigorous anal-
|
||
ysis of the concept of the totalitarian State (in its Italian and German origins) and to refuse to
|
||
define Italian fascism and German Nazism by that concept (which operates on a different
|
||
plane than the "subjacent process"). Faye goes into all of these points in La critique du langage
|
||
et son economic (Paris: Galilee, 1973).
|
||
12. On the complementarity between the "macropolitics of security" and the "micropoli-
|
||
tics," see Virilio, L'insecurit'e du territoire, pp. 96, 130, 228-235. The microorganization of
|
||
permanent stress in large modern cities has frequently been noted.
|
||
13. Valery Giscard d'Estaing, speech of June 1, 1976, before the Institut des Hautes
|
||
Etudes de Defense Nationale (complete text in Le Monde, June 4, 1976).
|
||
14. On the "flow with mutant power" and the distinction between the two kinds of money,
|
||
see Bernard Schmitt, Monnaie, salaires et profits (Paris: Castella, 1980), pp. 236, 275-277.
|
||
15. Michel Lelart, Le dollar. Monnaie Internationale (Paris: Albatros, 1975), p. 57.
|
||
16. Take Foucault's analysis, in Discipline and Punish, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 217-224 D 537
|
||
|
||
York: Vintage, 1975), of what he calls the "microphysics of power." First, it is indeed a ques-
|
||
tion of miniaturized mechanisms, or molecular focuses operating in detail or in the infinitely
|
||
small and forming any number of "disciplines" in the school, army, factory, prison, etc. (see
|
||
pp. 138ff.). But second, these segments themselves, and the focuses operating within them at
|
||
the molecular level, present themselves as the singularities of an "abstract" diagram coexten-
|
||
sive with the entire social field, or as quanta deducted from a flow of a nonspecific nature—
|
||
the nonspecific flow being defined by "a multiplicity of individuals" to be controlled (see pp.
|
||
205ff. [translation modified]).
|
||
17. On "quantitative sinfulness," quanta, and the qualitative leap, one may refer to the
|
||
microtheology constructed by Sdren Kierkegaard in The Concept of Dread, trans. Walter
|
||
Lowrie (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1957).
|
||
18. According to Tarde, psychology is quantitative, but only insofar as it studies the desire
|
||
and belief components of sensation. And logic is quantitative when it does not restrict itself to
|
||
forms of representation, but extends to degrees of belief and desire, and their combinations;
|
||
see La logique sociale (Paris: Alcan, 1893).
|
||
19. On all of these points, see especially Maurice Dobb, Studies in the Development of
|
||
Capitalism, rev. ed. (New York: International Publishers, 1964), and Georges Duby, The
|
||
Early Growth of the European Economy: Warriors and Peasants from the Seventh to Twelfth
|
||
Century, trans. Howard E. Clarke (London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1974).
|
||
20. Rosa Luxemburg, in "Social Reform or Revolution," and "Mass Strike, Party and
|
||
Trade Unions," in Selected Political Writings, ed. Dick Howard (New York: Monthly Review,
|
||
1971), formulated the problem of the differences and relations between masses and classes,
|
||
but from a still-subjective point of view: masses as the "instinctual basis of class conscious-
|
||
ness" (see Nicolas Boulte and Jacques Moiroux, "Masse et Parti," Partisans, no. 45, Rose
|
||
Luxemburg vivante [December-January 1969], pp. 29-38. Alain Badiou and Francois Balmes
|
||
advance a more objective hypothesis: masses are "invariants" that oppose the State-form in
|
||
general and exploitation, whereas classes are the historical variables that determine the con-
|
||
crete State, and, in the case of the proletariat, the possibility of its effective dissolution; De
|
||
I'ideologie [Paris: Maspero, 1976]). But it is difficult to see, first of all, why masses are not
|
||
themselves historical variables, and second, why the word is applied only to the exploited (the
|
||
"peasant-plebeian" mass), when it is also suitable for seigneurial, bourgeois masses—or even
|
||
monetary masses.
|
||
21. Jules Michelet, Histoire de France au seizieme siecle in Oeuvres Completes, vol. 7, ed.
|
||
Paul Viallaneix (Paris: Flammarion, 1971-).
|
||
22. Henri Pirenne, Mohammed and Charlemagne, trans. Bernard Miall (New York:
|
||
Norton, 1939), p. 22.
|
||
23. See Emile Felix Gautier, Genseric, roi des Vandales (Paris: Payot, 1932). ("Precisely
|
||
because they were the weakest, eternally being pushed from behind, they were forced to go
|
||
the farthest.")
|
||
24. Totalitarianism is not defined by the size of the public sector because in many cases
|
||
there is still a liberal economy. What defines it is the artificial constitution of "closed vessels,"
|
||
particularly monetary and industrial. It is primarily in this sense that Italian fascism and Ger-
|
||
man Nazism were totalitarian States, as demonstrated by Daniel Guerin in Fascism and Big
|
||
Business, trans. Frances and Mason Merrill (New York: Pioneer Publishers, 1939), chapter 9.
|
||
25. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, p. 27: "These relations go right down into the depths
|
||
of society, they are not localized in the relations between the state and its citizens or on the
|
||
frontier between classes and they do not merely reproduce... the general form of the law or
|
||
government... .They define innumerable points of confrontation, focuses of instability, each
|
||
of which has its own risks of conflict, of struggle, and of an at least temporary inversion of the
|
||
power relation."
|
||
538 D NOTES TO PP. 225-237
|
||
|
||
26. [TRANS: Kafka, The Castle, pp. 233, 238.]
|
||
27. On these aspects of banking power, see Suzanne de Brunhoff, L 'offre de monnaie. Cri-
|
||
tique d'un concept (Paris: Maspero, 1971), especially pp. 102-131.
|
||
28. Carlos Castaneda, The Teachings of Don Juan (Berkeley: University of California
|
||
Press, 1971), pp. 57-60.
|
||
29. Maurice Blanchot, L'amitie(Paris: Gallimard, 1971), p. 232.
|
||
30. F. Scott Fitzgerald, "The Crack-up," in The Crack-up. With Other UncollectedPieces,
|
||
ed. Edmund Wilson (New York: New Directions, 1956), pp. 77-78, 81.
|
||
31. [TRANS: See 12, "1227: Treatise on Nomadology," Proposition IX, pp. 416-423.]
|
||
32. Klaus Mann, Mephisto, trans. Robin Smith (New York: Random House, 1977), pp.
|
||
202-204. This kind of declaration abounds, at the very moment when the Nazis were succeed-
|
||
ing. See Goebbels's famous formulations: "In the world of absolute fatality in which Hitler
|
||
moves, nothing has meaning any longer, neither good nor bad, time nor space, and what other
|
||
people call success cannot be used as a criterion.... Hitler will probably end in catastrophe";
|
||
Hitler parle a ses generaux (Paris: Albin Michel, 1964). This catastrophism can be reconciled
|
||
with considerable satisfaction, good conscience and comfortable tranquillity. There is a
|
||
whole bureaucracy of catastrophe. On Italian fascism, one may consult, in particular, the
|
||
analysis of Maria-Antonietta Macciochi, "Sexualite feminine dans 1'ideologie fasciste," Tel
|
||
Quel, no. 66 (Summer 1976), pp. 26-42: the women's death squad, the public display of wid-
|
||
ows and mothers in mourning, the slogan (mots d'ordre) "Coffins and Cradles."
|
||
33. Paul Virilio, L 'ins'ecurite du territoire, chapter 1. Although Hannah Arendt identifies
|
||
Nazism and totalitarianism, she expressed this principle of Nazi domination: "Their idea of
|
||
domination was something that no state and no mere apparatus of violence can ever achieve,
|
||
but only a movement that is constantly kept in motion"; The Origins of Totalitarianism (New
|
||
York: Harcourt, Brace and World, 1966), p. 326; even the war, and the danger of losing the
|
||
war, acted as accelerators (pp. 325-326, 394ff., 41 Off., 462ff.).
|
||
|
||
|
||
10.1730: Becoming-Intense, Becoming-Animal,
|
||
Becoming-Imperceptible
|
||
1. On the complementarity between series and structure, and how it differs from evolu-
|
||
tionism, see Henri Daudin, Cuvier et Lamarck. Les classes zoologiques et I'idee de serie
|
||
animale, vol. 2 of Etudes d'histoire des sciences naturelles (Paris: Alcan, 1926); and Michel
|
||
Foucault, The Order of Things (New York: Vintage, 1970).
|
||
2. See Carl Jung, Symbols of Transformation, trans. R. F. C. Hull (New York: Harper,
|
||
1962), and Gaston Bachelard, Lautreamont (Paris: Librairie Jose Corti, 1939).
|
||
3. Claude Levi-Strauss, Totemism, trans. Rodney Needham (Boston: Beacon Press,
|
||
1963), p. 78.
|
||
4. Jean-Pierre Vernant in Problemes de la guerre en Grece ancienne (Civilisations et
|
||
societ'es, no. 11), ed. Jean-Pierre Vernant (The Hague: Mouton, 1968), pp. 15-16.
|
||
5. On the opposition between sacrificial series and totemic structure, see Levi-Strauss,
|
||
The Savage Mind (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1966), pp. 223-228. Despite all of his
|
||
severity toward the series, Levi-Strauss recognizes the compromise between the two themes:
|
||
structure itself implies a very concrete feeling for affinities (pp. 37-38) and is based on two
|
||
series between which it organizes homologies of relations. In particular, "becoming-
|
||
historical" can bring complications or degradations that replace these homologies with
|
||
resemblances and identifications between terms (see pp. 115ff., and what Levi-Strauss calls
|
||
the "flipside of totemism").
|
||
6. Jean Duvignaud, L'anomie. Her'esie et Subversion (Paris: Ed. Anthropos, 1973).
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 240-247 D 539
|
||
|
||
7. [TRANS: H. P. Lovecraft, "Through the Gates of the Silver Key," in The Dream-Quest
|
||
of Unknown Kadath (New York: Ballantine Books, 1970), pp. 191-192.]
|
||
8. Hugo von Hofmannsthal, Lettres du voyageur a son retour, trans. Jean-Claude
|
||
Schneider (Paris: Mercure de France, 1969), letter of May 9, 1901.
|
||
9. A nton Reiser (extracts) in La legende disperses. A nthologie du romantisme allemand
|
||
(Paris: Union Generate d'Editions, 1976), pp. 36-43.
|
||
10. [TRANS: A Universal History of Infamy, trans. Norman Thomas di Giovanni (New
|
||
York: Dutton, 1972); Jorge Luis Borges and Margarita Guerrero, Manual de zoologia
|
||
fantastica (Mexico City: Fondo de Cultura Economica, 1957), p. 9. The lobizbn is a fantastic
|
||
creature of Uruguayan folklore to which many shapes are attributed.]
|
||
11. On the man of war, his extrinsic position in relation to the State, the family, and reli-
|
||
gion, and on the becomings-animal, becomings-wild animal he enters into, see Dumezil, in
|
||
particular, Mythes et dieux des Germains (Paris: E. Leroux, 1939); Horace et les Curiaces
|
||
(Paris: Gallimard, 1942); The Destiny of the Warrior, trans. Alf Hiltebeital (Chicago: Univer-
|
||
sity of Chicago Press, 1970); Mythe et epopee (Paris: Gallimard, 1968-1973), vol. 2. One may
|
||
also refer to the studies on leopard-man societies, etc., in Black Africa; it is probable that these
|
||
societies derive from brotherhoods of warriors. But after the colonial State prohibited tribal
|
||
wars, they turned into crime associations, while still retaining their territorial and political
|
||
importance. One of the best studies on this subject is Paul Ernest Joset, Les societ'es secretes
|
||
des hommes-l'eopards en Afrique noire (Paris: Payot, 1955). The becomings-animal proper to
|
||
these groups seem to us to be very different from the symbolic relations between human and
|
||
animal as they appear in State apparatuses, but also in pre-State institutions of the totemism
|
||
type. Levi-Strauss clearly demonstrates that totemism already implies a kind of embryonic
|
||
State, to the extent that it exceeds tribal boundaries (The Savage Mind, pp. 157ff).
|
||
12. [TRANS: Kafka, "Josephine the Singer, or the Mouse Folk," in The Complete Stories of
|
||
Franz Kafka, ed. Nahum N. Glazer (New York: Schocken, 1983).]
|
||
13. Georges Canguilhem, On the Normal and the Pathological, trans. Carolyn R.
|
||
Fawcett, intro. Michel Foucault (Boston: Reidel, 1978), pp. 73-74.
|
||
14. D. H. Lawrence: "I am tired of being told there is no such animal.... If I am a giraffe,
|
||
and the ordinary Englishmen who write about me and say they know me are nice well-behaved
|
||
dogs, there it is, the animals are different.... You don't love me. The animal that I am you
|
||
instinctively dislike"; The Collected Letters ofD. H. Lawrence, vol. 2, ed. Harry T. Moore
|
||
(New York: Viking, 1962), letter to J. M. Murry, May 20, 1929, p. 1154.
|
||
15. [TRANS: Herman Melville, Moby Dick, chapter 36, "The Quarter-Deck."]
|
||
16. Rene Thorn, Structural Stability and Morphogenesis, trans. D. H. Fowler (Reading,
|
||
Mass.: Benjamin Fowler/Cummings, 1975), p. 319.
|
||
17. Edward Leach, Rethinking Anthropology (New York: Humanities Press, 1971),
|
||
pp. 18-25.
|
||
18. [TRANS: Emile Erckmann and Alexandre Chatrian, Hugues-le-loup (Paris: J.
|
||
Bonaventure, n.d.).]
|
||
19. [TRANS: Leach, Rethinking Anthropology, p. 18.]
|
||
20. See Jacques Lacarriere, Les hommes ivres de dieu (Paris: Fayard, 1975).
|
||
21. Pierre Gordon, in Sex and Religion, trans. Renee and Hilda Spodheim (New York:
|
||
Social Science Publishers, 1949), studied the role of animal-men in rites of "sacred
|
||
defloration." These animal-men impose a ritual alliance upon filiative groups, themselves
|
||
belong to brotherhoods that are on the outside or on the fringes, and are masters of contagion
|
||
and epidemic. Gordon analyzes the reaction of the villages and cities when they begin to fight
|
||
the animal-men in order to win the right to perform their own initiations and order their alli-
|
||
ances according to their respective filiations (for example, the fight against the dragon). We
|
||
find the same theme, for example, in Genevieve Calame-Griaule and Z. Ligers, "L'homme-
|
||
540 D NOTES TO PP. 247-261
|
||
|
||
hyene dans la tradition soudanaise," L'Homme, 1, 2 (May-August 1961), pp. 89-118: the
|
||
hyena-man lives on the fringes of the village, or between two villages, and can keep a lookout
|
||
in both directions. A hero, or even two heroes with a fiancee in each other's village, triumphs
|
||
over the man-animal. It is as though it were necessary to distinguish two very different states
|
||
of alliance: a demonic alliance that imposes itself from without, and imposes its law upon all
|
||
of the filiations (a forced alliance with the monster, with the man-animal), and a consensual
|
||
alliance, which is on the contrary in conformity with the law of filiations and is established
|
||
after the men of the villages have defeated the monster and have organized their own rela-
|
||
tions. This sheds new light on the question of incest. For it is not enough to say that the prohi-
|
||
bition against incest results from the positive requirements of alliance in general. There is
|
||
instead a kind of alliance that is so foreign and hostile to filiation that it necessarily takes the
|
||
position of incest (the man-animal always has a relation to incest). The second kind of alliance
|
||
prohibits incest because it can subordinate itself to the rights of filiation only by lodging itself,
|
||
precisely, between two distinct filiations. Incest appears twice, once as a monstrous power of
|
||
alliance when alliance overturns filiation, and again as a prohibited power of filiation when
|
||
filiation subordinates alliance and must distribute it among distinct lineages.
|
||
22. [TRANS: See Fitzgerald, "The Crack-up," in The Crack-up. With Other Uncollected
|
||
Pieces, ed. Edmund Wilson (New York: New Directions, 1956). The allusion to Faust is to
|
||
Goethe, Faust, Part I, lines 1323-1324.]
|
||
23. Richard Matheson and Isaac Asimov are of particular importance in this evolution
|
||
(Asimov extensively develops the theme of symbiosis).
|
||
24. Carlos Castaneda, Tales of Power (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1974), p. 159.
|
||
25. [TRANS: Lovecraft, "Through the Gates of the Silver Key," p. 197.]
|
||
26. See D. H. Lawrence, the first and second poems of Tortoises (New York: T.
|
||
Selzer, 1921).
|
||
27. [TRANS: Virginia Woolf, The Waves (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1931),
|
||
p. 139.]
|
||
28. See the Inquisition manual, Le marteau des sorciers (1486), ed. H. Institoris and J.
|
||
Sprengler (Paris: Plon, 1973), vol. l,p. 10,andvol. 2, p. 8. The first and simplest case is that of
|
||
Ulysses' companions, who believed themselves, and were believed to have been, transformed
|
||
into pigs (or again, King Nebuchadnezzar, transformed into an ox). The second case is more
|
||
complicated: Diomedes' companions do not believe they have been changed into birds, since
|
||
they are dead, but demons take over birds' bodies and pass them off as those of Diomedes'
|
||
companions. The need to distinguish this more complex case is explained by phenomena of
|
||
transfer of affects; for example, a lord on a hunting excursion cuts off the paw of a wolf and
|
||
returns home to find his wife, who had not left the house, with a hand cut off; or a man strikes
|
||
cats, and the exact wounds he inflicts turn up on women.
|
||
29. On the problem of intensities in the Middle Ages, the proliferation of theses on this
|
||
topic, the constitution of kinetics and dynamics, and the particularly important role of
|
||
Nicholas Oresme, see Pierre Duhem's classic work, Le systeme du monde (Paris: A. Hermann
|
||
& Fils, 1913-1959), vols. 7-9 (La physiqueparisienne au XlVesiede).
|
||
30. Etienne Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire, Principes dephilosophic zoologique(Paris: Picton et
|
||
Didier, 1930). And on particles and their movements, Notions synthetiques, historiques et
|
||
physiologiques dephilosophic naturelle (Paris: Denain, 1838).
|
||
31. Vladimir Slepian, "Fils de chien," Minuit, no. 7 (January 1974). We have given a
|
||
very simplified presentation of this text.
|
||
32. See Roger Dupouy, "Du masochisme," Annales Medico-psychologiques, series 12,
|
||
vol. 2 (1929), p. 405.
|
||
33. This is sometimes written "eccei ty," deriving the word from ecce, "here is." This is an
|
||
error, since Duns Scotus created the word and the concept from haec, "this thing." But it is a
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 261-265 D 541
|
||
|
||
fruitful error because it suggests a mode of individuation that is distinct from that of a thing or
|
||
a subject.
|
||
34. Michel Tournier, Les meteores (Paris: Gallimard, 1975), chapter 23, "L'ame deployee."
|
||
35. [TRANS: On Aeon versus chronos, see Deleuze, Logique du sens (Paris: Minuit, 1969),
|
||
especially series 23, pp. 190-197.]
|
||
36. Pierre Boulez, Conversations with C'elestin Deliege (London: Eulenberg Books,
|
||
1976), pp. 68-71 ("It is not possible to introduce phenomena of tempo into music that has
|
||
been calculated only electronically, in ... lengths expressed in seconds or microseconds"; p.
|
||
70).
|
||
37. Ray Bradbury, The Machineries of Joy (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1964), p. 53.
|
||
38. [TRANS: Virginia Woolf, Mrs. Dalloway (New York: Harcourt Brace and World,
|
||
1925), p. 11.]
|
||
39. Gustave Guillaume has proposed a very interesting conception of the verb. He dis-
|
||
tinguishes between an interior time, enveloped in the "process," and an exterior time per-
|
||
taining to the distinction between epochs (Epoques et niveaux temporels dans lesysteme de
|
||
la conjugation francaise, Cahiers de linguistique structurale [Universite de Laval, Quebec],
|
||
no. 4 [1955]). It seems to us that these two poles correspond respectively to the infinitive-
|
||
becoming, Aeon, and the present-being, Chronos. Each verb leans more or less in the direc-
|
||
tion of one pole or the other, not only according to its nature, but also according to the
|
||
nuances of its modes and tenses, with the exception of "becoming" and "being," which cor-
|
||
respond to both poles. Proust, in his study of Flaubert's style, shows how the imperfect tense
|
||
in Flaubert takes on the value of an infinitive-becoming: Chroniques (Paris: Gallimard,
|
||
1927), pp. 197-199.]
|
||
40. On the problem of proper names (in what sense is the proper name outside the limits
|
||
of classification and of another nature, and in what sense is it at the limit and still a part of
|
||
classification?), see Alan Henderson Gardiner, The Theory of Proper Names, 2nd ed. (New
|
||
York: Oxford University Press, 1957), and Levi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, chapter 7 ("Time
|
||
Regained"), pp. 217-244.
|
||
41. We have already encountered this problem of the indifference of psychoanalysis to
|
||
the use of the indefinite article or pronoun among children: as early as Freud, but more espe-
|
||
cially in Melanie Klein (the children she analyzes, in particular, Little Richard, speak in terms
|
||
of "a," "one," "people," but Klein exerts incredible pressure to turn them into personal and
|
||
possessive family locutions). It seems to us that Laplanche and Pontalis are the only ones in
|
||
psychoanalysis to have had any inkling that indefinites play a specific role; they protested
|
||
against any overrapid interpretive reduction: "Fantasme originaire," Les temps modernes,
|
||
no. 215 (April 1964), pp. 1861, 1868.
|
||
42. See the subjectivist or personalist conception of language in Emile Benveniste, Prob-
|
||
lems in General Linguistics, trans. Mary Elizabeth Meek (Coral Gables, Fla.: University of
|
||
Miami Press, 1971), chapters 20 ("Subjectivity in Language," pp. 223-230) and 21 ("Analyti-
|
||
cal Philosophy and Language," pp. 231-238), especially pp. 220-221 and 225-226.
|
||
43. The essential texts of Maurice Blanchot serve to refute the theory of the "shifter" and
|
||
of personology in linguistics. See L'entretien inflni (Paris: Gallimard, 1969), pp. 556-567.
|
||
And on the difference between the two propositions, "I am unfortunate" and "he is unfortu-
|
||
nate," or between "I die" and "one dies," see La part du feu (Paris: Gallimard, 1949), pp.
|
||
29-30, and The Space of Literature, trans. Ann Smock (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press,
|
||
1982), pp. 90, 122, 126. Blanchot demonstrates that in all of these cases the indefinite has
|
||
nothing to do with "the banality of daily life," which on the contrary would be on the side of
|
||
the personal pronoun.
|
||
44. [TRANS: These quotes, the first from Nietzsche, the second from Kafka, are quoted
|
||
more fully in 12, "1227: Treatise on Nomadology," p. 353.]
|
||
542 D NOTES TO PP. 265-274
|
||
|
||
45. For example, Francois Cheng, Chinese Poetic Writing, trans. Donald A. Riggs and
|
||
Jerome P. Seaton (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982), his analysis of what he calls
|
||
"the passive procedures," pp. 23-42.
|
||
46. See the statements of the "repetitive" American musicians, particularly Steve Reich
|
||
and Philip Glass.
|
||
47. Nathalie Sarraute, in The Age of Suspicion, trans. Marie Jolas (New York: Braziller,
|
||
1963), shows how Proust, for example, is torn between the two planes, in that he extracts from
|
||
his characters "the infinitesimal particles of an impalpable matter," but also glues all of the
|
||
particles back into a coherent form, slips them into the envelope of this or that character. See
|
||
pp. 50, 94-95.
|
||
48. See the distinction between the two Planes in Artaud. One of them is denounced as
|
||
the source of all illusions: The Peyote Dance (translation ofLes Tarahumaras), trans. Helen
|
||
Weaver (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1976), pp. 12-13.
|
||
49. Robert Rovini, introduction to FriedrichHoldeilin, Hyperion (Paris: 10/18,1968).
|
||
50. We have referred to an unpublished study of Kleist by Mathieu Carriere.
|
||
51. "Where did the title of your second book, A Year From Monday, come from?" "From
|
||
a plan a group of friends and I made to meet each other again in Mexico 'a year from next
|
||
Monday.' We were together on a Saturday. And we were never able to fulfil that plan. It's a
|
||
form of silence.... The very fact that our plan failed, the fact we were unable to meet does not
|
||
mean that everything failed. The plan wasn't a failure"; John Cage and Daniel Charles, For the
|
||
Birds (Boston: Marion Boyers, 1981), pp. 116-117.
|
||
52. That is why we were able to take Goethe as an example of a transcendental plane.
|
||
Goethe, however, passes for a Spinozist; his botanical and zoological studies uncover an
|
||
immanent plane of composition, which allies him to Geoffrey Saint-Hilaire (this resem-
|
||
blance has often been pointed out). Nonetheless, Goethe retains the twofold idea of a devel-
|
||
opment of form and a formation-education of the Subject; for this reason, his plane of
|
||
immanence has already crossed over to the other side, to the other pole.
|
||
53. On all of these points (proliferations-dissolutions, accumulations, indications of
|
||
speed, the affective and dynamic role), see Pierre Boulez, Conversations with C'elestin
|
||
Deliege, pp. 21 -22, 68-71. In another text, Boulez stresses a little-known aspect of Wagner:
|
||
not only are the leitmotifs freed from their subordination to the scenic characters, but the
|
||
speeds of development are freed from the hold of a "formal code" or a tempo ("Le temps
|
||
re-cherche," in Das Rheingold Programmheft, vol. I [Bayreuth, 1976], pp. 3-11). Boulez
|
||
pays homage to Proust for being one of the first to understand this floating and
|
||
transformable role of Wagnerian motifs.
|
||
54. The themes of speed and slowness are most extensively developed in The Captive:
|
||
"To understand the emotions which they arouse, and which others even better-looking do not,
|
||
we must realise that they are not immobile, but in motion, and add to their person a sign corre-
|
||
sponding to that which in physics denotes speed... to such beings, such fugitive beings, their
|
||
own nature and our anxiety fasten wings"; vol. 3 of Remembrance oj"Things Past, trans. C. K.
|
||
Moncrieff, Terence Kilmartin, and Andreas Mayor (New York: Random House, 1981), pp.
|
||
86-87, 88.
|
||
55. [TRANS: The word translated as "proximity" is voisinage, which Deleuze and Guattari
|
||
draw from set theory. The corresponding mathematical term in English is "neighborhood."]
|
||
56. Louis Wolfson, Leschizo et les langues, preface by Gilles Deleuze (Paris: Gallimard,
|
||
1970).
|
||
57. Rene Scherer and Guy Hocquenghem, Co-ire, Recherche, no. 22 (1976), pp. 76-82:
|
||
see their critique of Bettelheim's thesis, which considers the becomings-animal of the child
|
||
merely an autistic symbolism that expresses the anxiety of the parents more than any reality
|
||
of the child. See Bruno Bettelheim, The Empty Fortress (New York: Free Press, 1967).
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 274-287 D 543
|
||
|
||
58. Philippe Gavi, "Les philosophes du fantastique," Liberation, March 31, 1977. For
|
||
the preceding cases, what we must arrive at is an understanding of certain so-called neurotic
|
||
behaviors as a function of becomings-animal, instead of relegating becomings-animal to a
|
||
psychoanalytic interpretation of behaviors. We saw this in relation to masochism (and Lolito
|
||
explains that the origin of his feats lies in certain masochistic experiences; a fine text by Chris-
|
||
tian Maurel conjugates a becoming-monkey and a becoming-horse in a masochistic pairing).
|
||
Anorexia would also have to be understood from the point of view of becoming-animal.
|
||
59. See Newsweek, May 16, 1977, p. 57.
|
||
60. See Trost, Visible et invisible (Paris: Arcanes) and Librement mecanique (Paris:
|
||
Minotaure): "She was simultaneously, in her sensible reality and in the ideal prolongation of
|
||
her lines, like the projection of a human group yet to come."
|
||
61. See the examples of structural explanation proposed by Jean-Pierre Vernant, in
|
||
Problem.es de la guerre en Grece ancienne, pp. 15-16.
|
||
62. On transvestism in primitive societies, see Bruno Bettelheim (who offers an
|
||
identificatory psychological interpretation), Symbolic Wounds (Glencoe, 111.: Free Press,
|
||
1954), and especially Gregory Bateson (who proposes an original structural interpretation),
|
||
Naven: A Survey of the Problems Suggested by a Composite Picture of the Culture of a New
|
||
Guinea Tribe Drawn from Three Points of Views, 2nd ed. (Stanford, Calif: Stanford Univer-
|
||
sity Press, 1958).
|
||
63. Francois Cheng, Chinese Poetic Writing, p. 13.
|
||
64. The Diary of Virginia Woolf, ed. Anne Olivier Bell (London: Hogarth Press, 1980),
|
||
vol. 3, p. 209: "The idea has come to me that what I want now to do is to saturate every
|
||
atom." On all of these points, we make use of an unpublished study on Virginia Woolf by
|
||
Fanny Zavin.
|
||
65. [TRANS: Sdren Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling, trans. Walter Lowrie (Princeton,
|
||
N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1954), p. 104.]
|
||
66. Ibid., .p. 49. Fear and Trembling seems to us to be Kierkegaard's greatest book
|
||
because of the way it formulates the problem of movement and speed, not only in its content,
|
||
but also in its'style and composition.
|
||
67. [TRANS: Fear and Trembling, p. 61.]
|
||
68. Carlos Castaneda, Journey to Ixtlan (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1973), pp. 297ff.
|
||
69. Leslie Fiedler, The Return of the Vanishing American (New York: Stein and Day,
|
||
1968). Fiedler explains the secret alliance of the white American with the black or the Indian
|
||
by a desire to escape the molar form and ascendancy of the American woman.
|
||
70. Henri Michaux, Miserable Miracle: Mescaline, trans. Louise Varese (San Francisco:
|
||
City Lights, 1963), p. 87: "The horror of it was that I was nothing but a line. In normal life one
|
||
is a sphere, a sphere that surveys panoramas.... Now only a line... the accelerated line I had
|
||
become." See Michaux's line drawings. In the first eighty pages of The Major Ordeals of the
|
||
Mind, and the Countless Minor Ones, trans. Richard Howard (New York: Harcourt Brace
|
||
Jovanovich, 1974), Michaux further develops the analysis of speeds, molecular perceptions,
|
||
and "microphenomena" or "microoperations."
|
||
71. [TRANS: A rewriting of Freud's famous phrase, "Where id was, there ego shall be"
|
||
(New Introductory Lectures, Standard Edition, vol. 22, p. 80), and Lacan's earlier rewriting of
|
||
it in "The Freudian Thing," Ecrits, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Norton, 1977), pp. 128-
|
||
129,136.]
|
||
72. Artaud, The Peyote Dance, pp. 12-14.
|
||
73. Michaux, Miserable Miracle ("Remaining Master of One's Speeds," pp. 87-88).
|
||
74. On the possibilities of silicon, and its relation to carbon from the point of view of
|
||
organic chemistry, see the article, "Silicium," in the Encyclopedia Universalis.
|
||
75. Luc de Heusch shows that it is the man of war who brings the secret: he thinks, eats,
|
||
544 D NOTES TO PP. 287-293
|
||
|
||
loves, judges, arrives in secret, while the man of the State proceeds publicly. See Le mi ivre ou
|
||
I'origine de I'Etat (Paris: Gallimard, 1972). The idea of the State secret is a late one and
|
||
assumes that the war machine has been appropriated by the State apparatus.
|
||
76. In particular, Georg Simmel. See The Sociology ofGeorg Simmel, trans. Kurt H.
|
||
Wolff (Glencoe, 111.: Free Press, 1950), chapter 3.
|
||
77. Paul Ernest Joset clearly notes these two aspects of the secret initiatory society, the
|
||
Mambela of the Congo: on the one hand, its relation of influence over the traditional political
|
||
leaders, which gets to the point of a transfer of social powers; and on the other hand, its de
|
||
facto relation with the Anioto, as a secret hindsociety of crime or leopard-men (even if the
|
||
Anioto are of another origin than the Mambela). See Les societes secretes des hommes-
|
||
leopards en Afrique noire, chapter 5.
|
||
78. On the psychoanalytic conceptions of the secret, see Du secret, Nouvelle revue de
|
||
psychanalyse, no. 14 (Fall 1976); and for the evolution of Freud on this subject, the article by
|
||
Claude Girard, "Le secret aux origines," pp. 55-83.
|
||
79. Bernard Pingaud shows, on the basis of the exemplary text of Henry James, "The
|
||
Figure in the Carpet" [The Novels and Tales of Henry James (New York: C. Scribner's Sons,
|
||
1907-1917), vol. 15—Trans.], how the secret jumps from content to form, and escapes both:
|
||
Du secret, pp. 247-249. This text has been frequently commented upon from the viewpoint of
|
||
psychoanalysis; above all, J.-B. Pontalis, Apres Freud (Paris: Gallimard, 1968). But psycho-
|
||
analysis remains prisoner to a necessarily disguised content and a necessarily symbolic form
|
||
(structure, absent cause ...), at a level that defines both the unconscious and language. That is
|
||
why, in its aesthetic or literary applications, it misses the secret in an author, as well as the
|
||
secret o/an author. The same goes for the secret of Oedipus: they concern themselves with the
|
||
first two kinds of secret but not with the second, which is nevertheless the most important.
|
||
80. On the fogginess of the idea of majority, see Kenneth Arrow's two famous themes,
|
||
"the Condorcet effect" and the "theorem of collective decision."
|
||
81. See William Faulkner, Intruder in the Dust (New York: Vintage, 1948), p. 216. Speak-
|
||
ing of Southern whites after the Civil War (not only the poor but also the old monied families),
|
||
Faulkner writes, "We are in the position of the German after 1933 who had no other alterna-
|
||
tive but to be a Nazi or a Jew."
|
||
82. The subordination of the line to the point is clearly evident in the arborescent
|
||
schemas: see Julien Pacotte, Le reseau arborescent, scheme primordial de la pensee (Paris:
|
||
Hermann, 1936), and the status of centered or hierarchical systems according to Pierre
|
||
Rosenthiehl and Jean Petitot, "Automate asocial et systemes acentres," Communications, no.
|
||
22 (1974), pp. 45-62. The arborescent schema of majority could be presented as follows:
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
83. A line of becoming, in relation to the localizable connection of A and B (distance), or
|
||
in relation to their contiguity:
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 293-298 D 545
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
84. The Diary of Virginia Woolf, vol. 3, p. 236 (Wednesday, November 28, 1928). The
|
||
same thing applies to the works of Kafka, in which childhood blocks function as the opposite
|
||
of childhood memories. Proust's case is more complicated because he performs a mixture of
|
||
the two. The situation of the psychoanalyst is to grasp memories or phantasies, but never
|
||
childhood blocks.
|
||
85. For example, in the system of memory, the formation of a memory implies a diago-
|
||
nal that turns present A into representation A' in relation to the new present B, and into A" in
|
||
relation to C, etc.:
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
See Edmund Husserl, The Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness, ed. Martin
|
||
Heidegger, trans. James S. Churchill, intro. Calvin O. Schrag (Bloomington: Indiana Univer-
|
||
sity Press, 1964), pp. 48-50.
|
||
86. Friedrich Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (New York:
|
||
Cambridge University Press, 1983), "On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life,"
|
||
sec. 1, pp. 63-64.
|
||
87. On all of these themes, see Pierre Boulez. (1) On how transversals always tend to
|
||
escape horizontal and vertical coordinates of music, sometimes even drawing "virtual lines,"
|
||
see Notes of an Apprenticeship, ed. Paule Thevenin, trans. Robert Weinstock (New York:
|
||
Knopf, 1968), pp. 231 -232,295-301,382-383. (2) On the idea of the sound block or "block of
|
||
duration," in relation to this transversal, see Boulez on Music Today, trans. Susan Bradshaw
|
||
and Richard Bennett (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 55-59. (3) On
|
||
the distinction between points and blocks, "punctual sets," and "aggregative sets" with vary-
|
||
ing individuality, see "Senate que me veux-tu?", Mediations, no. 7 (1964). The hatred of
|
||
memory appears frequently in Boulez; see "Eloge de 1'amnesie," Musique enjeu, no. 4 (1971),
|
||
pp. 5-14, and "J'ai horreur du souvenir," in Roger Desormiere et son temps, ed. Denise Mayer
|
||
and Pierre Souvtchinsky (Monaco: Ed. du Rocher, 1966). Confining ourselves to contempo-
|
||
rary examples, one finds analogous declarations in Stravinsky, Cage, Berio. Of course, there is
|
||
a musical memory that is tied to coordinates and is exercised in social settings (getting up,
|
||
going to bed, beating a retreat). But the perception of a musical "phrase" appeals less to mem-
|
||
ory, even of the reminiscence type, than to an extension or contraction of perception of the
|
||
encounter type. It should be studied how each musician sets in motion veritable blocks of for-
|
||
getting: for example, what Jean Barraque calls "slices of forgetting" and "absent develop-
|
||
ments" in the work of Debussy; Debussy (Paris: Seuil, 1977), pp. 169-171. One can refer to a
|
||
general study by Daniel Charles, "La musiqueetl'oubli," Traverses, no.4 (1977), pp. 14-23.
|
||
88. Roland Barthes, "Rasch," in The Responsibility of Forms, trans. Richard Howard
|
||
(New York: Hill and Wang, 1985), pp. 300-302, 308-309.
|
||
89. There are many differences among painters, in all respects, but also a common
|
||
546 D NOTES TO PP. 298-305
|
||
|
||
movement: see Wassily Kandinsky, Point and Line to Plane in vol. 2 of Complete Writings on
|
||
Art, ed. Kenneth C. Lindsay and Peter Verge (Boston: G. K. Hall, 1982), pp. 524-700; and Paul
|
||
Klee, On Modern Art, trans. Paul Findlay, intro. Herbert Reed (London: Faber, 1966). The
|
||
aim of statements like those of Mondrian on the exclusive value of the vertical and the hori-
|
||
zontal is to show the conditions under which the vertical and horizontal are sufficient to cre-
|
||
ate a transversal, which does not even have to be drawn; for example, coordinates of unequal
|
||
thickness intersect inside the frame and extend outside the frame, opening a "dynamic axis"
|
||
running transversally (see Michel Butor's comments in Repertoire [Paris: Minuit, 1960- ], vol.
|
||
3, "Le carre et son habitant"). One can also consult Michel Fried's article on Pollock's line,
|
||
Three American Painters (Cambridge, Mass.: Fogg Art Museum, 1965), and Henry Miller's
|
||
discussion of Nash's line, On Turning Eighty (London: Village Press, 1973).
|
||
90. "There was something tense, exasperated to the point of intolerable anger, in his
|
||
good-humored breast, as he played the finely-spun peace-music. The more exquisite the
|
||
music, the more perfectly he produced it, in sheer bliss; and at the same time, the more intense
|
||
was the maddened exasperation within him"; D. H. Lawrence, Aaron's Rod (New York:
|
||
Thomas Seltzer, 1922), p. 16.
|
||
91. Although Luciano Berio indicates otherwise, it seems to us that his work, Visage, is
|
||
composed according to the three states of faciality: first, a multiplicity of sound bodies and
|
||
silhouettes, then a short symphonic and dominant organization of the face, and finally a
|
||
launching of probe-heads in all directions. However, there is no question here of music "imi-
|
||
tating" the face and its avatars, or of the voice constituting a metaphor. Instead, the sounds
|
||
accelerate the deterritorialization of the face, giving it a properly acoustical power, and the
|
||
face reacts musically by in turn inducing a deterritorialization of the voice. This is a molecu-
|
||
lar face, produced by electronic music. The voice precedes the face, itself forms the face for
|
||
an instant, and outlives it, increasing in speed—on the condition that it is unarticulated,
|
||
asignifying, asubjective.
|
||
92. Will Grohman, Paul Klee (New York: Harry N. Abrams, n.d.): "Somewhat paradoxi-
|
||
cally he remarked that perhaps it had been his good fortune to develop painting, at least on the
|
||
formal plane, to the stage reached in music by Mozart" (p. 71).
|
||
93. Dominique Fernandez, La rose des Tudors (Paris: Julliard, 1976) (and the novel
|
||
Porporino [Paris: Grasset, 1974]). Fernandez cites pop music as a timid return to great English
|
||
vocal music. It would be necessary to take into consideration techniques of circular breathing,
|
||
in which one sings breathing in as well as out, or of sound filtering using zones of resonance
|
||
(nose, forehead, cheekbones—a properly musical use of the face).
|
||
94. Marcel More, Le dieu Mozart et le monde des oiseaux (Paris: Gallimard, 1971).
|
||
95. As we have seen, imitation can be conceived either as a resemblance of terms culmi-
|
||
nating in an archetype (series), or as a correspondence of relations constituting a symbolic
|
||
order (structure); but becoming is not reducible to either of these. The concept of mimesis is
|
||
not only inadequate, it is radically false.
|
||
96. Francois Truffaut, Hitchcock(New York: Simon and Schuster, 1967): "I took the dra-
|
||
matic licence of not having the birds scream at all" (p. 224).
|
||
97. See Ernesto de Martino, La terredu remords (Paris: Gallimard, 1966), pp. 142-170.
|
||
Martino, however, retains an interpretation based on the archetype, imitation, and
|
||
identification.
|
||
98. Jean Claude Larouche, Alexis le trotteur (Montreal: Ed. du Jour, 1971). They quote
|
||
this account: "He didn't play music with his mouth like one of us; he had a huge harmonica we
|
||
couldn't even play. . . . When he played with us, he would decide all of a sudden to double us.
|
||
In other words, he doubled the beat; in the time we played one beat, he played two, which
|
||
required extraordinary wind" (p. 95).
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 306-315 D 547
|
||
|
||
99. [TRANS: See Kafka, The Castle, trans. Willa and Edwin Muir (New York: Knopf,
|
||
1976).]
|
||
100. [TRANS: See 7, "Year Zero: Faciality," pp. 167-191.]
|
||
101. Andre Tetry, Les outils chez les etres vivants (Paris: Gallimard, 1948), the chapter on
|
||
"musical instruments," with bibliography. An animal's movement or labor may make noise,
|
||
but we speak of a musical instrument whenever animals use apparatuses whose sole function
|
||
is to produce various sounds (the musical character, to the extent that it is determinable, is
|
||
quite variable, as is the case with the vocal apparatus of birds; there are veritable virtuosos
|
||
among insects). From this standpoint, we distinguish: (1) stridulatory apparatuses, of the
|
||
stringed instrument type: the rubbing of a rigid surface against another surface (insects, crus-
|
||
taceans, spiders, scorpions, pedipalps); (2) percussive apparatuses, of the drum, cymbal, or
|
||
xylophone type: direct application of muscles to a vibratory membrane (crickets and certain
|
||
fish). Not only is there an infinite variety of apparatuses and sounds, but the same animal
|
||
varies its rhythm, tonality, intensity according to still more mysterious urgencies. "It then be-
|
||
comes a song of anger, anxiety, fear, triumph, love. When there is keen excitation, the rhythm
|
||
of the stridulation varies: in Crioceris lilii, the frequency of the rubbing goes from 228 strokes
|
||
per minute to 550 or more."
|
||
102. Gisele Brelet, "Musique contemporaine en France," in Histoire de la musique, ed.
|
||
Roland Manuel, "Pleiade" (Paris: Gallimard, 1977), vol. 2, pp. 1166.
|
||
103. A text by Henry Miller for Varese, The Air-Conditioned Nightmare (New York: New
|
||
Directions, 1945), pp. 176-177.
|
||
|
||
11.1837: Of the Refrain
|
||
1. Fernand Deligny, Voix et Voir, Recherches, no. 8 (April 1975), on the way in which,
|
||
among autistic children, a "line of drift" deviates from the customary path and begins to
|
||
"vibrate," "toss about," "yaw."
|
||
2. Paul Klee, On Modern Art, trans. Paul Findlay, intro. Herbert Reed (London: Faber,
|
||
1966), p. 43 [translation modified to agree with the French version cited by the authors]. See
|
||
Henri Maldiney's comments in Regard, parole, espace (Lausanne: L'Age d'homme, 1973),
|
||
pp. 149-151.
|
||
3. On the musical nome, the ethos, and the ground or land, notably in polyphony, see
|
||
Joseph Samson in Histoire de la musique, ed. Roland Manuel (Paris: Gallimard, 1977), vol.
|
||
2, pp. 1168-1172. One may also refer to the role in Arab music of the "maqam," which is
|
||
both a modal type and a melodic formula: Simon Jargy, La musique arabe (Paris: PUF,
|
||
1971), pp. 55ff.
|
||
4. Gaston Bachelard, La dialectique de la duree (Paris: Bovin, 1936), pp. 128-129.
|
||
Emphasis added.
|
||
5. Jakob Johann von Uexkull, Mondesanimauxet mondehumain (Paris: Gonthier, 1965).
|
||
6. "Their glorious dress is constant.... The coloring of coral fish is distributed in large,
|
||
sharply contrasting areas of the body. This is quite different from the color patterns not only
|
||
of most fresh-water fish but of nearly all less aggressive and less territorial fish.... Like the
|
||
colors of the coral fish, the song of the nightingale signals from a distance to all members of its
|
||
species that a territory has found an owner." Konrad Lorenz, On Aggression, trans. Marjorie
|
||
Kerr Wilson (New York: Harcourt, Brace and World, 1966), pp. 19-20.
|
||
7. Irenaus Eibl-Eibesfeldt, Ethology, trans. Erich Klinghammer (New York: Holt,
|
||
Rinehart and Winston, 1975): on monkeys, p. 487; on rabbits, p. 346; on birds, p. 171: "Zebra
|
||
finches with colorful plumage maintain a certain distance from one another, while all-white
|
||
birds of the same species perch much closer together."
|
||
548 D NOTES TO PP. 315-325
|
||
|
||
8. W. H. Thorpe, Learning and Instinct in Animals (London: Methuen, 1956), p. 364
|
||
(Fig. 2).
|
||
9. Lorenz has a constant tendency to present territoriality as an effect of intraspecific
|
||
aggression; see OnAgression, pp. 38-39, 42-43, 53-54, 161-162.
|
||
10. On the aesthetic and vital primacy of "having," see Gabriel Tarde, L'opposition
|
||
universelle (Paris: Alcan, 1897).
|
||
11. Details on Messiaen's conceptions of bird song, his evaluation of its aesthetic quali-
|
||
ties, and his methods for both reproducing it and using it as a material are to be found in
|
||
Claude Samuel, Conversations with Olivier Messiaen, trans. Felix Aprahamian (London:
|
||
Stainer and Bell, 1976), and in Antoine Golea, Rencontres avec Olivier Messiaen (Paris:
|
||
Julliard, 1961). In particular, on why Messiaen does not use a tape recorder or sonograph as
|
||
ornithologists usually do, see Samuel, pp. 61-63.
|
||
12. [TRANS: Lorenz, On Aggression, p. 87.]
|
||
13. On all of these points, see Claude Samuel, Conversations, chapter 4. On the "rhythmic
|
||
character," see pp. 36-39.
|
||
14. Pierre Boulez, "Le temps re-cherche," in Das Rheingold Programmheft, vol. 1
|
||
(Bayreuth, 1976), pp. 5-15.
|
||
15. [TRANS: Proust, The Captive, vol. 3 of Remembrance of Things Past, trans. C. K. Scott
|
||
Moncrief, Terence Kilmartin, and Andreas Mayor (New York: Random House, 1981), p. 156.
|
||
Translation modified.]
|
||
16. On mannerism and chaos, baroque dances, and the relation of schizophrenia to man-
|
||
nerism and dance, see Evelyne Sznycer, "Droit de suite baroque," in Schizophrenic et art, ed.
|
||
Leo Navratil (Paris: Ed. Complexe, 1978).
|
||
17. Lorenz, On Aggression, pp. 39-40. On the three rhythmic personages defined respec-
|
||
tively as active, passive, and witness, see Messiaen and Golea, Rencontres, pp. 90-91.
|
||
18. [TRANS: Mircea Eliade, Patterns in Comparative Religion, trans. Rosemary Sheed
|
||
(New York: World, 1963), pp. 242-243.]
|
||
19. [TRANS: This "close embrace" of energies recalls Proust's description of Vinteuil's lit-
|
||
tle phrase; The Captive, p. 262.]
|
||
20. On "the primary intuition of the earth as a religious form" (p. 242), see Eliade, Pat-
|
||
terns in Comparative Religion, pp. 245ff; on the center of the territory, see pp. 374ff. Eliade
|
||
makes it clear that the center is simultaneously outside the territory, very difficult to attain,
|
||
and inside the territory, within our immediate reach.
|
||
21. Biologists have often made a distinction between two factors of transformation: those
|
||
of the mutation type, and processes of isolation or separation, which may be genetic, geo-
|
||
graphical, or even psychical. Territoriality would be a factor of the second type. See Lucien
|
||
Cuenot, L'espece(Paris: G. Doin, 1936).
|
||
22. Paul Geroudet, Lespassereaux, 3 vols. (Paris: Delachaux et Niestle, 1951-1957), vol.
|
||
2, pp. 88-94.
|
||
23. In On Aggression, Lorenz makes a clear distinction between "anonymous flocks" such
|
||
as schools of fish, which form milieu blocks; "local groups," where recognition occurs only
|
||
inside the territory and, at its strongest, between "neighbors"; and finally, societies founded
|
||
on an autonomous "bond."
|
||
24. K. Immelmann, Beitrage zu einer vergleichenden Biologic australischer Prachtflnken,
|
||
Zoologische Jahrbucher; Abteilung fur Systematik, Okologie und Geographic de Tiere, 90
|
||
(1962).
|
||
25. Eibl-Eibesfeldt, Ethology, p. 225: "Carrying nesting material for nest building evolved
|
||
into the male courtship actions using grass stems. This was again secondarily reduced in some
|
||
species and became rudimentary, while at the same time the song, which originally served the
|
||
function of staking out a territory, also underwent a change in function. These animals are gre-
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 325-329 D 549
|
||
|
||
garious and are not really territorial. Instead of courting with grass stems, these males sing
|
||
softly while sitting next to the females." Eibl-Eibesfeldt, however, interprets the grass-stem
|
||
behavior as a vestige.
|
||
26. See L'Odyssee sous-marine de I'equipe Cousteau, film no. 36, La marche des
|
||
langoustes (L. R. A.), commentary by Cousteau-Diole: spiny lobsters along the northern coast
|
||
of the Yucatan Peninsula sometimes leave their territories. They assemble, at first in small
|
||
groups, before the first winter storm, and before any sign detectable by human instruments.
|
||
When the storm comes, they form long march processions, in single file, with a leader that is
|
||
periodically relieved and a rearguard (the speed of the march is five-eighths of a mile per hour,
|
||
for sixty miles or more). This migration does not seem to be associated with egg laying, which
|
||
does not take place until six months later. Hernnkind, a lobster specialist, hypothesizes that
|
||
this is a "vestige" from the last ice age (more than 10,000 years ago). Cousteau leans toward a
|
||
more current interpretation, even mentioning the possibility that it is a premonition of a new
|
||
ice age. The factual issue is that in this exceptional case the lobsters' territorial assemblage
|
||
opens onto a social assemblage, and that this social assemblage is connected to cosmic forces,
|
||
or, as Cousteau says, "pulsations of the earth." But "the enigma remains entirely unsolved,"
|
||
all the more so because this lobster procession occasions a slaughter by fishermen, and also
|
||
because lobsters cannot be tagged since they shed their shells.
|
||
27. The best book of nursery rhymes, and on nursery rhymes, seems to be Les complines
|
||
de langue francaise, with the commentary by editors Jean Beaucomot, Franck Guibat, et al.
|
||
(Paris: Seghers, 1970). The territorial character of nursery rhymes appears in such privileged
|
||
examples as "Pimpanicaille," two distinct versions of which exist in Gruyeres on "the two
|
||
sides of the street" (pp. 27-28); but it is a nursery rhyme in the strict sense only when there is a
|
||
distribution of specialized roles in a game, and the formation of an autonomous game assem-
|
||
blage that reorganizes the territory.
|
||
28. Nikolaas Tinbergen, The Study of Instinct (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1969).
|
||
29. On the one hand, the experiments of W. R. Hess have shown that there is not a cere-
|
||
bral center but instead points that are concentrated in one zone and disseminated in another,
|
||
and are capable of inciting the same effect; conversely, the effect may change according to the
|
||
duration and intensity of the excitation of a point. On the other hand, E. von Hoist's experi-
|
||
ments on "deafferented" fish demonstrate the importance of central nervous coordination in
|
||
fin rhythms; Tinbergen's schema takes these interactions into account only secondarily. The
|
||
hypothesis of a "population of oscillators" or a "pack of oscillating molecules" forming sys-
|
||
tems of articulation from the inside, independent of any common measure, is most compel-
|
||
ling in view of the problem of circadian rhythms. See A. Reinberg, "La chronobiologie,"
|
||
Sciences, vol. 1(1970); and T. van den Dreissche and A. Reinberg, "Rythmes biologiques," in
|
||
Encyclopedia Universalis, vol. 14, p. 572: "It does not seem possible to reduce the mechanism
|
||
of circadian rhythmicity to a simple sequence of elementary processes."
|
||
30. Jacques Monod, Chance and Necessity, trans. Austryn Wainhouse (New York: Vin-
|
||
tage, 1972): on indirect interactions and their nonlinear character, pp. 69-71 and 76-77; on
|
||
corresponding molecules that are least two-headed, pp. 68-69; on the inhibiting or releasing
|
||
character of these interactions, pp. 63-67. Circadian rhythms also depend on these character-
|
||
istics (see the chart in the Encyclopedia Universalis under "Rhythmes biologiques").
|
||
31. Eugene Dupreel elaborated a set of original notions, "consistency" (in relation to
|
||
"precariousness"), "consolidation," "interval," "intercalation." See Theorie de la consolida-
|
||
tion: La cause et I'intervalle (Brussels: M. Lamertin, 1933); La consistance et la probabilit'e
|
||
objective (Brussels: Academic Royale de Belgique, 1961); Esquisse d'une philosophie des
|
||
valeurs (Paris: Alcan, 1939); Bachelard, in La dialectique de la duree, draws on Dupreel.
|
||
32. [TRANS: The Diary of Virginia Woolf, ed. Anne Olivier Bell (London: Hogarth Press,
|
||
1980), vol. 3, p. 209.]
|
||
550 D NOTES TO PP. 330-342
|
||
|
||
33. On the song of the chaffinch, and the distinction between the "subsong" and "full
|
||
song," see Thorpe, Learning and Instinct, pp. 420-426.
|
||
34. Alexander James Marshall, Bower-Birds (Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1954).
|
||
35. Thorpe, Learning and Instinct, p. 426. In this respect, songs present an entirely differ-
|
||
ent problem than calls, which are often not very differentiated, and quite similar from species
|
||
to species.
|
||
36. Raymond Ruyer, Lagenesedesformes vivantes (Paris: Flammarion, 1958), chapter 7.
|
||
37. In particular, on widow birds (Viduinae), parasitic birds whose territorial song is
|
||
species-specific and whose courtship song is learned from their adoptive host, see J. Nicolai,
|
||
Der Brutparasitismus der Viduinae, Z. Tierps., vol. 21 (1964).
|
||
38. The participation of a black hole in an assemblage appears in numerous examples of
|
||
inhibition, or fascination-ecstasy, notably in the peacock: "The male peacock spreads his tail
|
||
feathers.... Then he bends the spread-out tail forward and points downward with his beak,
|
||
while his head is still upright. As a result, the female runs in front of him and pecks in a search-
|
||
ing manner on the ground in the focal point of the concave mirrorlike shape of the fanned tail.
|
||
The male peacock points, so to speak, with his fanned-out tail toward imaginary food," Eibl-
|
||
Eibesfeldt, Ethology, p. 116. But the peacock's focal point is no more imaginary than the
|
||
finch's grass stem is a vestige or symbol; it is an assemblage converter, the passage to a court-
|
||
ship assemblage, in this instance, effected by a black hole.
|
||
39. Ruyer, La genese des formes vivantes, pp. 54ff.
|
||
40. Francow Meyer, Probl'ematique de revolution (Paris: PUF, 1954).
|
||
41. Monod, Chance and Necessity.
|
||
42. Female birds, which do not normally sing, start singing when they are administered
|
||
male sex hormones, "and they will sing the song of the species on which they have become
|
||
imprinted." Eibl-Eibesfeldt, Ethology, p. 265.
|
||
43. [TRANS: Klee, On Modern Art, p. 43. Translation modified to agree with the French
|
||
translation cited by the authors.]
|
||
44. Klee, On Modern Art, p. 55 [translation modified—Trans.].
|
||
45. See Renaissance, manierisme, baroque, Actes du Xle stage international de Tours
|
||
(Paris: Vrin, 1972), part 1, "Periodizations."
|
||
46. Proust, Swann's Way, in vol. 1 of Remembrance of Things Past, p. 382 [translation
|
||
modified—Trans.].
|
||
47. See the ambiguous role of the friend at the end of Das Lied von der Erde. Or Eichen-
|
||
dorff s poem in Schumann's lied, Zwielicht(\n Opus 39): "If you have a friend in this world, do
|
||
not trust him at this hour, for even if he is kind in eye and mouth, he dreams of war in deceitful
|
||
peace." (On the problem of the One-Alone, or "solitary Being," in German romanticism, see
|
||
Holderlin, "Le cours et la destination de 1'homme en general," trans. Emmanuel Marineau,
|
||
Po'esie, no. 4 [1978], pp. 6-22.)
|
||
48. "The people in Mussorgsky's Boris do not form a true crowd; at times one group sings,
|
||
then another, and then a third, each in turn, and most often in unison. As for the people in
|
||
Mditres chanteurs, it is not a crowd but an army that is powerfully organized in the German
|
||
manner and marches in rows. What I would like is something sparser, more divided, more
|
||
relaxed, more impalpable, something in appearance inorganic and yet at bottom ordered."
|
||
Quoted by Jean Barraque, Debussy (Paris: Seuil, 1977), p. 159. This problem—how to do a
|
||
crowd—obviously recurs in other arts also, painting, cinema, etc. One may refer in particular
|
||
to the films of Eisenstein, which proceed by this type of very special group individuation.
|
||
49. On the relations between the cry, the voice, the instrument, and music as "theater," see
|
||
Berio's statements introducing his records. One will recall the eminently musical Nietzschean
|
||
theme of a multiple cry of all superior men, at the end of Thus Spoke Zarathustra.
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 342-350 D 551
|
||
|
||
50. On Bartok's chromaticism, see Gisele Brelet's study in Histoire de la musique, vol. 2,
|
||
pp. 1036-1072.
|
||
51. In his book on Debussy, Barraque analyzes the "dialogue of the wind and the sea" in
|
||
terms offerees instead of themes: pp. 153-154. See Messiaen's statements on his own works:
|
||
sounds are no longer anything more "than vulgar means of expression intended to make dura-
|
||
tions measurable."
|
||
52. Odile Vivier describes Varese's procedures for treating sound matter, in Varese (Paris:
|
||
Seuil, 1973): the use of pure sounds acting as a prism (p. 36); mechanisms of projection onto a
|
||
plane (pp. 45 and 50); non-octave-forming scales (p. 75); the "ionization" procedure (pp.
|
||
98ff.); the theme of sound molecules, the transformations of which are determined by forces
|
||
or energies (passim).
|
||
53. See the interview with Stockhausen on the role of synthesizers and the effectively
|
||
"cosmic" dimension of music, in Le Monde, July 21,1977: "Work with very limited materials
|
||
and integrate the universe into them through a continuous variation." Richard Pinhas has
|
||
written an excellent analysis of the possibilities of synthesizers in this regard, in relation to
|
||
pop music: "Input, Output," inAlem, no. 10 (1977).
|
||
54. The definition of fuzzy aggregates brings up all kinds of problems because one cannot
|
||
appeal to a local determination: "The set of all objects on this table" is obviously not a fuzzy
|
||
set. Mathematicians concerned with the question speak only of "fuzzy subsets" because the
|
||
reference set must always be an ordinary set. See Arnold Kaufmann, Introduction to the The-
|
||
ory of Fuzzy Subsets, foreword L. A. Zadeh, trans. D. L. Swanson (New York: Academic Press,
|
||
1975), and Hourya Sinacoeur, "Logique et mathematique du flou," Critique, no. 372 (May
|
||
1978), pp. 512-525. In considering fuzziness as the characteristic of certain sets, our point of
|
||
departure was a functional, as opposed to a local, definition: sets of heterogeneous elements
|
||
that have a territorial, or rather territorializing, function. But this is a nominal definitiion that
|
||
does not take "what happened" into account. The real definition can come only at the level of
|
||
processes affecting the fuzzy set; a set is fuzzy if its elements belong to it only by virtue of spe-
|
||
cific operations of consistency and consolidation, which themselves follow a special logic.
|
||
55. Paul Klee, On Modern Art, p. 53: "The legend of the childishness of my drawing must
|
||
have originated from those linear compositions of mine in which I tried to combine a concrete
|
||
image, say that of a man, with the pure representation of the linear element. Had I wished to
|
||
present man 'as he is,' then I should have had to use such a bewildering confusion of lines that
|
||
pure elementary representation would have been out of the question. The result would have
|
||
been vagueness beyond recognition."
|
||
56. Paul Virilio, L'insecurite du territoire (Paris: Stock, 1975), p. 49. Henry Miller devel-
|
||
ops this theme in The Time of the Assassins. A Study ofRimbaud(NoTfo\k, Conn.: J. Laughlin,
|
||
1956), and in the text he wrote for Varese, "Lost! Saved!" (The Air-Conditioned Nightmare
|
||
[New York: New Directions, 1945]). It is undoubtedly Miller who has taken the modern figure
|
||
of the writer as cosmic artisan the farthest, particularly in Sexus.
|
||
57. On the relation of colors to sound, see Messiaen and Samuel, Conversations, pp.
|
||
15-17. Messiaen faults drug users for oversimplifying the relation, which they make into a
|
||
relation between a noise and a color, instead of isolating complexes of sounds-durations and
|
||
complexes of colors.
|
||
58. On the crystal, or the crystalline type, added and subtracted values, retrograde
|
||
motion, see also Messiaen's texts in Samuel, Conversations, and those of Paul Klee in his
|
||
diary, The Diaries of Paul Klee, 1898-1918, ed. and intro. Felix Klee (Berkeley: University of
|
||
California Press, 1964).
|
||
59. See Roland-Manuel's article, "L'evolution de 1'harmonie en France et le renouveau de
|
||
1880" (pp. 867-879), and the article by Delage on Chabrier (pp. 831-840), in Histoire de la
|
||
musique, vol. 2. And especially, Brelet's article on Bartok: "Are not the difficulties learned
|
||
552 D NOTES TO PP. 350-355
|
||
|
||
music experiences in utilizing popular music due to this antinomy between melody and
|
||
theme? Popular music is melody, in its fullest sense, melody persuading us that it is self-
|
||
sufficient and is in fact synonymous with music itself. How could it not refuse to bend to the
|
||
learned development of a musical work pursuing its own ends? Many symphonies inspired by
|
||
folklore are only symphonies about a popular theme, to which the learned development
|
||
remains alien and exterior. The popular melody could never constitute a true theme; and that
|
||
is why, in popular music, the melody is the entire work, and why once it is over it has no other
|
||
resource than to repeat itself. But can't the melody transform itself into a theme? Bartok
|
||
solves this problem, which was thought insoluble" (p. 1056).
|
||
60. Marcel More, LedieuMozart etlemondedes oiseaux (Paris: Gallimard, 1971), p. 168.
|
||
And, on the crystal, pp. 83-89.
|
||
61. See Alban Berg's famous analysis of "Reverie" in Ecrits (Paris: Ed. du Rocher, 1957),
|
||
pp. 44.64.
|
||
|
||
12.1227: Treatise on Nomadology—the War Machine
|
||
1. Georges Dumezil, Mitra- Varuna (Paris: Gallimard, 1948 [forthcoming in English
|
||
translation from Zone Books]). On nexum and mutuum, the bond and the contract, see pp.
|
||
118-124.
|
||
2. "The first pole of the State (Varuna, Uranus, Romulus) operates by magic bond, sei-
|
||
zure, or immediate capture: it does not wage battles, and has no war machine, it binds, and
|
||
that is all." Its other pole (Mitra, Zeus, Numa) appropriates an army but imposes upon it
|
||
juridical and institutional rules that become nothing more than a piece in the State apparatus:
|
||
thus Mars-Tiwaz is not a warrior god, but a god who is a "jurist of war." See Dumezil, Mitra-
|
||
Varuna, pp. 113ff., 148ff., 202ff.
|
||
3. Dumezil, The Destiny of the Warrior, trans. Alf Hiltebeital (Chicago: University of
|
||
Chicaga Press, 1970).
|
||
4. For the role of the warrior as one who "unties" and opposes both the magic bond and
|
||
the juridical contract, see Dumezil, Mitra-Varuna, pp. 124-132. See also the analysis of furor
|
||
in the works of Dumezil.
|
||
5. [TRANS: The first quote is from Friedrich Nietzsche, The Genealogy of Morals, sec-
|
||
ond essay, sect. 17, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Vintage, 1967),
|
||
p. 86; the second is from Franz Kafka, "An Old Manuscript," The Complete Stories, ed.
|
||
Nahum N. Glazer (New York: Schocken, 1983), p. 416.]
|
||
6. Luc de Heusch emphasizes the public nature of Nkongolo's actions, in contrast to
|
||
the secrecy of the actions of Mbidi and his son; in particular, the former eats in public, whereas
|
||
the others hide during their meals. Later, we will see the essential relation of the war machine
|
||
with the secret, which is as much a matter of principle as a result: espionage, strategy, diplo-
|
||
macy. Commentators have often underlined this link. Le roi ivre ou I'origine de I'Etat (Paris:
|
||
Gallimard, 1972).
|
||
7. For an analysis of the three sins in the cases of the Indian god Indra, the Scandina-
|
||
vian hero Starcatherus, and the Greek god Hercules, see Dumezil, Mythe et epopee, vol. 2, pp.
|
||
17-19 (Paris: Gallimard, 1971). See also Dumezil, The Destiny of the Warrior.
|
||
8. Dumezil, Mitra- Varuna, p. 13 5. Dumezil analyzes the dangers and causes of the con-
|
||
fusion, which could be due to economic variables. See pp. 153, 159.
|
||
9. [TRANS: Richard III, act I, scene i, line 158.]
|
||
10. On Ajax and the tragedy of Sophocles, see the analysis of Jean Starobinski, Trois
|
||
Fureurs (Paris: Gallimard, 1974). Starobinski explicitly raises the question of war and the
|
||
State.
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 356-362 D 553
|
||
|
||
11. These themes are analyzed by Mathieu Carriere in an as yet unpublished study of
|
||
Kleist.
|
||
12. Pierre Clastres, Society against the State, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Uri-
|
||
zen, 1977), and "Archeologie de la violence: la guerre dans les societes primitives" and
|
||
"Malheur du guerrier sauvage" in Recherches d'anthropologie politique (Paris: Seuil,
|
||
1980), pp. 171-208, 209-248. In the last text, Clastres depicts the destiny of the warrior in
|
||
primitive society and analyzes the mechanism that prevents the concentration of power
|
||
(in the same way that Mauss demonstrated that the potlatch was a mechanism preventing
|
||
the concentration of wealth).
|
||
13. Jacques Meunier, Les gaminsde Bogota (Paris: Lattes, 1977), p. 159 ("blackmail for
|
||
dispersion") and p. 17 7: if necessary, "it is the other street children who, by means of a compli-
|
||
cated interplay of humiliations and silence, get the idea across that he must leave the gang."
|
||
Meunier emphasizes the degree to which the fate of the ex-gang member is jeopardized: not
|
||
only for health reasons, but because he finds it hard to integrate himself into the criminal
|
||
underworld, a society too hierarchical, too centralized, too centered on organs of power for
|
||
him to fit into (p. 178). On child gangs, see also the novel by Jorge Amado, Capitaes de areia
|
||
(Sao Paolo: Livraria Martins, 1944).
|
||
14. See I. S. Bernstein, "La dominance sociale chez les primates" in La Recherche, no. 91
|
||
(July 1978).
|
||
15. Clastres, Society against the State, p. 169: "The emergence of the State brought about
|
||
the great typological division between Savage and Civilized man; it created the unbridgeable
|
||
gulf whereby everything was changed, for, on the other side, Time became History." In order
|
||
to account for this emergence, Clastres cites first a demographic factor ("but there is no ques-
|
||
tion of replacing an economic determinism with a demographic determinism"; p. 180), then
|
||
the possibility of a warring machine (?) running amok; he also cites, more unexpectedly, the
|
||
indirect role of a certain mode of prophetic speech, which, directed first against the "chiefs,"
|
||
produces a formidable new kind of power. But one obviously cannot prejudge more elabo-
|
||
rated solutions Clastres might have found for this problem. On the possible role of prophetic
|
||
speech, refer to Helene Clastres, La terre sans mat, leproph'etisme tupi-guarani (Paris: Edi-
|
||
tions du Seuil, 1975).
|
||
16. Michel Serres, La naissance de la physique dans le texte de Lucrece. Fleuves et turbu-
|
||
lences (Paris: Minuit, 1977). Serres was the first to make the first three points given in the text;
|
||
the fourth seems to follow from them.
|
||
17. [TRANS: According to Serres, the dinamen, or declination of the atom, is the "mini-
|
||
mal angle leading to the formation of a vortex, and appears by chance in a laminar flow" (La
|
||
naissance de la physique, p. 14). The dinamen is the angle between a curve and its tangent, or
|
||
"the smallest [angle] one can make, preventing anything from coming between the two lines
|
||
which form it In other words, the angle appears at the same time as curvature" (p. 18).
|
||
"The dinamen is a differential" (p. 11).]
|
||
18. [TRANS: A flow is laminar when, "no matter how small we make the layers (or lamel-
|
||
lae) into which we divide the flow, they remain strictly parallel to one another in their move-
|
||
ments"; Serres, ibid., p. 12.]
|
||
19. [TRANS: Turba "designates a multitude, a large population, confusion and tumult."
|
||
Turbo "is a round form in movement... a revolving cone or vortical spiral." "The origin of
|
||
things and the beginning of order consists simply in the subtle passage from turba to turbo";
|
||
Serres, ibid., pp. 38-39.]
|
||
20. This is the distinction Pierre Boulez makes between two kinds of space-time in
|
||
music: in striated space, the measure can be irregular or regular, but it is always assignable; in
|
||
smooth space, the partition, or break, "can be effected at will." Boulez on Music Today, trans.
|
||
554 D NOTES TO PP. 362-366
|
||
|
||
Susan Bradshaw and Richard Bennett (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971),
|
||
p. 85.
|
||
21. Greek geometry is thoroughly marked by the opposition between these two poles,
|
||
the theorematic and problematic, and by the relative triumph of the former: in his Commen-
|
||
tary of the First Book of Euclid's Elements, trans, and intro. Glenn R. Murrow (Princeton,
|
||
N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1970), Proclus analyzes the difference between the poles,
|
||
taking the Speusippus-Menaechmus opposition as an example. Mathematics has always been
|
||
marked by this tension also; for example, the axiomatic element has confronted a proble-
|
||
matic, "intuitionist," or "constructivist" current emphasizing a calculus of problems very dif-
|
||
ferent from axiomatics, or any theorematic approach. See Georges Bouligand, Le declin des
|
||
absolus mathematico-logiques (Paris: Ed. d'Enseignement Superieur, 1949).
|
||
22. Paul Virilio, L'insecurite duterritoire (Paris: Stock, 1975), p. 120: "We know that
|
||
the youth of geometry, geometry as free, creative investigation, came to an end with Ar-
|
||
chimedes. . .. The sword of a Roman soldier cut the thread, tradition says. In killing geo-
|
||
metrical creation, the Roman State lay the foundation for the geometrical imperialism of
|
||
the West."
|
||
23. With Monge, and especially Poncelet, the limits of sensible, or even spatial, repre-
|
||
sentation (striated space) are indeed surpassed, but less in the direction of a symbolic power
|
||
(puissance) of abstraction than toward a transspatial imagination, or a transintuition (conti-
|
||
nuity). See Leon Brunschvicg's commentary on Poncelet, Les etapes de la philosophic
|
||
mathematique (Paris: PUF, 1947).
|
||
24. Michel Serres (La naissance de la physique, pp. 105-107) analyzes the opposition
|
||
d'Alembert-Bernoulli from this point of view. More generally, what is at issue is the difference
|
||
between two models of space: "In the Mediterranean basin there is a shortage of water, and he
|
||
who harnesses water rules. Hence that world of physics in which the conduit is essential, and
|
||
the dinamen seems like freedom because it is precisely a turbulence that rejects forced flow.
|
||
Incomprehensible to scientific theory, incomprehensible to the master of the waters....
|
||
Hence the great figure of Archimedes: the master of floating bodies and military machines"
|
||
(p. 106).
|
||
2 5. See Ben veniste, "The Notion of Rhythm in Its Linguistic Expression" in Problems in
|
||
General Linguistics, trans. Mary Elizabeth Meek (Coral Gables, Fla.: University of Miami
|
||
Press, 1971), pp. 281-288. This text, often considered decisive, seems ambiguous to us
|
||
because it invokes Democritus and atomism without dealing with the hydraulic question, and
|
||
because it treats rhythm as a "secondary specialization" of the form of the body (p. 286).
|
||
26. Anne Querrien, Devenir fonctionnaire ou le travail de I'Etat (Paris: Cerfi). We have
|
||
drawn from this book, as well as from unpublished studies by Anne Querrien.
|
||
27. See Raoul Vergez, Les illumines de I'art royal. Huit siecles de compagnonnages
|
||
(Paris: Julliard, 1976), p. 54. [TRANS: In the present context, trait refers to the cutting line fol-
|
||
lowed by the artisan and to the working sketch of the construction under way. Vergez gives the
|
||
following definition: "The Trait is a kind of graphic poem derived from geometry, which indi-
|
||
cates the building plan in sketches drawn with precision on the ground, showing sections, ele-
|
||
vations and all other projections, the three dimensions of a volume"; p. 86.]
|
||
28. Gerard Desargues, Oeuvres (Paris: Leiber, 1864). See also the text by Michel Chasles
|
||
[Apercu historique sur I'origine et le developpement de methodes en geometric... (Brussels:
|
||
M. Hayez, 1837)—Trans.], which establishes a continuity between Desargues, Monge, and
|
||
Poncelet as the "founders of a modern geometry."
|
||
29. Anne Querrien, Devenirfonctionnaire, pp. 26-27: "Is the State founded upon the col-
|
||
lapse of experimentation?. . . The State is not under construction, its construction sites must
|
||
be short-lived. An installation is made to function, not to be socially constructed: from this
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 366-371 D 555
|
||
|
||
point of view, the State involves in the construction only those who are paid to implement or
|
||
command, and who are obliged to follow the model of a preestablished experimentation."
|
||
30. On the question of the "Colbert lobby," see Daniel Dessert and Jean-Louis Journet,
|
||
"Le Lobby Colbert. Un royaume, ou une affaire de famille?" Annales, 30, no. 6 (November-
|
||
December 1975), pp. 1303-1336.
|
||
31. See Ibn Khaldun, The Muqaddimah: An Introduction to History, trans. Franz
|
||
Rosenthal (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1967). One of the essential themes of
|
||
this masterpiece is the sociological problem of the esprit de corps, and its ambiguity. Ibn
|
||
Khaldun contrasts bedouinism (the bedouin life-style, not the ethnic group) with sedentarily
|
||
or city living. The first aspect of this opposition is the inverted relation between the public and
|
||
the secret: not only is there a secrecy of the bedouin war machine, as opposed to the publicity
|
||
of the State city dweller, but in the first case "eminence" is based on a secret solidarity, while in
|
||
the second case the secret is subordinated to the demands of social eminence. Second,
|
||
bedouinism brings into play both a great purity and a great mobility of the lineages and their
|
||
genealogy, whereas city life makes for lineages that are very impure, and at the same time rigid
|
||
and fixed: Solidarity has a different meaning at either pole. Third, and this is the main point,
|
||
bedouin lineages mobilize an esprit de corps and integrate into it, as a new dimension: this is
|
||
asablyah, or ikhtilat, from which the Arabic word for socialism is derived (Ibn Khaldun
|
||
stresses the absence of any "power" residing in the tribal chief, who has no State constraints at
|
||
his disposal). On the other hand, in city living the esprit de corps becomes a dimension of
|
||
power and is adapted for "autocracy."
|
||
32. The principal texts of Husserl are Ideas, trans. W. R. Gibson (New York: Humanities
|
||
Press, 1976), part 1, sec. 74, and Edmund Husserl's Origin of Geometry: An Introduction,
|
||
trans. John P. Leavey, Jr., ed. David B. Allison (Stoney Brook, N.Y.: N. Hayes, 1978) (with
|
||
Derrida's very important commentary, pp. 118-132). On the issue of a vague yet rigorous sci-
|
||
ence, we may refer to the formula of Michel Serres, in his commentary on the geometrical fig-
|
||
ure called the salinon: "It is rigorous, anexact. And not precise, exact or inexact. Only a
|
||
metrics is exact" (Naissance de la physique, p. 29). Gaston Bachelard's book Essai sur la
|
||
connaissance approch'ee (Paris: Vrin, 1927) remains the best study of the steps and procedures
|
||
constituting a rigor of the anexact, and of their creative role in science.
|
||
33. Gilbert Simondon has contributed much to the analysis and critique of the hylo-
|
||
morphic schema and of its social presuppositions ("form corresponds to what the man in
|
||
command has thought to himself, and must express in a positive manner when he gives his
|
||
orders: form is thus of the order of the expressible"). To the form-matter schema, Simondon
|
||
opposes a dynamic schema, that of matter endowed with singularities-forces, or the ener-
|
||
getic conditions at the basis of a system. The result is an entirely different conception of the
|
||
relations between science and technology. See L'individu et sa genese physico-biologique
|
||
(Paris: PUF, 1964).
|
||
34. In Timaeus, 28-29, Plato entertains for an instant the thought that Becoming is not
|
||
simply the inevitable characteristic of copies or reproductions, but could itself be a model
|
||
rivaling the Identical and the Uniform. He states this hypothesis only in order to reject it; for
|
||
it is true that if becoming is a model, not only must the duality of the model and the copy, of
|
||
the model and reproduction, disappear, but the very notions of model and reproduction tend
|
||
to lose all meaning. [TRANS: Deleuze develops this point in "Plato and the Simulacrum," trans.
|
||
Rosalind Krauss, October, 21 (Winter 1983), pp. 45-56. See especially p. 53.]
|
||
3 5. [TRANS: Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York:
|
||
Vintage, 1968), sec. 630(1885), p. 336.]
|
||
36. The situation is in fact more complex than that, and gravity is not the only feature of
|
||
the dominant model: there is heat in addition to gravity (already in chemistry, combustion is
|
||
coupled with weight). Even so, the problem was to know to what extent the "thermal field"
|
||
556 D NOTES TO PP. 371-379
|
||
|
||
deviated from gravitational space, or on the contrary was integrated with it. Monge is a typical
|
||
example; he began by grouping heat, light, and electricity as "variable affections of bodies,"
|
||
the concern of "specific physics," while general physics would deal with extension, gravity,
|
||
and movement. It was only later that Monge unified all of the fields under general physics
|
||
(Anne Querrien).
|
||
37. Serres, La naissance de la physique, p. 65.
|
||
38. Carlos Castaneda, The Teachings of Don Juan (Berkeley: University of California
|
||
Press, 1971), p. 88.
|
||
39. Albert Lautman has shown quite clearly how Riemann spaces, for example, admit a
|
||
Euclidean conjunction making it possible at all times to define the parallelism of two neigh-
|
||
boring vectors; this being the case, instead of exploring a multiplicity by legwork, the multipli-
|
||
city is treated as though "immersed in a Euclidean space with a sufficient number of
|
||
dimensions." See Les schemas de structure (Paris: Hermann, 1938), pp. 23-24, 43-47.
|
||
40. In Bergson, the relations between intuition and intelligence are very complex, and
|
||
they are in perpetual interaction. Bouligand's theme is also relevant here: the dualism of the
|
||
two mathematical elements, the "problem" and the "global synthesis," is developed only
|
||
when they enter a field of interaction in which the global synthesis defines the "categories"
|
||
without which the problem would have no general solution. See Le d'eclin des absolus
|
||
mathematico-logiques.
|
||
41. Marcel Detienne, in Les maltres de verite dans la Grece archdique (Paris: Maspero,
|
||
1973), clearly articulates these two poles of thought, which correspond to the two aspects of
|
||
sovereignty according to Dumezil: the magico-religious speech of the despot or of the "old
|
||
man of the sea," and the dialogue-speech of the city. Not only are the principal character types
|
||
of Greek thought (the Poet, the Physicist, the Philosopher, the Sophist, etc.) situated in rela-
|
||
tion to these poles, but Detienne interposes between the two poles a distinct group, the Warri-
|
||
ors, which brings about transition or evolution.
|
||
42. There exists a Hegelianism of the right that lives on in official political philosophy
|
||
and weds the destiny of thought to the State. Alexandre Kojeve ("Tyranny and Wisdom," in
|
||
Leo Strauss, On Tyranny [New York: Free Press of Glencoe, 1963]) and Eric Weil (Hegel et
|
||
I'Etat. Philosophicpolitique [Paris: Vrin, 1974]) are its recent representatives. From Hegel to
|
||
Max Weber there developed a whole line of reflection on the relation of the modern State to
|
||
Reason, both as rational-technical and as reasonable-human. If it is objected that this ration-
|
||
ality, already present in the archaic imperial State, is the optimum of the governors them-
|
||
selves, the Hegelians respond that the rational-reasonable cannot exist without a minimum of
|
||
participation by everybody. The question, rather, is whether the very form of the rational-
|
||
reasonable is not extracted from the State, in a way that necessarily makes it right, gives it
|
||
"reason" (lui donner n'ecessairement "raison").
|
||
43. On the role of the ancient poet as a "functionary of sovereignty," see Dumezil,
|
||
Servius et la Fortune (Paris: Gallimard, 1943), pp. 64ff., and Detienne, Les maitres de verite,
|
||
pp. 17ff.
|
||
44. See Michel Foucault's analysis of Maurice Blanchot and the form of exteriority of
|
||
thought: "La pensee du dehors," Critique, no. 229 (June 1966), pp. 523-548.
|
||
45. Nietzsche, Schopenhauer as Educator, in Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J.
|
||
Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), pp. 177-178.
|
||
46. A curious text of Karl Jaspers, entitled Descartes und die Philosophic (Berlin: W. de
|
||
Gruyter, 1956), develops this point of view and accepts its implications.
|
||
47. Kenneth White, Intellectual Nomadism. The title of the second volume of this
|
||
unpublished work is Poetry and Tribe.
|
||
48. [TRANS: Arthur Rimbaud, A Season in Hell, trans. Louise Varese (Norfolk, Conn.:
|
||
New Directions, 1952), pp. 9, 13, 17, 39.]
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 380-384 D 557
|
||
|
||
49. Anny Milovanoff, "La seconde peau du nomade," Nouvelles litt'eraires, no. 2646
|
||
(July 27, 1978), p. 18: "The Larbaa nomads, on the border of the Algerian Sahara, use the
|
||
word triga, which generally means road or way, to designate the woven straps serving to rein-
|
||
force the cords holding the tent to the stakes.... In nomad thought, the dwelling is tied not to a
|
||
territory but rather to an itinerary. Refusing to take possession of the land they cross, the
|
||
nomads construct an environment out of wool and goat hair, one that leaves no mark at the
|
||
temporary site it occupies Thus wool, a soft material, gives nomad life its unity....
|
||
Nomads pause at the representation of their journeys, not at a figuration of the space they
|
||
cross. They leave space to space.... Woolly polymorphism."
|
||
50. See W. Montgomery Watt, Mohammed at Medina (London: Oxford University
|
||
Press, 1956), pp. 85-86, 242.
|
||
51. Emmanuel Laroche, Histoire de la ratine "Nem " en grec ancien (Paris: Klincksieck,
|
||
1949). The root "Nem" indicates distribution, not allocation, even when the two are linked.
|
||
In the pastoral sense, the distribution of animals is effected in a nonlimited space and implies
|
||
no parceling out of land: "The occupation of shepherd, in the Homeric age, had nothing to do
|
||
with a parceling of land; when the agrarian question came to the foreground, in the time of
|
||
Solon, it was expressed in an entirely different vocabulary." To take to pasture (nemo) refers
|
||
not to a parceling out but to a scattering, to a repartition of animals. It was only after Solon
|
||
that Nomos came to designate the principle at the basis of the laws and of right (Thesmo'i and
|
||
Dike), and then came to be identified with the laws themselves. Prior to that, there was instead
|
||
an alternative between the city, or polis, ruled by laws, and the outskirts as the place of the
|
||
nomos. A similar alternative is found in the work of Ibn Khaldun: between hadara as city liv-
|
||
ing, and badiya as nomos (not the town, but the preurban countryside, the plateau, steppe,
|
||
mountain, or desert).
|
||
52. Arnold Toynbee, A Study of History (New York: Oxford University Press, 1947),
|
||
abridged by D. C. Somerwell, vol. 1, pp. 164-186: "They flung themselves upon the Steppe,
|
||
not to escape beyond its bounds but to make themselves at home on it" (p. 168).
|
||
53. See Pierre Hubac, Les nomades (Paris: La Renaissance du Livre, 1948), pp. 26-29
|
||
(although Hubac tends to confuse nomads and migrants).
|
||
54. On the nomads of the sea, or of the archipelago, Jose Emperaire writes: "They do not
|
||
grasp an itinerary as a whole, but in a fragmentary manner, by juxtaposing in order its various
|
||
successive stages, from campsite to campsite in the course of the journey. For each of these
|
||
stages, they estimate the length of the crossing and the successive changes in direction mark-
|
||
ing it." Les nomades de la mer (Paris: Gallimard, 1954), p. 225.
|
||
55. Wilfred Thesiger, Arabian Sands (London: Longmans, Green, 1959), pp. 112-113,
|
||
125, 165-166.
|
||
56. See the two admirable descriptions, of the sand desert by Wilfred Thesiger and of the
|
||
ice desert by Edmund Carpenter, in Eskimo (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1964): the
|
||
winds, and tactile and sound qualities; the secondary character of visual data, particularly the
|
||
indifference of the nomads to astronomy as a royal science; and yet the presence of a whole
|
||
minor science of qualitative variables and traces.
|
||
57. EmileFelixGautier,Le passe del'AfriqueduNord(Paris: Payot, 1952), pp. 267-316.
|
||
58. From this perspective, Clastres's analysis of Indian prophetism can be generalized:
|
||
"On one side, the chiefs, on the other, and standing against them, the prophets. . . . And the
|
||
prophetic machine worked perfectly well since the karai were able to sweep astonishing
|
||
masses of Indians along behind them the insurrectional act of the prophets against the
|
||
chiefs conferred on the former, through a strange reversal of things, infinitely more power
|
||
than was held by the latter." Society against the State, pp. 184-185.
|
||
59. One of the most interesting themes of the classic work by Paul Alphandery (La
|
||
chr'etient'e et I'id'ee de croisade [Paris: Albin Michel, 1959] is his demonstration that the
|
||
558 D NOTES TO PP. 384-386
|
||
|
||
changes in course, the pauses, the detours were an integral part of the Crusade: "this army of
|
||
crusaders that we envision as a modern army, like those of Louis XIV or Napoleon, marching
|
||
with absolute passivity, obeying the will of a diplomatic officer and staff. Such an army knows
|
||
where it is going, and when it makes a mistake, it is not for lack of reflection. A history more
|
||
attentive to differences accepts a more realistic image of the army of the Crusade. The army of
|
||
the Crusade was freely, sometimes anarchically alive. ... This army was motivated from
|
||
within, as a function of a complex coherence by virtue of which nothing happened by chance.
|
||
It is certain that the conquest of Constantinople had its reason, necessity and a religious char-
|
||
acter, like the other deeds of the Crusades" (vol. 2, p. 7). Alphandery shows in particular that
|
||
the idea of a battle against the Infidel, at any point, appeared early on, along with the idea of
|
||
liberating the Holy Land (vol. 1, p. 219).
|
||
60. Modern historians have been inspired to fine analyses by this confrontation between
|
||
the East and the West, which began in the Middle Ages (and is tied to the question, Why did
|
||
capitalism develop in the West and not elsewhere?). See especially Fernand Braudel, Capital-
|
||
ism and Material Life, 1400-1800, trans. Miriam Kochan (New York: Harper and Row, 1967),
|
||
pp. 97-108; Pierre Chaunu, L'expansion europeenne du XIHe au XVe siecle (Paris: PUF,
|
||
1969), pp. 334-339 ("Why Europe? Why not China?"); Maurice Lombard, Espaces et reseaux
|
||
du hautMoyen Age (The Hague: Mouton, 1971), chapter 8 (and p. 219: "What is called defor-
|
||
estation in the East is named clearing in the West. The first deep cause of the shift of the domi-
|
||
nant centers from the East to the West is therefore a geographical reason: forest-clearing
|
||
proved to have more potential than desert-oasis").
|
||
61. Marx's observations on the despotic formations of Asia have been confirmed by the
|
||
African analyses of Max Gluckman, Custom and Conflict in Africa (Glencoe, 111.: Free Press,
|
||
1959): at the same time immutability of form and constant rebellion. The idea of a "transfor-
|
||
mation" of the State indeed seems to be a Western one. And that other idea, the "destruction"
|
||
of the State, belongs much more to the East and to the conditions of a nomad war machine.
|
||
Attempts have been made to present the two ideas as successive phases of revolution, but
|
||
there are too many differences between them and they are difficult to reconcile; they reflect
|
||
the opposition between the socialist and anarchist currents of the nineteenth century. The
|
||
Western proletariat itself is perceived from two points of view: as having to seize power and
|
||
transform the State apparatus (the point of view of labor power), and as willing or wishing for
|
||
the destruction of the State (this time, the point of view of nomadization power). Even Marx
|
||
defines the proletariat not only as alienated (labor) but as deterritorialized. The proletariat, in
|
||
this second perspective, appears as the heir to the nomad in the Western world. Not only did
|
||
many anarchists invoke nomadic themes originating in the East, but the bourgeoisie above all
|
||
were quick to equate proletarians and nomads, comparing Paris to a city haunted by nomads
|
||
(see Louis Chevalier, Laboring Classes and Dangerous Classes in Paris during the First Half of
|
||
the Nineteenth Century, trans. Frank Jellenck [New York: H. Fertig, 1973], pp. 362-366).
|
||
62. See Lucien Mussel, Les invasions. Le secondassaut (Paris: PUF, 1965), for example,
|
||
the analysis of the Danes' three "phases," pp. 135-137.
|
||
63. Paul Virilio, Speed and Politics, trans. Mark Polizzotti (New York: Semiotext[e],
|
||
1986), pp. 12-13 and passim. Not only is the "town" unthinkable apart from the exterior flows
|
||
with which it is in contact, and the circulation of which it regulates, but specific architectural
|
||
aggregates, the fortress, for example, are veritable transformers, by virtue of their interior
|
||
spaces, which allow an analysis, prolongation, or restitution of movement. Virilio concludes
|
||
that the issue is less confinement than the management of the public ways, or the control of
|
||
movement. Foucault was already moving in this direction with his analysis of the naval hospi-
|
||
tal as operator and filter; see Discipline and Punish, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New York:
|
||
Vintage, 1975), pp. 143-146.
|
||
64. On Chinese, and Arab, navigation, the reasons behind their failure, and the impor-
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 386-390 D 559
|
||
|
||
tance of this question in the East-West "dossier," see Braudel, Capitalism and Material Life,
|
||
pp. 300-309, and Chaunu, L'expansion europeenne, pp. 145-147.
|
||
65. Virilio gives a very good definition of the fleet in being and its historical conse-
|
||
quences: "The fleet in being... is the permanent presence in the sea of an invisible fleet able
|
||
to strike no matter where and no matter when . . . it is a new idea of violence that no longer
|
||
comes from direct confrontation... but rather from the unequal properties of bodies, evalu-
|
||
ation of the number of movements allowed them in a chosen element, permanent verification
|
||
of their dynamic efficiency... .Henceforth it is no longer a question of crossing a continent or
|
||
an ocean from one city to the next, one shore to the next. The fleet in being creates . . . the
|
||
notion of displacement without destination in space and time.... The strategic submarine
|
||
has no need to go anywhere in particular; it is content, while controlling the sea, to remain
|
||
invisible . . . the realization of the absolute, uninterrupted, circular voyage, since it involves
|
||
neither departure nor arrival... .If, as Lenin claimed,'strategy means choosing which points
|
||
we apply force to,' we must admit that these 'points', today, are no longer geostrategic
|
||
strongpoints, since from any given spot we can now reach any other, no matter where it might
|
||
be... geographic localization seems to have definitively lost its strategic value, and, inversely,
|
||
that this same value is attributed to the delocalization of the vector, of a vector in permanent
|
||
movement"; Speed and Politics, pp. 38,40-41,134-135. Virilio's texts are of great importance
|
||
and originality in every respect. The only point that presents a difficulty for us is his assimila-
|
||
tion of three groups of speed that seem very different to us: (1) speeds of nomadic, or revolu-
|
||
tionary, tendency (riot, guerrilla warfare); (2) speeds that are regulated, convened, appropri-
|
||
ated by the State apparatus (management of the public ways); (3) speeds that are reinstated by
|
||
a worldwide organization of total war, or planetary overarmament (from the fleet in being to
|
||
nuclear strategy). Virilio tends to equate these groups on account of their interactions and
|
||
makes a general case for the "fascist" character of speed. It is, nevertheless, his own analyses
|
||
that make these distinctions possible.
|
||
66. Jean-Pierre Vernant in particular has analyzed the connection between the Greek
|
||
city-state and a homogeneous geometrical extension, Mythe et pensee chez les Grecs (Paris:
|
||
Maspero, 1971 -1974), vol. 1, part 3. The problem is necessarily more complicated in relation
|
||
to the archaic empires, or in relation to formations subsequent to the classical city-state. That
|
||
is because the space in question is very different. But it is still the case that the number is sub-
|
||
ordinated to space, as Vernant suggests with regard to Plato's ideal state. The Pythagorean or
|
||
Neoplatonic conceptions of number envelop imperial astronomical spaces of a type other
|
||
than homogeneous extension, but they maintain the subordination of the number; that is why
|
||
Numbers become ideal, but not strictly speaking "numbering."
|
||
67. Dumezil stresses the role played by the arithmetic element in the earliest forms of
|
||
political sovereignty. He even tends to make it a third pole of sovereignty. See Servius et la For-
|
||
tune and Le troisieme souverain (Paris: Maisonneuve, 1949). But the role of this arithmetic
|
||
element is, rather, to organize a matter; in so doing it submits that matter to one or the other of
|
||
the two principal poles.
|
||
68. Karl von Clausewitz stresses the secondary role of geometry, in tactics and in strat-
|
||
egy: On War, trans. Michael Howard, Peter Paret, and Bernard Brodie (Princeton, N. J.:
|
||
Princeton University Press, 1976), pp. 214-216 ("The Geometrical Factor").
|
||
69. See one of the most profound ancient texts relating the number and direction to the
|
||
war machine, Ssu-ma Ch'ien, The Records of the Grand Historian, trans. Burton Watson (New
|
||
York: Columbia University Press, 1961), vol. 2, pp. 155-193 ("The Account of the
|
||
Hsiung-nu").
|
||
70. Frank Herbert, Children of Dune (New York: Berkley Books, 1977), p. 212. One may
|
||
refer to the characteristics proposed by Julia Kristeva to define the numbering number.
|
||
560 D NOTES TO PP. 390-399
|
||
|
||
"arrangement," "plural and contingent distribution," "infini-point," "rigorous approxima-
|
||
tion," etc. Semeiotike. Recherches pour une semanalyse (Paris: Seuil, 1969), pp. 293-297.
|
||
71. Boris lakovlevich Vladimirtsov, Le regime social des Mongols, trans. Michel Carsow
|
||
(Paris: Maisonneuve, 1948). The term used by Vladimirtsov, "antrustions," is borrowed from
|
||
the Saxon regime, in which the king's company, or "trust," was composed of Franks.
|
||
72. A particularly interesting case is that of a special body of smiths among the Tuareg,
|
||
called the Enaden (the "Others"); the Enaden are thought to have been originally Sudanese
|
||
slaves, Jewish settlers in the Sahara, or descendants of the knights of Saint Louis. See Rene
|
||
Pettier, "Les artisans sahariens du metal chez les Touareg," in Techniques et civilisations, vol.
|
||
1 (M'etaux et civilisations), no. 2 (1945), pp. 31-40.
|
||
73. Feudalism is no less a military system than so-called military democracy; but both
|
||
systems assume an army integrated into some kind of State apparatus (for feudalism, it was
|
||
the Carolingian land reform). It is Vladimirtsov who developed a feudal interpretation of the
|
||
nomads of the steppe, whereas Mikhail Griaznov, The Ancient Civilization of Southern
|
||
Siberia, trans. James Hogarth (New York: Cowles, 1969), leans toward military democracy.
|
||
But one of Vladimirtsov's main arguments is that the organization of the nomads becomes
|
||
feudal precisely to the extent that it is in disintegration, or is integrated into the empires it
|
||
conquers. He himself remarks that in the beginning the Mongols did not organize the seden-
|
||
tary land they took over into fiefs, true or false.
|
||
74. J. F. C. Fuller, Armament and History (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1945),
|
||
p. 5.
|
||
75. Paul Virilio, "Metempsychose du passager," Traverses, no. 8 (May 1977), pp. 11-19.
|
||
Virilio, however, asserts that there was an indirect transition from hunting to war: when
|
||
women served as "portage or pack" animals, which already enabled the hunters to enter into a
|
||
relation of "homosexual duel" transcending the hunt. But it seems that Virilio himself invites
|
||
us to make a distinction between speed, as projector and projectile, and displacement, as
|
||
transport and portage. The war machine is defined from the first point of view, while the sec-
|
||
ond relates to the public sphere. The horse, for example, is not a part of the war machine if it
|
||
serves only to transport men who dismount to do battle. The war machine is defined by
|
||
action, not transport, even if the transport reacts upon the action.
|
||
76. J. F. C. Fuller, Armaments and History, pp. 137ff., shows that the First World War
|
||
was first conceived as an offensive war of movement based on artillery. But artillery was
|
||
turned against artillery, forcing immobility. It was not possible to reinstate mobility in the war
|
||
through "ever-increasing shell fire" (p. 138) since the craters made the terrain all the harder to
|
||
negotiate. The solution, to which the English, and General Fuller in particular, made decisive
|
||
contributions, came in the form of the tank: the tank, a "landship" (p. 139), reconstituted a
|
||
kind of maritime or smooth space on land, and "superimposed naval tactics on land warfare"
|
||
(p. 140). As a general rule, military response is never in kind: the tank was the response to artil-
|
||
lery, the helicopter to the tank, etc. This makes for an innovation factor in the war machine
|
||
that is very different from innovation in the work machine.
|
||
77. On this general distinction between the two models, "work-free action," "consum-
|
||
ing force/conserving force," "real effect/formal effect," etc., see Martial Gueroult's expo-
|
||
sition, Dynamique et metaphysique leibniziennes (Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1934), pp. 55,
|
||
119 ff., 222-224.
|
||
78. Marcel Detienne, "La phalange, problemes et controverses," in Problemes de la
|
||
guerre en Grece ancienne (Civilisations et societes, no. 11), ed. Jean-Pierre Vernant (The
|
||
Hague: Mouton, 1968), pp. 119-143: "Technology is in a way internal to the social and the
|
||
mental," (p. 134).
|
||
79. On the stirrup and the plow, see Lynn Townsend White, Jr., Medieval Technology and
|
||
Social Change (New York: Oxford University Press, 1962), chapters 1 and 2. Similarly, it has
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 399-406 D 561
|
||
|
||
been shown in the case of dry rice cultivation in Asia that the digging stick, the hoe, and the
|
||
plow depend upon collective assemblages that vary according to population density and the
|
||
fallow period. This enables Braudel to conclude: "The tool, according to this theory, is the
|
||
result and no longer the cause"; Capitalism and Material Life, p. 116.
|
||
80. Treatises on martial arts remind us that the Ways, which are still subject to the laws of
|
||
gravity, must be transcended in the void. Kleist's About Marionettes, trans. Michael Lebeck
|
||
(Mindelheim: Three Kings Press, 1970), without question one of the most spontaneously ori-
|
||
ental texts in Western literature, presents a similar movement: the linear displacement of the
|
||
center of gravity is still "mechanical" and relates to something more "mysterious" that con-
|
||
cerns the soul and knows nothing of weight.
|
||
81. See Paul Pelliot, "Les systemes d'ecriture en usage chez les anciens Mongols," Asia
|
||
Major 2 (1925), pp. 284-289: The Mongols used the Uighur script, with the Syriac alphabet (it
|
||
was the Tibetans who produced a phonetic theory of Uighur writing); the two versions of the
|
||
Secret History of the Mongols that have been passed down to us are a Chinese translation and a
|
||
phonetic transcription in Chinese characters.
|
||
82. Georges Charriere, Scythian Art (New York: Alpine Fine Arts Collection, 1979), p.
|
||
185 [translation modified].
|
||
83. See Lucien Mussel, Introduction a la runologie (Paris: Aubier-Montaigne, 1965).
|
||
84. There are, of course, forms of cooking and architecture that are part of the nomad
|
||
war machine, but they fall under a different "trait," one distinguishing them from their seden-
|
||
tary form. Nomad architecture, for example, the Eskimo igloo orthe Hunnish wooden palace,
|
||
is a derivative of the tent: its influence on sedentary art came by way of domes and half-
|
||
domes, and above all of space starting very low, as in a tent. As for nomad cooking, it consists
|
||
literally of break-fast (the paschal tradition is nomadic). And it is under this trait that it can be
|
||
part of a war machine: for example, the Janissaries used a cooking pot as their rallying point;
|
||
there were different ranks of cooks, and their hat had a wooden spoon through it.
|
||
85. Itisinthe Traitedu rebelle (Paris: Bourgois, 1981) that lunger takes his clearest stand
|
||
against national socialism and develops certain points contained in DerArbeiter: a concep-
|
||
tion of the "line" as an active escape passing between the two figures of the old Soldier and the
|
||
modern Worker, carrying both toward another destiny in another assembly (nothing of this
|
||
remains in Heidegger's notion of the Line, although it is dedicated to Jiinger).
|
||
86. Lynn White, Jr., who is actually not inclined to ascribe much power of innovation
|
||
to the nomads, sometimes establishes extensive technological lineages with surprising
|
||
origins: he traces hot-air and turbine technologies to Malaya (Medieval Technology and
|
||
Social Change, p. 95 and note): "Thus a chain of technological stimuli may be traced back
|
||
from some of the major figures of early modern science and technology through the later
|
||
Middle Ages to the jungles of Malaya. A second, and related, Malay invention, the fire pis-
|
||
ton, may have had significant influence upon the European understanding of air pressure
|
||
and its applications."
|
||
87. On the particularly thorny question of the stirrup, see Lynn White, Jr., Medieval
|
||
Technology and Social Change, chapter 1.
|
||
88. See the fine article by A. Mazaheri, "Le sabre centre 1'epee," Annales 13, no. 4
|
||
(October-December 1958), pp. 669-686.
|
||
89. Henri Limet, Le travail du metal au pays de Sumer au temps de la life dynastie d'Ur
|
||
(Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1960), pp. 33-40.
|
||
90. Along these lines, Mazaheri effectively demonstrates that the saber and sword
|
||
belong to two distinct technological lineages. In particular, damasking (damassage), which
|
||
does not come from Damascus at all, but rather from the Greek or Persian word for diamond,
|
||
designates the treatment of cast steel that makes it as hard as a diamond and the designs in this
|
||
steel resulting from the crystallization of the cement ("true damask was made in the centers
|
||
562 D NOTES TO PP. 406-414
|
||
|
||
that had never experienced Roman domination"). But on the other hand, damascening
|
||
(damasQuinage), which did come from Damascus, designates only inlay in metal (or in fab-
|
||
ric), intentional designs imitating damasking using entirely different means.
|
||
91. Andre Leroi-Gourhan, Milieu et techniques (Paris: Albin Michel, 1945), pp. 356ff.
|
||
Gilbert Simondon, discussing short series, takes up the question of the "absolute origins of a
|
||
technological lineage," or of the creation of a "technical essence": Du mode d'existence des
|
||
objects techniques (Paris: Aubier, 1969), pp. 41-49.
|
||
92. On the mold-modulation relation, and the way in which molding hides or contracts
|
||
an operation of modulation that is essential to matter-movement, see Simondon, Du mode
|
||
d'existence, pp. 2 8-50 ("modulation is molding in a continuous and perpetually variable man-
|
||
ner"; p. 42). Simondon clearly shows that the hylomorphic schema owes its power not to the
|
||
technological operation but to the social model of work subsuming that operation (pp.
|
||
47-49).
|
||
93. Simondon feels no special attraction for the problems of metallurgy. His analysis is
|
||
not, in fact, historical and prefers to deal with examples drawn from electronics. But, histori-
|
||
cally, there is no electronics without metallurgy. Thus Simondon pays homage to metallurgy:
|
||
"Metallurgy does not entirely accommodate itself to an analysis using the hylomorphic
|
||
schema. The fixing of the form is not accomplished visibly in a single stroke, but in several
|
||
successive operations; the forging and quenching of steel are anterior and posterior, respec-
|
||
tively, to the fixing of the form in the strict sense; forging and quenching are, nevertheless,
|
||
operations that constitute objects" (L'individu, p. 59).
|
||
94. Not only must myths be taken into account, but also positive history, for example,
|
||
the role of "the brass" in the evolution of musical form; or again, the constitution of a "metal-
|
||
lic synthesis" in electronic music (Richard Pinhas).
|
||
95. Wilhelm Worringer defines Gothic art in terms of a geometrical line that is "primi-
|
||
tive" but has taken on life. But this vitality is not organic, as it will be in the classical world: this
|
||
line "embodies no organic expression.. .it is nevertheless of the utmost vitality... .Since this
|
||
line is lacking in all organic timbre, its expression of life must, as an expression, be divorced
|
||
from organic life.. . The pathos of movement which lies in this vitalized geometry—a pre-
|
||
lude to the vitalized mathematics of Gothic architecture—forces our sensibility to an effort
|
||
unnatural to it." Form in Gothic (London: Putnam's and Sons, 1927), pp. 41-42.
|
||
96. This is one of the essential points of V. Gordon Childe's argument in The Prehistory
|
||
of European Civilization (London: Cassell, 1962): the metallurgist is the first specialized arti-
|
||
san, whose sustenance is made possible by the formation of an agricultural surplus. The rela-
|
||
tion of the smith to agriculture has to do not only with the tools smiths manufacture but also
|
||
with the food they take or receive. The Dogon myth, as analyzed in its variants by Griaule, can
|
||
be seen as marking this relation, in which the smith receives or steals grains, and hides them in
|
||
his mallet.
|
||
97. Maurice Lombard, Les metauxdans I'ancien mondedu Veau XIesiecle(The Hague:
|
||
Mouton, 1974), pp. 75, 255.
|
||
98. The social position of the smith has been the object of detailed studies; for Africa in
|
||
particular see the classic study by W. B. Cline, "Mining and Metallurgy in Negro Africa," Gen-
|
||
eral Series in Anthropology, no. 5 (1937); and Pierre Clement, "Le forgeron en Afrique noire,"
|
||
Revue de geographie humaine et d'ethnologie, no. 2 (April-June 1948), pp. 35-58. But these
|
||
studies are hardly conclusive; the better defined the principles invoked—"reaction of con-
|
||
tempt," "of approbation," "of apprehension"—the hazier and more overlapping the results,
|
||
as seen in Clement's tables.
|
||
99. See Jules Bloch, Les Tziganes, Que sais-je?, no. 580 (Paris: PUF, 1969). Bloch dem-
|
||
onstrates precisely that the distinction between sedentaries and nomads becomes secondary
|
||
in connection with cave dwelling.
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 414-421 D 563
|
||
|
||
100. Elie Faure, Medieval Art, vol. 2 of History of Art, trans. Walter Pach (Garden City,
|
||
N.Y.: Garden City Publishing, 1937), pp. 12-14.
|
||
101. On these peoples and their mysteries, see the analyses of V. Gordon Childe, The Pre-
|
||
history of European Society, chapter 7 ("Missionaries, Traders and Warriors of Temperate
|
||
Europe"), and The Dawn of European Civilization (New York: Knopf, 1958).
|
||
102. Maurice Griaule and Germaine Dieterlen, Le renard pale, vol. 1 (Paris: Institut
|
||
d'ethnologie, 1965), p. 376.
|
||
103. The book by Robert James Forbes, Metallurgy in Antiquity (Leiden: Brill, 1950),
|
||
analyzes the different ages of metallurgy, as well as the types of metallurgists that existed in the
|
||
"ore stage": the "miner," who did the prospecting and mining; the "smelter" [who produced
|
||
the crude metal or alloy]; the "blacksmith" [who manufactured mass products from crude
|
||
metals]; and the "metalworker" [who produced smaller objects; includes gold- and silver-
|
||
smiths] (pp. 74-76). The specialization system becomes more complicated in the Iron Age,
|
||
with attendant variations in the nomad-itinerant-sedentary distribution.
|
||
104. The texts of T. E. Lawrence, Seven Pillars of Wisdom (New York: Doubleday,
|
||
Doran, 1935) and "The Science of Guerrilla War," in Encyclopedia Britannica, 14th ed.
|
||
(1929), vol. 10, pp. 950-953, remain among the most significant works on guerrilla warfare;
|
||
they present themselves as an "anti-Foch" theory and elaborate the notion of the nonbattle.
|
||
But the nonbattle has a history that is not entirely dependent on guerrilla warfare: (1) the
|
||
traditional distinction between the "battle" and the "maneuver" in war; see Raymon Aron,
|
||
Penser la guerre. Clausewitz (Paris: Gallimard, 1976), vol. 1, pp. 122-131; (2) the way in
|
||
which the war of movement places the role and importance of the battle in question (as early
|
||
as Marshal de Saxe, and the controversial question of the battle during the Napoleonic
|
||
Wars); (3) finally, more recently, the critique of the battle in the name of nuclear arms, which
|
||
play a deterrent role, with conventional forces now having a role only in "testing" or "man-
|
||
euver"; see the Gaullist conception of the nonbattle, and Guy Brossollet, Essai sur la non-
|
||
bataille (Paris: Belin, 1975). The recent return to the notion of the battle cannot be
|
||
explained simply by technological factors such as the development of tactical nuclear arms,
|
||
but implies political considerations—it is upon these that the role assigned to the battle (or
|
||
nonbattle) in war depends.
|
||
105. On the fundamental differences between Tamerlane and Genghis Khan, see Rene
|
||
Grousset, The Empire of the Steppes, trans. Naomi Walford (New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers
|
||
University Press, 1970), pp. 417-419.
|
||
106. See Armees etfiscalite dans le monde antique, ed. A. Chastagnol, C. Nicolet, and
|
||
H. van Effenterre (Paris: CNRS, 1977); this colloquium best covers the fiscal aspect but
|
||
deals with the other two as well. The question of the distribution of land to soldiers and the
|
||
families of soldiers comes up in every State and plays an essential role. In one particular form,
|
||
it lay the foundation for fiefs and feudalism. But it already lay at the basis of "false fiefs"
|
||
around the world, most notably of the cleros and cleruchy in Greek civilization. Claire
|
||
Preaux, L'economie royale des Lagides (Brussels: Ed. de la Fondation Egyptologique Reine
|
||
Elisabeth, 1939), pp. 463ff.
|
||
107. Clausewitz, On War, especially book 8, and the commentary on these three theses by
|
||
Raymond Aron, Penser la guerre, vol. 1 (particularly pp. 139 ff., "Pourquoi les guerres de la
|
||
deuxieme espece?").
|
||
108. Erich Ludendorff, Der totale Krieg (Munich: Ludendorff Verlag, 1935), notes that
|
||
the evolution has been toward attributing more and more importance to the "people" and
|
||
"domestic policies" in war, whereas Clausewitz still puts the emphasis on armies and foreign
|
||
policy. This criticism is true overall, despite certain texts of Clausewitz. The same criticism is
|
||
also made by Lenin and the Marxists (although they obviously have a totally different concep-
|
||
tion of the people and domestic policy than Ludendorff). Certain authors have convincingly
|
||
564 D NOTES TO PP. 421-428
|
||
|
||
demonstrated that the proletariat is as much of military origin, naval in particular, as of indus-
|
||
trial origin; see, for example, Virilio, Speed and Politics, pp. 38, 40-41, 134-35.
|
||
109. As John Ulric Nef shows, it was during the great period of "limited war" (1640-1740)
|
||
that the phenomena of concentration, accumulation, and investment emerged—the same
|
||
phenomena that were later to determine "total war." See War and Human Progress (New
|
||
York: Norton, 1968). The Napoleonic code of war represents a turning point that brought
|
||
together the elements of total war: mobilization, transport, investment, information, etc.
|
||
110. On this "transcending" of fascism, and of total war, and on the new point of inversion
|
||
of Clausewitz's formula, see Virilio's entire analysis in L'insecurite du territoire, especially
|
||
chapter 1.
|
||
111. Guy Brossollet, Essai sur la non-bataille, pp. 15-16. The axiomatic notion of the
|
||
"unspecified enemy" is already well developed in official and unofficial texts on national
|
||
defense, on international law, and in the judicial or police spheres.
|
||
|
||
|
||
13. 7000 B.C.: Apparatus of Capture
|
||
1. The principal book in this respect is Mitra-Varuna (Paris: Gallimard, 1948) (it also
|
||
contains the analysis of the "One-Eyed" and the "One-Armed" gods).
|
||
2. The theme of the Binder-God and the magic knot has been the object of general stud-
|
||
ies in mythology, notably Mircea Eliade, Images and Symbols, trans. Philip Mairet (Kansas
|
||
City: Sheed, Andrews, and McMeel, 1961), chapter 3. But these studies are ambiguous
|
||
because they use a syncretic and archetypal method. Dumezil's method, on the other hand, is
|
||
differential: the theme of capture or of the bond only groups various data together under a dif-
|
||
ferential trait, which is constituted precisely by political sovereignty. On the opposition
|
||
between these two methods, one can refer to Edmond Ortigues, Le discours et le symbole
|
||
(Paris: Aubier, 1962).
|
||
3. Dumezil, Mitra- Varuna, pp. 113-114, 151, 202-203.
|
||
4. Ibid., p. 150: "There are many ways of being a god of war, and Tiwaz defines one that is
|
||
very badly expressed by the labels warrior god, god of combat... . Tiwaz is something else: the
|
||
jurist of war, and at the same time a kind of diplomat" (the same applies for Mars).
|
||
5. Ibid., pp. 124-132.
|
||
6. Ernst Junger, The Glass Bees, trans. Louise Bogan and Elizabeth Mayer (New York:
|
||
Noonday Press, 1960), p. 112 [translation modified to agree with the French translation cited
|
||
by the authors].
|
||
7. Marcel Detienne, Les maitres de verite dans la Grece archdique (Paris: Maspero,
|
||
1973), and "Le phalange, problemes et controverses," in Problemes de la guerre en Grece
|
||
ancienne (Civilisations et societes, no. 11), ed. Jean-Pierre Vernant (The Hague: Mouton,
|
||
1968). See also Jean-Pierre Vernant, The Origins of Greek Thought (Ithaca, N. Y: Cornell Uni-
|
||
versity Press, 1982).
|
||
8. Jacques Harmand cites an "enterprise using extensive manpower exceptionally
|
||
directed by a functionary, Ouni, under the Pharaoh Pepi I toward 1400 B.C."; La guerre
|
||
antique (Paris: PUF, 1973), p. 28. Even the military democracy Morgan described does not
|
||
explain, but presupposes, an archaic State of the imperial type (the work of Detienne and
|
||
Vernant establishes this). This imperial State itself functions first with jailers and police, and
|
||
not warriors: see Dumezil, Mitra- Varuna, pp. 200-204.
|
||
9. The idea itself of an Asiatic despotic formation appeared in the eighteenth century,
|
||
notably in Montesquieu, but was used to describe an evolved state of the empires and corre-
|
||
sponded to absolute monarchy. Entirely different is the viewpoint of Marx, who recreates the
|
||
notion in order to define the archaic empires. The principal texts in this regard are Marx,
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 428-433 D 565
|
||
|
||
Grundrisse, trans. Martin Nicolaus (New York: Vintage, 1973), pp. 471-514; Karl Wittfogel,
|
||
Oriental Despotism (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1957); and Pierre Vidal-
|
||
Naquet's preface to the first French edition, Le despotisme oriental (Paris: Minuit, 1964),
|
||
which was surpressed in the second edition at Wittfogel's request; Ferenc Tokei, Essays on the
|
||
Asiatic Mode of Production (Budapest: Akademiai Kiado, 1979); and the studies in CERM,
|
||
Sur le mode de production asiatique (Paris: Ed. Sociales, 1969).
|
||
10. Varron made a famous pun on nexum and nee suumfit ( = the thing does not become
|
||
the property of he who receives it). In effect, the nexum is a fundamental form of archaic
|
||
Roman law, according to which it is not an accord between contracting parties that creates an
|
||
obligation, but the borrower's or donor's word, in a magico-religious mode. This is not a con-
|
||
tract (mancipatio), and it involves no buying-selling, even deferred, and no interest, although
|
||
it seems to us that it may involve a kind of rent. See in particular Pierre Noailles, Fas et Jus
|
||
(Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1948); and Dumezil, who stresses the connection between the
|
||
nexum and the magic bond, Mitra- Varuna, pp. 118-124.
|
||
11. See the excavations and studies of James Mellaart, Earliest Civilizations in the Near
|
||
East (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1965) and CatalHuyuk(New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967). The
|
||
urbanist Jane Jacobs has drawn on this work in proposing an imperial model she calls "New
|
||
Obsidian" (after the name of the lava used to make tools), which may go back to the beginning
|
||
of Neolithic times, or even much further into the past. She stresses the "urban" origin of agri-
|
||
culture and the role of hybridizations occurring in the urban grain stocks: It is agriculture that
|
||
presupposes the stock, and not the reverse. In an as yet unpublished study, Jean Robert ana-
|
||
lyzes Mellaart's theses and Jacobs's hypothesis, applying them to new perspectives
|
||
(Decoloniser I'espace).
|
||
12. Clastres, Society against the State, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Urizen, 1977).
|
||
We have seen that, according to Clastres, primitive war is one of the principal mechanisms
|
||
warding off the State in that it maintains the opposition and dispersion of small segmentary
|
||
groups. But also, from this viewpoint, primitive war remains subordinated to these preven-
|
||
tive mechanisms and does not become autonomous as a machine, even when it comprises a
|
||
specialized body.
|
||
13. According to Griaznov, it was the sedentary farmers who went out on the steppe and
|
||
became nomadic, during the Bronze Age: This is a case of a zigzag movement in evolution. See
|
||
The Ancient Civilization of Southern Siberia, trans. James Hogarth (New York: Cowles,
|
||
1969), pp. 97-98, 131-133.
|
||
14. Jean Robert develops this notion of an "inversion of signs and messages": "In a first
|
||
phase, information circulates principally from the periphery toward the center, but at a cer-
|
||
tain critical point, the town begins to emit, in the direction of the rural world, increasingly
|
||
imperative messages"; the town becomes an exporter (Decoloniser I'espace).
|
||
15. On Chinese towns and their subordination to the imperial principle, see Etienne
|
||
Balazs, Chinese Civilization and Bureaucracy, trans. H. M. Wright (New Haven, Conn.: Yale
|
||
University Press, 1964), p. 410: "The social structures in both India and China automatically
|
||
rejected the town and offered, as it were, refractory, substandard material to it. It was because
|
||
society was well and truly frozen in a sort of irreducible system, a previous crystallization."
|
||
16. From all of these standpoints, Francois Chatelet questions the classical notion of the
|
||
city-state and doubts that the Athenian city can be equated with any variety of State: "La
|
||
Grece classique, la Raison, 1'Etat," in Alberto Asor Rosa et al., En marge. L 'Occident etses
|
||
"autres", (Paris: Aubier Montaigne, 1978). Islam was to confront analogous problems, as
|
||
would Italy, Germany, and Flanders beginning in the eleventh century; in these cases, politi-
|
||
cal power does not imply the State-form. An example is the community of Hanseatic towns,
|
||
which lacked functionaries, an army, and even legal status. The town is always inside a net-
|
||
work of towns, but, precisely, "the network of towns" does not coincide with "mosaic of
|
||
566 D NOTES TO PP. 433-439
|
||
|
||
States." On all of these points, see the analyses of Francois Fourquet and Lion Murard, Les
|
||
equipements de pouvoir. ville, territoires et equipements collectifs (Paris: 10/18, 1976), pp.
|
||
79-106.
|
||
17. Claude Levi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, trans Claire Jacobson and Brooke
|
||
Grundfest Schoeft (New York: Basic Books, 1963), pp. 150-151.
|
||
18. Louis Berthe analyzes a specific example of the need for a "third village" to prevent
|
||
the directional circuit from closing: "Ames et cadets, 1'alliance et la hierarchic chez les Baduj,"
|
||
L'Homme, vol. 5, no. 3/4 (July-December 1965), pp. 214-215.
|
||
19. Fernand Braudel, Capitalism and Material Life, 1400-1800, trans. Miriam Kochan
|
||
(New York: Harper and Row, 1967), 60), pp. 398,405,411. Emphasis added. (On town-State
|
||
relations in the West, see pp. 396-406.) And as Braudel notes, one of the reasons for the victory
|
||
of the States over the towns from the beginning of the fifteenth century was that the State
|
||
alone had the ability fully to appropriate the war machine: by means of the territorial recruit-
|
||
ment of men, material investment, the industrialization of war (it was more in the arms facto-
|
||
ries than in the pin factories that mass production and mechanical division appeared). The
|
||
commercial towns, on the other hand, required wars of short duration, resorted to mercenar-
|
||
ies, and were only able to encast the war machine.
|
||
20. This theme is frequently developed by Samir Amin: "Since the theory of relations
|
||
between different social formations cannot be an economistic one, international relations,
|
||
which belong precisely to this context, cannot give rise to an economic theory." Unequal
|
||
Development, trans. Brian Pearce (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1976), p. 146.
|
||
21. See Jacques Lacarriere, Les hommes ivres de Dieu (Paris: Fayard, 1975).
|
||
22. [TRANS: On capitalism repelling its limits, see Deleuze and Guattari, Anti-Oedipus,
|
||
trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
|
||
Press, 1983), pp. 230-232.]
|
||
23. Samir Amin analyzes this particularity of the "peripheral formations" of the Third
|
||
World and distinguishes two principal types, the oriental and African, and the American:
|
||
"The Americas, Asia and the Arab world, and Black Africa were not transformed in the same
|
||
way because they were not integrated at the same stage of capitalist development at the center
|
||
and therefore did not fulfill the same function in development." Unequal Development, p.
|
||
295. See also Accumulation on a Worldscale, vol. 2, trans. Brian Pearce (New York: Monthly
|
||
Review Press, 1974), pp. 390-394. We shall see, however, that under certain conditions the
|
||
center and the periphery are determined in such a way as to exchange their characteristics.
|
||
24. Gaetan Pirou, Economie liberate et economic dirigee, vol. 1 (Paris: Ed. Sedes, 1946-
|
||
1947), p. 117: "The productivity of the marginal worker determines not only that worker's
|
||
wage but that of all the others, in the same way that, when it was a question of commodities,
|
||
the utility of the last bucket of water or last sack of wheat governed the value not only of that
|
||
bucket or that sack but of all the other buckets and all the other sacks." (Marginalism seeks to
|
||
quantify the assemblage, when in fact all kinds of qualitative factors are at work in the evalua-
|
||
tion of the "last.")
|
||
25. On the importance of the theory of evaluation and feeling out for marginalism, see
|
||
Jacques Fradin's critical discussion, Les fondements logiques de la theorie neoclassique de
|
||
I'echange (Grenoble: Presses Universitaires de Grenoble, 1976). For Marxists, there is also a
|
||
groping evaluation, but one that can bear only on the quantity of socially necessary labor;
|
||
Engels speaks of this precisely in the context of precapitalist societies. He invokes "a process
|
||
of zig-zag approximation, often groping back and forth in the dark," which is governed more
|
||
or less by the "need for each person to have a rough idea of his costs" (one may wonder if this
|
||
last part of the phrase does not reinstate a sort of marginalist criterion). Engels, "Supplement
|
||
to Volume Three of Capital," in Marx, Capital, vol. 3, trans. David Fernbach (New York: Vin-
|
||
tage, 1981), p. 1036.
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 439-443 D 567
|
||
|
||
26. [TRANS: "Ophelimity" (from the Greek for "useful," "serviceable") was introduced by
|
||
Vilfredo Pareto in his Cows d'economie politique (1896), ed. G.-H. Bousquet and G. Busino
|
||
(Geneva: Librairie Droz, 1964), pp. 2-16. The first portion of this discussion is translated in
|
||
Vilfredo Pareto, Sociological Writings, ed. and intro. S. E. Fine, trans. Derick Mirtin (New
|
||
York: Praeger, 1966), pp. 97-102.]
|
||
27. David Ricardo, On the Principles of Political Economy, in The Works and Correspon-
|
||
dence of David Ricardo, vol. 1, ed. Piero Sraffa (London: Cambridge University Press,
|
||
1962), chapter 2. See also Marx's analysis of the two forms of "differential rent," Capital,
|
||
vol. 3, part 6.
|
||
28. Of course, the least fertile land is also in theory the most recent or the last in a series
|
||
(which allows many commentators to say that Ricardo prefigured marginalism in his theory
|
||
of rent). But this is not even a rule, and Marx shows that an "increasing sequence" is just as
|
||
possible as a "decreasing sequence" and that a better soil can "take the lowest place instead of
|
||
that which was formerly the worst." Capital, vol. 3, p. 798.
|
||
29. [TRANS: Capital, vol. 3, p. 788.]
|
||
30. Ricardo, On the Principles of Political Economy, p. 75: "If air, water, the elasticity of
|
||
steam, and the pressure of the atmosphere, were of different qualities; if they could be appro-
|
||
priated, and each quality existed only in moderate abundance, they, as well as the land, would
|
||
afford a rent, as the successive qualities were brought into use."
|
||
31. The two forms of differential rent are based on comparison. But Marx maintains the
|
||
existence of another form, unknown to the theorists (Ricardo), but with which the practition-
|
||
ers, he says, are quite familiar: absolute rent, based on the special character of landed property
|
||
as monopoly. In effect, land is not a commodity like the others because it is not reproducible at
|
||
the level of a determinable aggregate. There is therefore monopoly, which is not the same as
|
||
"monopoly price" (monopoly price, and the eventual corresponding rent, are totally different
|
||
questions). In the simplest terms, differential rent and absolute rent can be distinguished in
|
||
the following manner: since the price of the product is calculated on the basis of the worst soil,
|
||
the entrepreneur with the best soil would have a surplus profit if the latter were not trans-
|
||
formed into differential rent accruing to the landowner; but on the other hand, since agricul-
|
||
tural surplus value is proportionally greater than industrial surplus value (?), the agricultural
|
||
entrepreneur in general would have a surplus profit if the latter were not transformed into
|
||
absolute rent accruing to the landowner. Rent is thus a necessary element in the equalization
|
||
and adjustment of profit: whether it be the equalization of the agricultural profit rate (differ-
|
||
ential rent), or the equalization of this rate and the rate of industrial profit (absolute rent).
|
||
Certain Marxist economists have proposed an entirely different schema of absolute rent, but
|
||
one that maintains Marx's necessary distinction. [TRANS: On absolute rent, see Marx, Capital,
|
||
vol. 3, part 6, chapter 45, pp. 895-899.]
|
||
32. Bernard Schmitt, Monnaie, salaires et profit (Paris: Castella, 1980), pp. 289-290,
|
||
distinguishes between two forms of capture or "harnessing," which correspond moreover to
|
||
the two principal figures of the hunt, waiting and pursuit. Rent would be a residual or
|
||
waiting kind of capture because it depends on external forces and operates by transfer;
|
||
profit would be a capture of pursuit or conquest because it derives from a specific action and
|
||
requires a force of its own or a "creation." This holds true, however, only in relation to differ-
|
||
ential rent; as Marx noted, absolute rent represents the "creative" aspect of landed property
|
||
(Capital, vol. 3, p. 889).
|
||
33. Edouard Will, Korinthiaka (Paris: Ed. De Boccard, 1955), pp. 470ff., analyzes a late,
|
||
but exemplary, case, that of the tyrant Cypselos's reform in Corinth: (1) a portion of the land
|
||
belonging to the hereditary aristocracy was confiscated and distributed to the poor peasants;
|
||
(2) but at the same time a metallic stock was constituted, through seizure of the property of
|
||
proscribed persons; (3) this money itself was distributed to the poor, but in order for them to
|
||
568 D NOTES TO PP. 443-449
|
||
|
||
give it to the old owners as an indemnity; (4) the old owners from then on paid their taxes in
|
||
money, so as to ensure a circulation or turnover of the currency, and an equivalence between
|
||
money, goods, and services. We already find analogous figures directly inscribed in the
|
||
archaic empires, independently of the problems of private property. For example, land is dis-
|
||
tributed to the functionaries in their capacity as functionaries, and they exploit or lease it. But
|
||
if the functionary thereby receives a rent in labor or in kind from it, he owes the emperor a tax
|
||
payable in money. Hence the necessity of "banks," which, under complex conditions, ensure
|
||
the equivalence, conversion, and circulation of goods-money throughout the economy; see
|
||
Guillaume Cardascia, "Armee et fiscalite dans la Babylone achemenide," in Armees et
|
||
fiscalit'e dans le monde antique (Paris: CNRS, 1977).
|
||
34. [TRANS: On these three forms of rent, see Marx, Capital, vol. 3, part 6, chapter 47,
|
||
pp. 925-938.]
|
||
35. Authors like Will and Gabriel Ardant have demonstrated that the commercial func-
|
||
tion does not account for the origin of money, tied to ideas of "payment," "settlement," "tax-
|
||
ation." Will proves this in particular for the Greek and Western worlds; but even in the
|
||
oriental empires, we think that the monopoly over monetarized trade assumes monetary
|
||
taxation. See Edouard Will, "Reflexions et hypotheses sur les origines du monnayage,"
|
||
Revue numismatique, vol. 17 (1955), pp. 3-24; Gabriel Ardant, Histoire flnanciere de
|
||
I'antiquite a nos jours (Paris: Gallimard, 1976), pp. 28ff.: "The milieus that gave rise to taxa-
|
||
tion also gave rise to money."
|
||
36. On this aspect of indirect taxation, see Arghiri Emmanuel, Unequal Exchange, trans.
|
||
Brian Pearce (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1972), pp. 1-2, 228-236 (in relation to for-
|
||
eign trade). Concerning the relations taxation-trade, a particularly interesting case is that of
|
||
mercantilism, analyzed by Eric Alliez (Capital et pouvoir, unpublished manuscript).
|
||
37. [TRANS: Marx presents his trinity formula (capital-profit, land-ground rent, labor-
|
||
wages) in Capital, vol. 3, chapter 48.]
|
||
38. Bernard Schmitt, Monnaie, salaires et profits.
|
||
39. Marx often emphasizes the following points, particularly in his analysis of primitive
|
||
accumulation: (1) Primitive accumulation precedes the mode of production and makes it pos-
|
||
sible. (2) It therefore implies specific action by the State and the law, which are not opposed to
|
||
violence but, on the contrary, promote it ("These methods depend in part on brute force....
|
||
But they all employ the power of the state, the concentrated and organized force of society."
|
||
Capital, vol. 1, trans. Ben Fowkes [New York: Vintage, 1977], chapter 31, p. 915). (3) This
|
||
lawful violence appears first in its raw form but ceases to be conscious to the degree that the
|
||
mode of production becomes established; it seems to be a fact of nature pure and simple
|
||
("direct extra-economic force is still of course used, but only in exceptional cases"; ibid., p.
|
||
899). (4) A movement such as this is explained by the particular character of this violence,
|
||
which is in no case reducible to theft, crime, or illegality (see Notes surAdolph Wagner in Oeu-
|
||
vres de Karl Marx, "Pleiade" edition, vol. 2, ed. Maximilien Rubel [Paris: Gallimard, 1968]):
|
||
what is taken away from the worker is not something surface level; the capitalist "does not
|
||
limit himself to taking away or stealing, but extorts the production of a surplus value, in other
|
||
words, he first contributes to the creation of that from which he takes away.... A part of the
|
||
value created without the labor of the capitalist can be appropriated legally by the capitalist,
|
||
in other words, without violating the corresponding right to the exchange of commodities."
|
||
40. Jean Robert thoroughly demonstrates, in this context, that primitive accumulation
|
||
implies the violent construction of a homogenized, "colonized" space ("Decoloniser
|
||
1'espace," unpublished manuscript).
|
||
41. Ferenc Tokei, "Les conditions de la propriete fonciere dans la Chine de 1'epoque
|
||
Tcheou," Acta Antiqua, vol. 6 (1958), pp. 245-300. Marx and Engels already noted that the
|
||
Roman plebs (partially composed of freedmen) alone had the right to the "transfer of property
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 449-453 D 569
|
||
|
||
out of the ager publicus" (Marx, Grundrisse, p. 477): the plebeians became private owners of
|
||
landed property, and also of commercial and industrial wealth, precisely insofar as they were
|
||
"excluded from all public rights" (Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the
|
||
State [New York: International Publishers, 1972], p. 190).
|
||
42. See the two great books by V. Gordon Childe, The Most Ancient East (London: K.
|
||
Paul, Trench, Triibner, 1928) and especially The Prehistory of European Civilization (London:
|
||
Cassell, 1962). In particular, archaeological analysis permits Childe to conclude that nowhere
|
||
in the Aegean world were there accumulations of wealth or food comparable to those of the
|
||
Orient (The Prehistory of European Civilization, pp. 106-110).
|
||
43. On the differences between "generalized slavery" in the archaic empire, and private
|
||
slavery, feudal corvee, etc., see Charles Parain, "Protohistoire mediterraneenne et mode de
|
||
production asiatique," in CERM, Sur le mode de production asiatique, pp. 170-173.
|
||
44. Gerard Boulvert, Domestique et fonctionnaire sous le haul-empire romain (Paris: Les
|
||
Belles Lettres, 1974). More generally, Paul Veyne has analyzed the formation of "subjective
|
||
law" in the Roman Empire, the corresponding institutions, and the new meaning of the public
|
||
and private. He demonstrates that Roman law is a "law without concepts" that proceeds by
|
||
"topics," and in this sense differs from the modern, "axiomatic" conception of the law. See
|
||
Veyne, Le pain et le cirque (Paris: Seuil, 1976), chapters 3 and 4, and p. 744.
|
||
45. See Francois Hincker, "La monarchic absolue francaise," in CERM, Sur lefeodalisme
|
||
(Paris: Ed. Sociaies, 1971).
|
||
46. Edgar Quinet, La genie des religions, vol. 1 of Oeuvres Completes (Paris: Hachette,
|
||
ca. 1899).
|
||
47. Marx, "Introduction to the Critique of Political Economy," in A Contribution to the
|
||
Critique of Political Economy, trans. N. I. Stone (Chicago: Charles H. Kerr, 1904), p. 298
|
||
[translation modified].
|
||
48. On the historical independence of the two series, and their "encounter," see Etienne
|
||
Balibar in Althusser and Balibar, Lirele Capital, vol. 2 (Paris: Maspero, 1968), pp. 286-289.
|
||
49. Arghiri Emmanuel, Unequal Exchange, pp. 13-14, and the following passage he cites
|
||
from Paul Sweezy, The Theory of Capitalist Development (New York: Monthly Review Press,
|
||
1942), p. 338: "'Capital' is not simply another name for means of production; it is means of
|
||
production reduced to a qualitatively homogeneous and quantitatively measurable fund of
|
||
value" (whence the equalization of profit). In his analysis of the primitive accumulation of
|
||
capital, Maurice Dobb (Studies in the Development of Capitalism, rev. ed. [New York: Inter-
|
||
national Publishers, 1964], pp. 177-186) effectively demonstrates that primitive accumula-
|
||
tion bears not on the means of production but on "rights or titles to wealth" (p. 177; modified
|
||
to agree with the French translation cited by the authors), which, depending on the circum-
|
||
stances, are convertible into means of production.
|
||
50. See the distinction certain jurists make between Roman, "topical," law, and modern,
|
||
"axiomatic," law of the civil-code type. We may define certain fundamental ways in which the
|
||
French Civil Code is closer to an axiomatic than to a code: (1) the predominance of the
|
||
enunciative form over the imperative and over affective formulas (damnation, exhortation,
|
||
admonishment, etc.); (2) the code's pretension that it forms a complete and saturated rational
|
||
system; (3) but at the same time the relative independence of the propositions, which permit
|
||
axioms to be added. On these aspects, see Jean Ray, Essai sur la structure logique du code civil
|
||
francais (Paris: Alcan, 1926). It has been established that the systematization of Roman law
|
||
took place very late, in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.
|
||
51. [TRANS: Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, ed. and intro. Dirk J.
|
||
Struik, trans. Martin Mulligan (New York: International Publishers, 1964), p. 129.]
|
||
52. See Jean Saint-Geours, Pouvoir et finance (Paris: Fayard, 1979). Saint-Geours is one
|
||
570 D NOTES TO PP. 453-463
|
||
|
||
of the best analysts of the monetary system, as well as of "private-public" mixes in the modern
|
||
economy.
|
||
53. On the tendency toward the elimination of ground rent in capitalism, see Samir Amin
|
||
and Kostas Vergopoulos, La question paysanne et le capitalisme (Paris: Ed. Anthropos, 1974).
|
||
Amin analyzes the reasons why ground rent and rent of mines keep or assume a present-day
|
||
meaning in the peripheral regions, although in different ways; The Law of Value and Historical
|
||
Materialism, trans. Brian Pearce (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1978), chapters 4 and 6.
|
||
54. Introductory books on the axiomatic method emphasize a certain number of prob-
|
||
lems. For example, Robert Blanche's fine book, L'axiomatique (Paris: PUF, 1959) [abridged
|
||
and translated by G. B. Keeneas^4jc/o/r)<3i/cj(NewYork: Free Press of Glencoe, 1962)]. There
|
||
is first of all the question of the respective independence of the axioms, and whether or not the
|
||
system is saturated, or "strongly complete" (sec. 14 and 15). Second, there is the question of
|
||
"models of realization," their heterogeneity, but also their isomorphy in relation to the axio-
|
||
matic system (sec. 12). Then there is the possibility of a polymorphy of models, not only in a
|
||
nonsaturated system, but even in a saturated axiomatic (sec. 12, 15, and 26). Then, once
|
||
again, there is the question of the "undecidable propositions" an axiomatic confronts (sec.
|
||
20). Finally, there is the question of "power," by which nondemonstrable infinite sets exceed
|
||
the axiomatic (sec. 26 and "the power of the continuum"). The comparison of politics to an
|
||
axiomatic is based on all of these aspects.
|
||
55. Lewis Mumford, "The First Megamnchine," Diogenes, no. 55 (July-September 1966),
|
||
p. 3. [translation modified to agree with the French translation cited by the authors].
|
||
56. Ergonomics distinguishes between "human-machine" systems (or work posts) and
|
||
"humans-machines" systems (communicational aggregates composed of human and
|
||
nonhuman elements). But this is not only a difference of degree; the second point of view is
|
||
not a generalization of the first: "The notion of information loses its anthropocentric aspect,"
|
||
and the problems are not of adaptation but of the choice of a human or nonhuman element
|
||
depending on the case. See Maurice de Montmollin, Les systemes hommes-machines (Paris:
|
||
PUF, 1967). The issue is no longer to adapt, even under violence, but to localize: Where is your
|
||
place? Even handicaps can be made useful, instead of being corrected or compensated for. A
|
||
deaf-mute can be an essential part of a "humans-machines" communicational system.
|
||
57. One of the basic themes of science fiction is to show how machinic enslavement com-
|
||
bines with processes of subjection, but exceeds and differs from them, performing a qualita-
|
||
tive leap. Take Ray Bradbury: television not as an instrument located at the center of the
|
||
house, but as forming the walls of the house.
|
||
58. See Lewis Mumford, The Pentagon of Power,-vol. 2 of The Myth of the Machine (New
|
||
York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1970), pp. 236-360 (a comparison of the "old megama-
|
||
chine" and the modern one; despite writing, the old megamachine notably suffered from dif-
|
||
ficulties in "communication").
|
||
59. Marx, Manuscripts of 1844, p. 129.
|
||
60. Historically, these have been the major problems in axiomatics: "undecidable" prop-
|
||
ositions (contradictory statements are also nondemonstrable); the powers of infinite sets,
|
||
which by nature elude axiomatic treatment ("the continuum, for example, cannot be con-
|
||
ceived axiomatically in its structural specificity since every axiomatization one can give it
|
||
will rely on a denumerable model"). See Blanche, L'axiomatique, p. 80.
|
||
61. The "intuitionist" school (Brouwer, Heytig, Griss, Bouligand, etc.) is of great impor-
|
||
tance in mathematics, not because it asserted the irreducible rights of intuition, or even
|
||
because it elaborated a very novel constructivism, but because it developed a conception of
|
||
problems, and of a calculus of problems that intrinsically rivals axiomatics and proceeds by
|
||
other rules (notably with regard to the excluded middle).
|
||
62. In our opinion, one of the best analyses of the Nazi economy is Jean-Pierre Faye's
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 463-472 D 571
|
||
|
||
Langages totalitaires (Paris: Hermann, 1972), pp. 664-676. Faye shows that Nazism is indeed
|
||
a totalitarianism, precisely because of its minimal State, its refusal of any statification of the
|
||
economy, its reduction of wages, its hostility toward large-scale public works. But at the same
|
||
time, he shows that Nazism carries out the creation of domestic capital, strategic construc-
|
||
tion, and the building of an arms industry, which makes it rival or sometimes even meld with
|
||
an economy of socialist leaning ("something that seems to resemble the Swedish loans praised
|
||
by Myrdal with a view to large-scale projects, but which is in fact and immediately its oppo-
|
||
site, the writing of an arms economy and a war economy," and the corresponding difference
|
||
between "the public works entrepreneur" and the "army supplier"; pp. 668, 674).
|
||
63. See the critical list of the axioms of the periphery presented by Samir Amin, Accumu-
|
||
lation on a Worldscale, pp. 390-394.
|
||
64. Paul Virilio, L'insecurite du territoire (Paris: Stock, 1975); Speed and Politics, trans.
|
||
Mark Polizzotti (New York: Semiotext[e], 1986); Defense populaire et luttes ecologiques
|
||
(Paris: Galilee, 1978), forthcoming in English translation from Semiotext(e) as Popular
|
||
Defense and Ecological Struggles: it is precisely beyond fascism and total war that the war
|
||
machine finds its complete object, in the menacing peace of nuclear deterrence. It is there that
|
||
the reversal of Clausewitz's formula takes on a concrete meaning, at the same time as State
|
||
politics tends to wither and the war machine takes over a maximum of civil functions ("place
|
||
the whole of civil society under the regime of military security," "disqualify the whole of the
|
||
planet's habitat by stripping the peoples of their quality of inhabitant," "erase the distinction
|
||
between wartime and peacetime"; see the role of the media in this respect). Certain European
|
||
police forces could be taken as an example, when they claim the right to "shoot on sight": they
|
||
cease to be a cogwheel in the State apparatus and become pieces in a war machine.
|
||
65. Braudel shows how this center of gravity formed in northern Europe, but at the out-
|
||
come of movements that, starting in the ninth and tenth centuries, put the European spaces of
|
||
the North and the South in competition or rivalry with one another (this problem is not to be
|
||
confused with that of the town-form and State-form, but does intersect with it). See
|
||
"Naissance d'une economie-monde," Urbi, no. 1 (September 1979), pp. 3-20.
|
||
66. A movement in Marxist research formed on the basis of the work of Mario Tronti
|
||
(Operai e capitate [Turin: G. Einaudi, 1971]; French translation, Owners et capital [Paris:
|
||
Bourgois, 1977]), then that of Italian autonomy and Antonio Negri, whose aim was to analyze
|
||
the new forms of work and the struggle against work. It was a question of showing simultane-
|
||
ously: (1) that the struggle against work is not an accidental or "marginal" phenomenon in
|
||
capitalism, but one essential to the composition of capital (the growth in the proportion of
|
||
constant capital), and, (2) that this phenomenon engenders a new type of worldwide
|
||
struggle—workers' struggles, popular struggles, ethnic struggles—in every domain. See
|
||
Antonio Negri, especially Marx Beyond Marx: Lessons on the Grundrisse, ed. Jim Fleming,
|
||
trans. Harry Cleaver, Michael Ryan, and Maurizion Viano (South Hadley, Mass.: Bergin and
|
||
Garvey, 1984); Karl Heinz Roth, Die "andere" Arbeiterbewegung (Munich: Trikont, 1974);
|
||
and the current work in France of Yann Moulier, Alain and Daniele Guillerm, Benjamin
|
||
Coriat, etc. [TRANS: The best sources on the autonomy movement in English are Italy:
|
||
Autonomia. Post-Political Politics, Semiotext(e), vol. 3, no. 3 (1980) and Autonomy and the
|
||
Crisis. Italian Marxist Texts of 'the Theory and Praxis oj'a Class Movement: 1964-1979 (Lon-
|
||
don: Red Notes and CSE Books, 1979). Marx Beyond Marx includes a lengthy epilogue by
|
||
Michael Ryan summarizing Negri's major works and a bibliography of writings on the Italian
|
||
movement available in English.]
|
||
67. This is one of the essential theses of Tronti, who defined the new conceptions of the
|
||
"mass-worker" and of the relation to work: "To struggle against capital, the working class must
|
||
fight against itself insofar as it is capital; this is the maximal stage of contradiction, not forthe
|
||
workers, but for the capitalists.... The plan of capital begins to run backward, not as a social
|
||
572 D NOTES TO PP. 472-481
|
||
|
||
development, but as a revolutionary process." See Ouvriers et capital, p. 322; this is what Negri
|
||
has called the "crisis of the planning state" (Crisi dello Stato-plano [Milan: Feltrinelli, 1974]).
|
||
68. This is another aspect of the present-day situation: in addition to the new struggles
|
||
tied to work and the evolution in work, there is the entire domain of what are called "alterna-
|
||
tive practices" and the construction of such practices (pirate radio stations would be the
|
||
simplest example; other examples are urban community networks, the alternative to psychia-
|
||
try, etc.). On all these points, and the link between the two aspects, see Franco Berardi Bifo,
|
||
Finalemente il cielo e caduto sulla terra (Milan: Squilibri, 1978); and Les Untorelli, Re-
|
||
cherches, no. 30 (1977) (special issue on autonomia).
|
||
|
||
14.1440: The Smooth and the Striated
|
||
1. Andre Leroi-Gourhan, L'homme et la matiere (Paris: Albin Michel, 1971), pp. 244ff.
|
||
(and the opposition between fabric and felt).
|
||
2. William Faulkner, Sartoris (New York: Random House, 1956), p. 151.
|
||
3. On the history of the quilt and patchwork in American immigration, see Jonathan
|
||
Holstein, American Pieced Quilts (New York: Viking, 1973) (with reproductions and bibliog-
|
||
raphy). Holstein does not claim that the quilt is the principal source of American art, but he
|
||
does note the extent to which the "white on white" of plain quilts and patchwork composi-
|
||
tions inspired or gave impetus to certain tendencies in American painting: "We can see in
|
||
many [quilts] such phenomena as 'op' effects, serial images, use of 'color fields,' deep under-
|
||
standing of negative space, mannerisms of formal abstraction and the like," (p. 13).
|
||
4. Pierre Boulez, Boulez on Music Today, trans. Susan Bradshaw and Richard Bennett
|
||
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 83ff. We provide a summary of
|
||
Boulez's analysis in the following paragraph.
|
||
5. [TRANS: Boulez, Boulez on Music Today, p. 87. Translation modified.]
|
||
6. On this indexing of the inside and the outside among the nomads of the desert, see
|
||
Annie Milovanoff, "La seconde peau du nomade," Nouvelles litteraires, no. 2646 (July 27,
|
||
1978), p. 18. And on the relations between the igloo and the outside among the nomads of the
|
||
ice, see Edmund Carpenter, Eskimo (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 1964).
|
||
7. See the two convergent descriptions of the space of ice and the space of sand: Edmund
|
||
Carpenter, Eskimo, and Wilfred Thesiger, Arabian Sands (London: Longmans, Green, 1959).
|
||
(In both cases, there is an indifference to astronomy.)
|
||
8. See Pierre Chaunu's study, L'expansion europeenne du XHIe au XVe siecle (Paris:
|
||
PUF, 1969), pp. 288-305.
|
||
9. See in particular Paul Adam, "Navigation primitive et navigation astronomique," in
|
||
Les aspects internationaux de la d'ecouverte oceanique aux XVe et XVIe siecles. Ve Collogue
|
||
international d'histoire maritime, ed. Michel Mollat and Paul Adam (Paris: SEVPEN, 1960),
|
||
pp. 91-112. (See the operative geometry of the pole star.)
|
||
10. Guy Beaujouan, "Science livresque et nautique au XVe siecle," Les aspects interna-
|
||
tionaux de la d'ecouverte oceanique, pp. 61-90.
|
||
11. See Paul Virilio, L'insecurite du territoire (Paris: Stock, 1975), on how the sea
|
||
reconstitutes a smooth space with the "fleet in being," etc.; and how a vertical smooth
|
||
space of aerial and stratospheric domination springs up (especially chapter 4, "Le littoral
|
||
vertical," pp. 93-109).
|
||
12. Emmanuel Laroche, Histoire de la racine "Nem " en grec ancien (Paris: Klincksieck,
|
||
1949), clearly notes the difference between the ideas of distribution and allocation, between
|
||
the two linguistic groups concerned, between the two kinds of space, between the "province"
|
||
pole and the "city" pole.
|
||
13. This expression is found in Rene Thorn, who applies it to a continuous variation in
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 481-493 D 573
|
||
|
||
which the variable reacts upon its antecedents: Modeles math'ematiques de la morphogenese
|
||
(Paris: 10/18, 1974), pp. 218-219.
|
||
14. On Riemann's and Helmholtz's presentations of multiplicity, see Jules Vuillemin,
|
||
Philosophic de I'algebre (Paris: PUF, 1962), pp. 409ff.
|
||
15. See Bertrand Russell, The Principles of'Mathematics (New York: Norton, 1964), chap-
|
||
ter 31. The following discussion does not conform to Russell's theory. An excellent analysis of
|
||
the notions of distance and magnitude according to Meinong and Russell may be found in
|
||
Albert Spaier, Lapens'ee et la quantit'e (Paris: Alcan, 1927).
|
||
16. Beginning in chapter 2 of Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of
|
||
Consciousness, trans. F. L. Pogson (New York: Macmillan, 1958), Bergson repeatedly uses the
|
||
noun "multiplicity," under conditions that should attract the attention of commentators; that
|
||
there is an implicit reference to Riemann seems beyond doubt. Later, in Matter and Memory,
|
||
trans. Nancy Margaret Paul and W. Scott Palmer (New York: Humanities Press, 1978), he
|
||
explains that Achilles' stride can be divided perfectly into "submultiples" that differ in
|
||
nature, however, from that which they divide; the same goes for the tortoise's stride; and the
|
||
submultiples, "in both cases," themselves differ in nature.
|
||
17. See Bergson, Time and Free Will, p. 82: if a multiplicity "implies the possibility of
|
||
treating any number whatever as a provisional unit which can be added to itself, inversely the
|
||
units in their turn are true numbers which are as big as we like, but are regarded as provision-
|
||
ally indivisible for the purpose of compounding them with one another."
|
||
18. Albert Lautman, Les sch'emas de structure (Paris: Hermann, 1938), pp. 23, 34-35.
|
||
19. On this properly Euclidean conjunction (which is very different from the process of
|
||
accumulation), see Lautman, ibid., pp. 45-48.
|
||
20. Benoit Mandelbrot, Fractals: Form, Chance, and Dimension (San Francisco: W. H.
|
||
Freeman, 1977).
|
||
21. On these two kinds of space, see Jean-Pierre Vernant, Mythe et pens'ee chez les Grecs,
|
||
vol. 1 (Paris: Maspero, 1971-1974), pp. 174-175.
|
||
22. Michel Serres, La naissance de la physique dans le texte de Lucrece. Fleuves et turbu-
|
||
lences (Paris: Minuit, 1977): "Physics is based much more on a vectorial space than on a met-
|
||
ric space" (p. 79). On the hydraulic problem, see pp. 104-107.
|
||
23. Serres, La naissance de la physique, pp. 35, 135ff.
|
||
24. Anne Querrien has clearly demonstrated the importance of the Ecole des Ponts et
|
||
Chaussees (School of Bridges and Roadways) in this elaboration of the concept of work. For
|
||
example, Navier, an engineer and professor of mechanics, wrote in 1819: "We must establish a
|
||
mechanical currency with which to estimate the quantities of work used to accomplish every
|
||
kind of fabrication."
|
||
25. It is a commonplace of missionaries' narratives that there is nothing corresponding to
|
||
the category of work, even in transhumant agriculture, with its laborious ground-clearing
|
||
activities. Marshall Sahlins is not content to remark the briefness of the time devoted to the
|
||
labor necessary for maintenance and reproduction, but goes on to stress qualitative factors:
|
||
the continuous variation that regulates activity, and the mobility or freeness of movement,
|
||
which excludes stockpiling and is measured in terms of the "convenience of transporting the
|
||
object." "La premiere societe d'abondance," Les temps modernes, no. 268 (October 1968),
|
||
pp. 654-656, 662-663, 672-673.
|
||
26. The principal texts are Alois Riegl, Die Spatromische Kunstindustrie (Vienna:
|
||
Staatdruckerei, 1927); Wilhelm Worringer, Abstraction and Empathy; A Contribution to the
|
||
Psychology of Style, trans. Michael Bullock (New York: International Universities Press,
|
||
1963); Henri Maldiney, Regard, parole, espace(Lausanne: L'Age d'homme, 1973), especially
|
||
"L'art et le pouvoir du fond," and Maldiney's discussion of Cezanne.
|
||
27. All of these points already relate to Riemannian space, with its essential relation to
|
||
574 D NOTES TO PP. 493-498
|
||
|
||
"monads" (as opposed to the unitary Subject of Euclidean space): see Gilles Chatelet, "Sur
|
||
une petite phrase de Riemann," Analytiques, no. 3 (May 1979). Although the "monads" are no
|
||
longer thought to be closed upon themselves, and are postulated to entertain direct, step-by-
|
||
step local relations, the purely monadological point of view proves inadequate and should be
|
||
superseded by a "nomadology" (the ideality of striated space versus the realism of smooth
|
||
space).
|
||
28. See Edmund Carpenter's description in Eskimo of ice space, and of the igloo: "There
|
||
is no middle distance, no perpecti ve, no outline, nothing the eye can cling to except thousands
|
||
of smokey plumes of snow... a land without bottom or edge ... a labyrinth alive with the
|
||
movements of crowded people. No flat static walls arrest the ear or eye ... and the eye can
|
||
glance through here, past there" (no pagination).
|
||
29. These two aspects, the Encompassing Element and the Center, figure in Jean-Pierre
|
||
Vernant's analysis of space in Anaximander; Mythe et pens'eee chez les Grecs (Paris: Maspero,
|
||
1971-1974), vol. 1, part 3. From another perspective, the entire history of the desert concerns
|
||
the possibility of its becoming the encompassing element, and also of being repelled, rejected
|
||
by the center, as though in an inversion of movement. In a phenomenology of religion like that
|
||
of Van der Leeuw, the nomos itself does indeed appear as the encompassing-limit or ground,
|
||
and also as that which is repelled, excluded, in a centrifugal movement.
|
||
30. Whatever interactions there may be, the "art of the steppes" had a specificity that was
|
||
communicated to the migrating Germans; in spite of his many reservations about nomad cul-
|
||
ture, Rene Grousset makes this point in The Empire of the Steppes, trans. Naomi Walford
|
||
(New Brunswick, N. J.: Rutgers University Press, 1970). pp. 11 -25. He notes the irreducibility
|
||
of Scythian art to Assyrian art, Sarmatian art to Persian art, and Hunnic art to Chinese art. He
|
||
even points out that the art of the steppes influenced more than it borrowed (see in particular
|
||
the question of Ordos art and its relations to China).
|
||
31. On this question of light and color, in particular in Byzantine art, see Henri Maldiney,
|
||
Regard, parole, espace, pp. 203ff., 239ff.
|
||
32. The correlation, "haptic-close-abstract," was already suggested by Riegl. But it
|
||
was Worringer who developed the theme of the abstract line. Although he conceives of it
|
||
essentially in its Egyptian form, he describes a second form in which the abstract assumes
|
||
an intense life and an expressionist value, all the while remaining inorganic: Abstraction
|
||
and Empathy, chapter 5, and especially Form in Gothic (London: Putnam's and Sons,
|
||
1927), pp. 38-55.
|
||
33. Andre Leroi-Gourhan, Legesteet la parole (Paris: Albin Michel, 1964-1965), vol. 1,
|
||
Technique et langage, pp. 263ff.; vol. 2, La memoire et les rythmes, pp. 219ff. ("Rhythmic
|
||
marks are anterior to explicit figures.") Worringer's position is very ambiguous; thinking that
|
||
prehistoric art is fundamentally figurative, he excludes it from Art, on the same grounds as he
|
||
excludes the "scribblings of a child" (Abstraction and Empathy, pp. 51-55). Then he advances
|
||
the hypothesis that the cave dwellers were the "ultimate result" of a series he says began with
|
||
the abstract (p. 130). But would not such a hypothesis force Worringer to revise his conception
|
||
of the abstract, and to cease identifying it with Egyptian geometricism?
|
||
34. Worringer establishes an opposition between the power of repetition, which is
|
||
mechanical, multiplying, and without fixed orientation, and the force of symmetry, which is
|
||
organic, additive, oriented, and centered. He sees this as the fundamental difference between
|
||
Gothic ornamentation and Greek or classical ornamentation: Form in Gothic, pp. 53-55
|
||
("The Ceaseless Melody of the Northern Line"). In a fine book, Esthetiques d'Orient et
|
||
d'Occident (Paris: E. Leroux, 1937), Laura Morgenstern develops a particular example, dis-
|
||
tinguishing the "symmetrical antithetism" of Sassanid Persian art from the "disjointed
|
||
antithetism" of the art of the prdto-Iranian nomads (Sarmatians). Many authors, however,
|
||
have stressed the centered and symmetrical motifs in barbarian or nomad art. Worringer
|
||
NOTES TO PP. 498-499 D 575
|
||
|
||
anticipated this objection: "Instead of the regular and invariably geometrical star or rosette or
|
||
similar restful forms, in the North we find the revolving wheel, the turbine or the so-called sun
|
||
wheel, all designs which express violent movement. Moreover, the movement is peripheral
|
||
and not radial" (Form in Gothic, p. 54). The history of technology confirms the importance of
|
||
the turbine in the life of the nomads. In another, bio-aesthetic, context, Gabriel Tarde opposes
|
||
repetition as indefinite potential (puissance) to symmetry as limitation. With symmetry, life
|
||
constituted an organism for itself, taking a star-shaped or reflected, infolded form (the radiata
|
||
and mollusks). It is true that in doing so it unleashed another type of repetition, external
|
||
reproduction; see L 'opposition universelle (Paris: Alcan, 1897).
|
||
35. [TRANS: Worringer, Abstraction and Empathy, p. 33]
|
||
36. [TRANS: Worringer, Abstraction and Empathy, p. 42]
|
||
37. On all of these points, see Georges Charriere's very intuitive book, Scythian Art (New
|
||
York: Alpine Fine Arts Collection, 1979), which includes a great number of reproductions. It
|
||
is doubtless Rene Grousset who has most effectively emphasized "slowness" as a dramatic
|
||
pole of nomad art: The Empire of the Steppes, pp. 13-14.
|
||
38. Dora Vallier, in her preface to the French translation of Abstraction and Empathy
|
||
(Abstraction et Einfuhlung [Paris: Klincksieck, 1978]), is right to note Worringer and
|
||
Kandinsky's independence from one another, and the differences between the problems they
|
||
were addressing. However, she maintains that there is still convergence and resonance
|
||
between them. In a sense, all art is abstract, with the figurative springing from certain types of
|
||
abstraction. But in another sense, since there are very different types of lines (Egyptian-
|
||
geometrical, Greek-organic, Gothic-vital, etc.), the question then becomes one of determin-
|
||
ing which line remains abstract, or realizes abstraction as such. It is doubtful that it is the
|
||
geometrical line, since it still draws a figure, even though an abstract and nonrepresentative
|
||
one. Rather, the abstract line is that defined by Michael Fried in relation to certain works by
|
||
Pollock: multidirectional, with neither inside nor outside, form nor background, delimiting
|
||
nothing, describing no contour, passing between spots or points, filling a smooth space, stir-
|
||
ring up a close-lying haptic visual matter that "both invites the act of seeing on the part of the
|
||
spectator yet gives his eye nowhere to rest once and for all," (Three American Painters
|
||
[Cambridge, Mass.: Fogg Art Museum, 1965], p. 14). In Kandinsky himself, abstraction is
|
||
realized not so much by geometrical structures as by lines of march or transit that seem to
|
||
recall Mongolian nomadic motifs.
|
||
This page intentionally left blank
|
||
Bibliography
|
||
This page intentionally left blank
|
||
Bibliography
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
(compiled by Brian Massumi)
|
||
|
||
I before an entry indicates an interview.
|
||
P before an entry indicates a preface, postface, introduction, or afterword.
|
||
|
||
by Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari
|
||
|
||
English
|
||
Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Preface by Michel Foucault. Trans. Robert
|
||
Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane. New York: Viking, 1977; rpt. Minneapolis: Uni-
|
||
versity of Minnesota Press, 1983. Translation of I'Anti-Oedipe.
|
||
Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature. Trans. DanaPolan. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
|
||
Press, 1986. Translation of Kafka: Pour une litterature mineure.
|
||
Nomadology: The War Machine. Trans. Brian Massumi. New York: Semiotext(e), 1986.
|
||
Translation of Chapter \2ofMillePlateaux.
|
||
On the Line. Trans. John Johnston. New York: Semiotext(e), 1983. Translation of "Rhizome"
|
||
(the final version published in Mille plateaux) and "Politics" (Chapter 6 of Dialogues).
|
||
A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian Massumi. Minneapolis:
|
||
University of Minnesota Press, 1987. Translation of Mille Plateaux.
|
||
"Balance Sheet-Program for Desiring-Machines." Trans. Robert Hurley. Semiotext(e), Anti-
|
||
Oedipus, vol. 2, no. 5 (1977), pp. 117-135. Translation of "Bilan-programme pour
|
||
machines desirantes."
|
||
"Becoming-Woman." Trans. Brian Massumi. Subjects/Objects, no. 3 (Spring 1985), pp.
|
||
24-32. Extracts from Chapter 10 of Mille Plateaux.
|
||
"A Bloated Oedipus." Trans. Rachel McComas. Semiotext(e), Polysexuality, vol. 4, no. 1
|
||
579
|
||
580 D BIBLIOGRAPHY
|
||
|
||
(1981), pp. 97-101. Abridged translation of Chapter 2 of Kafka: Pour une litt'erature
|
||
mineure.
|
||
"City-State." Trans. Brian Massumi. Zone, no. 1II (1985), pp. 195-199. Extract from Chapter
|
||
13 ofMille Plateaux.
|
||
"Concrete Rules and Abstract Machines." Trans. Charles Stivale. Sub/Stance, vol. 13, nos.
|
||
3/4 (1984), pp. 7-19. Translation of Chapter \^i of Mille Plateaux.
|
||
"How to Make Yourself a Body without Organs." Trans. Suzanne Guerlac. Semiotext(e),
|
||
Polysexuality, vol. 4, no. 1(1981), pp. 265-270. Abridged translation of "Comment se faire
|
||
un corps sans organes," first version.
|
||
"The Interpretation of Utterances." With Claire Parnet and A. Scala. Trans, and ed. Paul Foss
|
||
and Meaghan Morris. In Language, Sexuality and Subversion. Ed. Paul Foss and Meaghan
|
||
Morris. Sydney: Feral Publications, 1978, pp. 141-157. Papers delivered at the Milan con-
|
||
ference on Psychoanalysis and Politics (May 1973); published in Deleuze and Guattari,
|
||
Politique et psychanalyse.
|
||
"One or Several Wolves?" Trans. Mark Seem. Semiotext(e), Anti-Oedipus, vol. 2, no. 3 (1977),
|
||
pp. 137-147. Translation of "Un seul ou plusieurs loups?", first version.
|
||
"Nomad Art." Trans. Brian Massumi. Art and Text, no. 19 (Oct.-Dec. 1985), pp. 16-24.
|
||
Extracts from Chapter 14 ofMille Plateaux.
|
||
"Rhizome." Trans. Paul Foss and Paul Patton. In Ideology and Consciousness, no. 8 (Spring
|
||
1981), pp. 49-71. Translation of Rhizome (the first version, published as a separate book).
|
||
"What Is a Minor Literature?" Trans. Robert Brinkley. Mississippi Review, vol. 2, no. 3
|
||
(Winter/Spring 1983), pp. 13-33. Translation of Chapter 3 of Kafka.
|
||
|
||
French
|
||
1'Anti-Oedipe.Vol. 1 of Capitalisme et schizophrenic. Paris: Minuit, 1972; 2nd ed., 1973, with
|
||
added appendix, "Bilan-Programme pour machines desirantes."
|
||
Kafka: Pour une litterature mineure. Paris: Minuit, 1975.
|
||
Mille Plateaux. Vol. 2 of Capitalisme et schizophrenic. Paris: Minuit, 1980.
|
||
Politique et psychanalyse. Alencon: Bibliotheque des Mots Perdues, 1977. Texts from the
|
||
Milan conference on Psychoanalysis and Politics (May 1973). Contains: "La place du
|
||
signifiant dans 1'institution," Guattari (revised version reprinted in La revolution
|
||
moleculaire, and included in the English edition); "Psychanalyse et politique," Guattari;
|
||
"Quatre propositions sur la psychanalyse," Deleuze; and "L'interpretation des enonces,"
|
||
Deleuze, Guattari, Claire Parnet, and Andre Scala.
|
||
Rhizome. Paris: Minuit, 1976. Modified and reprinted as the introduction to Mille Plateaux.
|
||
"Bilan-Programme pour machines desirantes." Minuit, no. 2 (January 1973), pp. 1-25.
|
||
Reprinted as appendix to second edition of I'Anti-Oedipe.
|
||
Discussions, in Francois Fourquet and Lion Murard, Les equipements de pouvoir (Paris:
|
||
10/18,1976), pp. 39-47,161-195,212-227. Revised version of Recherches, no. 13[Decem-
|
||
ber 1973], Les equipements collectifs.
|
||
"Le nouvel arpenteur. Intensites et blocs d'enfance dans 'le Chateau.'" Critique, vol. 29, no.
|
||
318 (November 1973), pp. 1046-1054.
|
||
"La synthese disjonctive." L'Arc, Klossowski, no. 43 (1970), pp. 54-62. Modified and
|
||
reprinted as Chapter 2, part 4 of I'Anti-Oedipe.
|
||
"Un seul ou plusieurs loups?" Minuit, no. 5 (Sept. 1973), pp. 2-16. Modified and reprinted as
|
||
Chapter 2 ofMille Plateaux.
|
||
BIBLIOGRAPHY D 581
|
||
|
||
by Gilles Deleuze
|
||
|
||
English
|
||
Cinema 1: The Movement-Image. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam. Minneap-
|
||
olis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986. Translation of Cinema I: L'image-mouvement.
|
||
Kant's Critical Philosophy. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam. Minneapolis:
|
||
University of Minnesota Press, 1984. With preface to the English edition. Translation of
|
||
La philosophic critique de Kant.
|
||
Masochism: An Interpretation of Coldness and Cruelty. Trans Jean McNeil. New York:
|
||
Braziller, 1971. With the text of Venus in Furs, Leopold von Sacher-Masoch. Translation
|
||
of Presentation de Sacher-Masoch.
|
||
Nietzsche and Philosophy. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson. New York: Columbia University Press,
|
||
1983. Translation of Nietzsche et la philosophic.
|
||
Proust and Signs. Trans. Richard Howard. New York: Braziller, 1972. Translation of Proust et
|
||
les signes, 2nd ed.
|
||
"Active and Reactive." Trans. Richard Cohen. In The New Nietzsche, ed. David B. Allison.
|
||
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1985, pp. 80-106. Translation of Chapter 2 of Nietzsche et
|
||
la philosophie.
|
||
"Four Propositions on Psychoanalysis." Trans. Meaghan Morris. In Language, Sexuality and
|
||
Subversion. Ed. Paul Foss and Meaghan Morris. Sidney: Feral Publications, 1978, pp. 134-
|
||
140. Translation of "Quatre propositions sur la psychanalyse" in Deleuze and Guattari,
|
||
Politique et psychanalyse.
|
||
"I Have Nothing to Admit." Trans. Janis Forman. Semiotext(e), Anti-Oedipus, vol. 2, no. 3
|
||
(1977), pp. 111-116. Translation of "Lettre a Michel Cressole."
|
||
"Intellectuals and Power." Discussion with Michel Foucault in Foucault, Language, Counter-
|
||
Memory, Practice. Ed. and trans. Donald Bouchard. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University
|
||
Press, 1977, pp. 205-217. Also trans. Mark Seem, Telos 16 (Summer 1973), pp. 103-109.
|
||
Translation of "Les intellectuals et le pouvoir."
|
||
"On Four Poetic Formulas Which Might Summarize the Kantian Philosophy." Preface to
|
||
Deleuze, Kant's Critical Philosophy.
|
||
"Open Letter to Negri's Judges." Trans. Committee April 7, London. Semiotext(e), Italy:
|
||
Autonomia, vol. 3, no. 3 (1980), pp. 182-184. From La Repubblica.
|
||
"Nomad Thought." Trans. Jacqueline Wallace. Semiotext(e), Nietzsche's Return, vol. 3, no. 1
|
||
(1978), pp. 12-20. Translation of "Pensee nomade." Also trans. David B. Allison in The
|
||
New Nietzsche, ed. David B. Allison (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 198 5), pp. 142-149.
|
||
"Plato and the Simulacrum." Trans. Rosalind Krauss. October, no. 16 (Winter 1983), pp.
|
||
45-56. Translation of "Platon et le simulacre." "The Rise of the Social." Foreword to
|
||
Jacques Donzelot, The Policing of Families. Trans. Robert Hurley. New York: Pantheon,
|
||
1979, pp. ix-xvii. Translation of "L'ascension du social."
|
||
"The Schizophrenic and Language: Surface and Depth in Lewis Carroll and Antonin Artaud."
|
||
In Textual Strategies. Ed. and trans. Josue Harari. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press,
|
||
1979, pp. 277-295. Translation of "Le schizophrene et le mot." Reprinted in Literature
|
||
and Psychoanalysis. Ed. Edith Kurzweil and William Phillips. New York: Columbia Uni-
|
||
versity Press, 1983.
|
||
"Three Group Problems." Trans. Mark Seem. Semiotext(e), Anti-Oedipus, vol. 2, no. 3 (1977),
|
||
pp. 99-109. Translation of "Trois problemes de groupe."
|
||
582 D BIBLIOGRAPHY
|
||
|
||
French
|
||
Le Bergsonisme. Paris: PUF, 1966.
|
||
Bergson. M'emoire et vie. Paris: PUF, 1957. Extracts from Bergson selected by Deleuze.
|
||
Cinema I: L'image-mouvement. Paris: Minuit, 1983.
|
||
Cinema II:L'image-temps. Paris: Minuit, 1985.
|
||
David Hume, la vie, son oeuvre. Paris: PUF, 1952. Extracts from Hume with an introduction
|
||
by Deleuze and Andre Cresson.
|
||
Dialogues. With Claire Parnet. Paris: Flammarion, 1977.
|
||
Difference et Repetition. Paris: PUF, 1968.
|
||
Empirisme et subjectivite. Paris: PUF, 1953. 3rded., 1980.
|
||
Foucault. Paris: Minuit, 1986.
|
||
Francis Bacon. Logique de la Sensation. 2 vols. Paris: Ed. de la Difference, 1981.
|
||
Instincts et Institutions. Paris: Hachette, 1953. Texts selected by Deleuze.
|
||
Logique du sens. Paris: Minuit, 1969.
|
||
Nietzsche. Paris: PUF, 1965. Extracts from Nietzsche with an introduction by Deleuze.
|
||
Nietzsche et la philosophic. Paris: PUF, 1962. 4th ed., 1973.
|
||
Un nouvel archiviste. Illustrations by d'Ipoustiguy. Montpellier: Fata Morgana, 1972. Reprint
|
||
of "Un nouvel archiviste."
|
||
La philosophie critique de Kant. Paris: PUF, 1963.
|
||
Presentation de Sacher-Masoch. Paris: Minuit, 1967. Rpt. Paris: 10/18, 1971. Lengthy intro-
|
||
duction by Deleuze with the text of Leopold von Sacher-Masoch's La Venus a lafourrure.
|
||
Proust et les signes. Paris: PUF, 1964. Augmented 2nd ed., 1970.
|
||
Spinoza et le probleme de I'expression. Paris: Minuit, 1968.
|
||
Spinoza. Philosophie pratique. Paris: PUF, 1970. Augmented 2nded. Paris: Minuit, 1981.
|
||
Superpositions. With Carmelo Bene. Paris: Minuit, 1979. The play, Richard HI, by Bene with
|
||
an essay on Bene by Deleuze entitled "Un manifeste de moins."
|
||
I "A propos des nouveaux philosophes et d'un probleme plus general." Le Monde, June 19-20,
|
||
1977, p. 16. Reprinted Recherches, Les Untorelli, no. 30 (November 1977), pp. 179-184.
|
||
Interview from June 5, 1977.
|
||
P "L'ascension du social." Postface to Jacques Donzelot, La police des families. Paris: Minuit,
|
||
1977, pp. 220.
|
||
"Capitalisme et schizophrenic." L'Arc, Deleuze, no. 49 (1972; 2nd ed., 1980), pp. 47-55.
|
||
Interview with Catherine Bakis-Clement from March 2, 1972.
|
||
"La conception de la difference chez Bergson." Etudes bergsoniennes, vol. 4(1956), pp. 79-112.
|
||
"Deux regimes de fous." In Psychanalyse et Semiotique. Actes du Collogue de Milan, 1974.
|
||
Ed. Armando Verdiglione. Paris: 10/18, 1975, pp. 165-186. Presentation by Deleuze
|
||
with discussion.
|
||
"Ecrivain non: un nouveau cartographe." Critique, no. 343 (December 1975), pp. 1207-1227.
|
||
Review of Michel Foucault, Surveiller et Punir (Discipline and Punish). Modified and
|
||
reprinted as "Un nouveau cartographe" in Foucault, pp. 31-51.
|
||
"En quoi la philosophie peut servir a des mathematiciens ou meme a des musiciens, meme et
|
||
surtout quand elle ne parle pas de musique ou de mathematiques," in Vincennes, ou le
|
||
desir d'apprendre. Ed. Pierre Merlin. Paris: Alain, Moreau, 1979, pp. 120-121.
|
||
"Faille et feux locaux. Kostas Axelos." Critique no. 275 (April 1970), pp. 344-351.
|
||
"Grandeur de Yasser Arafat." Revue d'EtudesPalestiniennes, no. 10 (Winter 1984), pp. 41-43.
|
||
"L'Homme: une existence douteuse." Le Nouvel Observateur, no. 81 (June 1-7, 1966), pp.
|
||
32-34. Review of Michel Foucault, Les mots et les chases (The Order of Things).
|
||
I "Huit ans apres." L'Arc, Deleuze, no. 49 (1972; 2nd ed., 1980), pp. 99-102. Interview with
|
||
Catherine Clement from 1980.
|
||
BIBLIOGRAPHY D 583
|
||
|
||
"Hume." In La philosophic, ed. Francois Chatelet. Paris: Hachette, 1979. Vol. 2, pp. 226-239.
|
||
I "Les intellectuals et le pouvoir." L 'Arc, Deleuze, no. 49 (1972; 2nd ed., 1980), pp. 3-10. Dis-
|
||
cussion with Michel Foucault.
|
||
I Interview. Liberation. October 23, 1980, pp. 16-17.
|
||
I Interview. Liberation. October 3, 1983, pp. 30-31.
|
||
I Interview. Le Monde. October 6, 1983, pp. 1,17.
|
||
I Interview. L'autre journal, no. 8 (October 1985), pp. 12-22.
|
||
I Interview. Liberation. September 2, 1986, pp. 27-28 and September 3, 1986, p. 38.
|
||
P "Introduction a 'La Bete humaine' de Balzac." In Oeuvres Completes d'Emile Zola. Paris:
|
||
Cercle du Livre Precieux, 1967. Vol. 6, pp. 13-21. Modified and reprinted under the title
|
||
"Zola et la felure" as an appendix to Logique du sens.
|
||
P Introduction to Friedrich Nietzsche, Legaisavoir. Lesfragments posthumes (1881-82). Trans.
|
||
Pierre Klossowski. Vol. 5 of Oeuvres philosophiques completes. Paris: Gallimard, 1967, pp.
|
||
i-iv. With Michel Foucault.
|
||
P Introduction to Johann Malfatti von Monteregio, Etudes sur la mathese, ou anarchie et
|
||
hierarchic de la science. Paris: Ed. du Griffon d'Or, 1946, pp. ix-xxiv.
|
||
"Klossowski et le corps-langage." Critique, no. 214 (March 1965), pp. 199-219. Modified and
|
||
reprinted as an appendix to Logique du sens.
|
||
"Lettre a Michel Cressole," in Michel Cressole, Deleuze. Paris: Editions Universitaires, 1973,
|
||
pp. 107-118. Translated as "I Have Nothing to Admit."
|
||
"Lucrece et le naturalisme." Etudes philosophiques, series 16, no. 1 (Jan.-March 1961), pp.
|
||
19-29. Modified and reprinted under the title "Lucrece et le simulacre" as an appendix to
|
||
Logique du sens.
|
||
"Lucrece et le simulacre." See "Lucrece et le naturalisme."
|
||
"Methode de dramatisation." Bulletin de la Soci'ete Francaise de Philosophic, vol. 61, no. 3
|
||
(July-September 1967), pp. 89-118. Presentation followed by discussion.
|
||
"Michel Tournier et le monde sans autrui." See "Une theorie d'Autrui."
|
||
"Mystere d'Ariane." Etudes nietzscheennes (1963).
|
||
"Nous croyons au caractere constructiviste de certaines agitations de gauche." Recherches,
|
||
Les Untorelli, no. 30 (November 1977), pp. 149-150. Statement on repression in Italy writ-
|
||
ten by Deleuze and signed by a number of French Intellectuals, September 20, 1977.
|
||
"Un nouvel archiviste." Critique, no. 274 (March 1970), pp. 195-209. Review of Michel
|
||
Foucault, L'arch'eologie du savoir. Modified and reprinted in Foucault, pp. 11-30.
|
||
"Penseenomade." In Nietzscheaujourd'hui?Vol. I.Paris: 10/18, 1973, pp. 159-190. Presen-
|
||
tation by Deleuze to the Colloque de Cerisy (1972), with discussion.
|
||
"Philosophic et minorite." Critique, no. 369 (February 1978), pp. 154-155.
|
||
"Laphotographic est deja tireedansleschoses," Cahiersdu Cinema, no. 352 (October 1983),
|
||
pp. 35-40. Interview with Pascal Bonitzer and Jean Narboni.
|
||
"Platon et le simulacre." See "Renverser le platonisme."
|
||
P Preface to Antonio Negri, L 'anomaliesauvage. Puissance et pouvoir chez Spinoza. Paris: PUF,
|
||
1981, pp. 9-12.
|
||
P Preface to Guy Hocquenghem. L'apres-mai desfaunes. Paris: Grasset, 1974, pp. 7-17.
|
||
P "Qu'est-ce que c'est, tes 'machines desirantes' a toi?" Les Temps Modernes, no. 316
|
||
(November 1972), pp. 854-856. Introduction to Pierre Benichou, "Saint Jackie, Come-
|
||
dienne et Bourreau."
|
||
"A quoi reconnait-on le structuralisme?" In La philosophie. Ed. Francois Chatelet. Paris:
|
||
Hachette, 1979. Vol. 4, pp. 293-339. (Abridged version ofHistoire de la philosophie. 8 vol-
|
||
umes. Paris: Hachette, 1972-1973.)
|
||
"Renverser le platonisme (les simulacres)," Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale, vol. 71, no. 4
|
||
584 D BIBLIOGRAPHY
|
||
|
||
(October-December 1967), pp. 426-438. Modified and reprinted under the title "Platon et
|
||
le simulacre" as an appendix to Logique du sens.
|
||
"De Sacher Masoch au masochisme." Arguments, vol. 5, no. 21 (Jan.-April 1961), pp. 40-46.
|
||
P "Schizologie." Preface to Louis Wolfson, Le schizo et les langues. Paris: Gallimard, 1970,
|
||
pp. 5-23.
|
||
"Le schizophrene et le mot." Critique, no. 255/256 (August-September 1968), pp. 731-746.
|
||
Modified and reprinted in Logique du sens, series 2 and 13.
|
||
"Schizophrenic et societe" in Encyclopaedia Universalis (1985), vol. 16, pp. 524-527.
|
||
"Sens et valeurs." Arguments, vol. 3, no. 15 (Sept.-Dec. 1959), pp. 20-28. Modified and
|
||
reprinted in Chapter 1 of Nietzsche et la philosophic.
|
||
"Spinoza et la methode generate de M. Gueroult." Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale, vol.
|
||
74, no. 2 (April-June 1970), pp. 426-437.
|
||
"Spinoza et nous." Revue de Synthese, 3rd series, nos. 89-91 (January-September 1978).
|
||
Reprinted as Chapter 6 of Spinoza. Philosophic pratique, 2nd ed.
|
||
"Une theorie d'Autrui. Michel Tournier." Critique, no. 241 (June 1967), pp. 503-525. Modi-
|
||
fied and reprinted under the title "Michel Tournier et le monde sans autrui" as an appen-
|
||
dix to Logique du sens. Reprinted as the postface to Tournier, Vendredi, ou les limbes du
|
||
Paciflque. Paris: Gallimard, 1972.
|
||
P "Trois problemes de groupe." Preface to Felix Guattari, Psychanalyse et transversalite. Paris:
|
||
Maspero, 1972, pp. i-xi.
|
||
"Unite de 'A la Recherche du Temps Perdu.'" Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale, vol. 68, no.
|
||
4 (Oct.-Dec. 1963), pp. 427-442.
|
||
"Sur la volonte de puissance et 1'eternel retour." In Nietzsche. Cahiers de Royaumont. Paris:
|
||
Minuit, 1967, pp. 275-287.
|
||
"Zola et la felure." See "Introduction a 'la Bete humaine' de Balzac."
|
||
|
||
by Felix Guattari
|
||
|
||
English
|
||
Molecular Revolution: Psychiatry and Politics. Trans. Rosemary Sheed. New York: Penguin,
|
||
1984. A selection of essays from Psychanalyse et transversalite and the two versions of La
|
||
revolution moleculaire, with a previously unpublished essay, "Capitalistic Systems,
|
||
Structures and Processes" (with Eric Alliez), later published in French in Guattari, Les
|
||
annees d'hiver.
|
||
"Becoming-Woman." Trans. Rachel McComas and Stamos Metzidakis. Semiotext(e),
|
||
Polysexuality, vol. 4, no. 1(1981), pp. 86-88. Also translated as "Becoming a Woman" by
|
||
Rosemary Sheed in Guattari, Molecular Revolution, pp. 233-235. Translation of "Devenir
|
||
femme," La revolution moleculaire (both editions).
|
||
"Everybody Wants to Be a Fascist." Trans. Suzanne Fletcher. Semiotext(e), Anti-Oedipus, vol.
|
||
2, no. 3(1977), pp. 87-98.
|
||
"Freudo-Marxism." Semiotext(e), Anti-Oedipus, vol. 2, no. 3(1977), pp. 73-75. Intended for
|
||
Le Nouvel Observateur but never published in French.
|
||
"Genet Regained." Trans. Brian Massumi. LAICA Journal, vol. 5, no. 47 (Spring 1987).
|
||
I Interview with Felix Guattari by Mark Seem. Diacritics, vol. 4, no. 3 (Fall 1974), pp. 38-41.
|
||
"Like an Echo of a Collective Melancholy." Trans. Mark Polizzotti. Semiotext(e), The Ger-
|
||
man Issue, vol. 4, no. 2 (1982), pp. 102-110. Translation of "Comme un echo de la
|
||
melancholic collective," in La revolution moleculaire (10/18 edition).
|
||
I "The New Alliance." Interview with Sylvere Lotringer. Impulse, vol. 10, no. 2 (Winter 1982),
|
||
pp. 41-44.
|
||
BIBLIOGRAPHY D 585
|
||
|
||
"The Proliferation of Margins." Trans. Richard Gardner and Sybil Walker. Semiotext(e),
|
||
Italy: Autonomia, vol. 3, no. 3 (1980), pp. 108-111.
|
||
"Psychoanalysis and Politics." Trans. Paul Foss. Language, Sexuality and Subversion. Ed.
|
||
Paul Foss and Meaghan Morris. Sydney: Feral Publications, 1978, pp. 125-133. Transla-
|
||
tion of "Psychanalyse et politique," first published in Politique et psychanalyse. Revised
|
||
and published in La revolution moleculaire under the title "Les luttes du desir et la
|
||
psychanalyse"; translated in The Molecular Revolution as "Psychoanalysis and the Strug-
|
||
gles of Desire."
|
||
"Psycho-Analysis and Schizo-Analysis." Trans. Janis Forman. Semiotext(e), Anti-Oedipus, vol.
|
||
2, no. 3 (1977), pp. 77-85. Extracts from an interview about Anti-Oedipus with Arno
|
||
Munster originally published in the Frankfurter Rundschau (January 17,1973). Other por-
|
||
tions of this interview were published as "La fin de fetichismes," La revolution moleculaire.
|
||
Response to questionnaire on the city. Trans. Bruce Henderson. Zone, no.l/2(1985),p.460.
|
||
I "Why Italy?" Trans. John Johnston. Semiotext(e), Italy: Autonomia, vol. 3, no. 3 (1980), pp.
|
||
234-237. Interview, unpublished in French.
|
||
|
||
French
|
||
Les annees d'hiver. Paris: Barrault, 1986. Collected essays 1980-1985.
|
||
L'inconscient moleculaire. Essais deSchizo-analyse. Paris: Recherches, 1979.
|
||
Les nouveaux espaces de liberte. With Toni Negri. Followed by Guattari, "Des libertes en
|
||
Europe," and Negri, "Lutte archeoligique." Paris: Dominique Bedou, 1985.
|
||
Psychanalyse et transversalit'e. Preface by Gilles Deleuze ("Trois problemes de groupe").
|
||
Paris: Maspero, 1972. Collected essays 1965-1970.
|
||
La revolution moleculaire. Fontenay-sous-Bois: Recherches, 1977. Essays 1971-1977. La
|
||
revolution moleculaire. Paris: Union Generate d'Editions (10/18), 1980. Essays 1972-1979.
|
||
NOTE: The two collections entitled La revolution moleculaire are substantially different. The
|
||
Recherches edition includes a section on cinema and extensive selections on semiotics
|
||
that do not appear in the 10/18 version; the 10/18 version deals extensively with the Italian
|
||
Autonomia movement.
|
||
I Interview. L'Autre Journal, no. 5 (May 1985), pp. 6-22.
|
||
"Masses et minorites a la recherche d'une nouvelle strategic." Recherches, Les Untorelli, no.
|
||
30 (November 1977), pp. 113-122.
|
||
"Semiologies signifiantes et semiologies asignifiantes," in Psychanalyse et semiotique. Actes
|
||
du Colloque de Milan, 1974. Ed. Armando Verdiglione. Paris: 10/18, 1975, pp. 151-163.
|
||
This page intentionally left blank
|
||
Index
|
||
This page intentionally left blank
|
||
Index
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Compiled by Hassan Melehy
|
||
|
||
Adam, Paul: 572 n. 9 segmentarity, 211-12; and territorial
|
||
Aesthetics: and smooth and striated space, assemblage, 327-28; of thought, 15-17;
|
||
492-99. See also Art; Epistemology and tracing, 15, 20; and writing, 5-7. See
|
||
Affect: and becoming-animal, 258-59; and also Rhizome; State apparatus;
|
||
body, 260-61; definition of, xvi; and Stratification
|
||
haeccity, 261-62; and war machine, 400. Archimedes: and nomad science, 361-63
|
||
See also Spinoza, Baruch Architecture: and consistency, 329; and
|
||
Afrikaans: as major language, 102 State science, 364-65. See also
|
||
Agriculture: West as, 18 Geometry; Science
|
||
Aguirre, the Wrath of God: 126 Ardant, Gabriel: 568 n. 35
|
||
A la recherche du temps perdu: 271-72, 289, Ardant, Will: 568 n. 35
|
||
319 Aristotle: and war machine, 417
|
||
Alembert's equation: 335 Arithmetic: see Mathematics
|
||
Alliez, Eric: 568 n. 36 Arland, Marcel: 195
|
||
Alphandery, Paul: 520 n. 23, 557-58 n. 59 Aron, Raymond: 563 nn. 104, 107
|
||
Althusser, Louis: 130, 536 n. 6 Arrow, Kenneth: 519 n. 14, 544 n. 80
|
||
Amado, Jorge: 553 n. 13 Art: and becoming, 316-17; and nomad,
|
||
Amalrik, Andrei: 470 401-2; salvation through, 185-87; and
|
||
America: as flow, 20; as rhizome, 19 smooth and striated space, 492-99; and
|
||
Amin, Samir: 566 n. 23, 570 n. 53; and territory, 320-21
|
||
capitalist axiomatic, 465, 469; and social Artaud: 542 n. 48; and body without
|
||
formation, 435-36 organs, 150, 158-59, 160, 162-63; and
|
||
Analogy: and representational thinking, drugs, 285; and nomad thought, xiii; and
|
||
xi-xii; and resemblance, 236-37. See also thought, 377-78
|
||
Representation Artisan: and flow of matter, 409; and
|
||
"And": and linguistic variation, 99; vs. "to metallurgy, 411-12
|
||
be," 25, 98 Artist: and population, 345-46. See also Art
|
||
Anti-Oedipus: xi, 3, 566 n. 22 Asimov, Isaac: 540 n. 23
|
||
Aphorism: as plateau, 23 Assemblage: and becoming, 306; and
|
||
Arborescent schema: and becoming, becoming-animal, 242, 257-60; and body
|
||
293-94; critique of, xii-xiii; of evolution, without organs, 156, 157-58; book as, 4;
|
||
10-11; as hierarchy, 16-17; of language, collective, of enunciation, 80, 85, 88; and
|
||
92-95; and line and point, 293-94; and consistency, 331-34; and content and
|
||
rhizome, 6-7, 20, 34, 328-29, 506; and expression, 88-89, 504-5; and
|
||
|
||
589
|
||
590 INDEX
|
||
|
||
deterritorialization, 333-34, 504-5; of Bartok, Bela: 342; and refrain, 349-50
|
||
enunciation, 83, 87; and exchange, Basaglia, Franco: x
|
||
437-41; and faciality, 180-81; and form Bataille, Georges: 383
|
||
and matter, 340; and haeccity, 262-63; Bateson, Gregory: 543 n. 62; and intensity,
|
||
and incorporeal transformation, 82; and 158; and plateau, iv, 21-22
|
||
language, 109-10; libidinal, 37; and Battle: and war machine, 416-23. See also
|
||
linguistic variation, 99-100; and War
|
||
machine, 343-44, 510-14; molecular, Beaufret, Jean: 529 n. 18
|
||
213; and multiplicity, 8, 22-23, 34; and Beaujouan, Guy: 572 n. 10
|
||
order-word, 108-10; and refrain, 312, Beckett, Samuel: 97-98, 199; and faciality,
|
||
323-27; and regime of signs, 119, 121-22, 173; and territorial assemblage, 503
|
||
140-41; and State apparatus, 513; and Becoming: and abstract machine, 252; and
|
||
stratification, 503-5; and subject, arborescence, 293-94; and assemblage,
|
||
264-65; and subjedification, 130, 134; 306; and causality, 283-84; and
|
||
territorial, 323-27, 332-34, 503-5; and deterritorialization, 291-92, 306-7; and
|
||
unconscious, 35; and war machine, drugs, 282-86; and haeccity, 280; and
|
||
398-403, 406-7, 513. See also Machine; heterogeneity, 10; of major and minor
|
||
Machinic assemblage; Multiplicity; languages, 104-6; and majority and
|
||
Plane of consistency minority, 291-93; and man, 291-93; and
|
||
Atomic bomb: and war machine, 404-5. memory, 291-98; molecular nature of,
|
||
See also Weapon 292-93; and music, 299-309; and plane
|
||
Attila: and war machine, 417 of consistency, 251-52, 507; and
|
||
Aurevilly, Barbey d': 193-94 pragmatics, 251; and refrain, 350; and
|
||
Austin, J. L.: 77 rhizome, 238-39, 251, 294; and
|
||
Autran, Charles: 530 n. 22 schizoanalysis, 251; and secret, 287-90;
|
||
Axiomatic: capitalist, 454-73 passim; and and sexuality, 275-79; and stratification,
|
||
diagrammatic, 143-44; and State 502-3; and structuralism, 237-38; and
|
||
apparatus, 460-73 passim; and transformation, 250-51; and war
|
||
stratification, 57. See also Capitalism; machine, 277-78
|
||
State apparatus Becoming-animal: and assemblage, 242-43,
|
||
257-59; of child, 14; and faciality,
|
||
Bach, Johann Sebastian: 511 115-16, 176, 187; and line, 245; and
|
||
Bachelard,Gaston:236,238,313,555n.32 masochism, 155-56; and molecule,
|
||
Badiou, Alain: 537 n. 20 272-75; and multiplicity, 239-52 passim;
|
||
Baer, Karl Ernst von: 46-47, 53, 254 and music, 304-5, 308-9; and plane of
|
||
Baillon, M. H.: 520 n. 20 consistency, 258-59; and psychoanalysis,
|
||
Bailly, Jean-Christophe: 521 n. 25 259-60; and resemblance, 233-35; and
|
||
Bakhtin, Mikhail: 82, 523 n. 5, 524 n. 10, State apparatus, 242-43; and
|
||
525 n. 21 stratification, 53; and transformation,
|
||
Balandier, Georges: 535 n. 4 252-53; and war machine, 242-43,
|
||
Balazs, Etienne: 565 n. 15 247-48, 396; and writing, 240
|
||
Balibar, Etienne: 569 n. 48 Beethoven, Ludwig van: 95, 270, 511; and
|
||
Balmes, Francois: 537 n. 20 refrain, 348
|
||
Balzac, Honore de: 266 Being: and State philosophy, xii-xiii
|
||
Bamberger, J.-R: 523 n. 5 Bellini, Vincenzo: 307
|
||
Bantu dialects: 102 Bene, Carmelo: and linguistic variation, 98
|
||
Barnes, Mary: 138 Bennet, E. A.: 521 ch. 2 n. 3
|
||
Barrague, Jean: 532 n. 3, 545 n. 87, 550 n. Benveniste, Emile: xviii, 78, 82, 130, 541
|
||
48,551 n. 51 n. 42, 554 n. 25
|
||
Barthes, Roland: 533 n. 7, 545 n. 88 Benveniste, R. E.: 10
|
||
INDEX 591
|
||
|
||
Berg, Alban: 339, 552 n. 61 becoming-animal, 156; and
|
||
Bergson, Henri: x, 237-39, 374, 483-84, becoming-woman, 276-77; and
|
||
486, 573 n. 17 deterritorialization, 156-57, 161; and
|
||
Berio, Luciano: 96,342,545 n. 87,546 n. 91 faciality, 171-72; and God, 150, 158-59;
|
||
Berlioz, Hector: 342 and intensity, 153, 157-58, 161, 164-65;
|
||
Bernoulli: and State science, 363 and line, 203; and map, 12, 163-64; and
|
||
Bernstein, I. S.: 553 n. 14 metallurgy, 411; and multiplicity, 30,
|
||
Berthe, Louis: 536 n. 9, 566 n. 18 154; and organism, 4, 30, 158-59; and
|
||
Bettelheim, Bruno: 542 n. 57, 543 n. 62 plane of consistency, 72, 154-55, 158,
|
||
Bible, the: and book, 127; King James, 529 159, 165-66, 270, 506-8; and plateau,
|
||
n. 16; numbers in, 118; and reality, 129; 158; and psychoanalysis, 151, 165; and
|
||
and subjectification, 131. See also schizoanalysis, 165; and signifiance,
|
||
Christ; Christianity; Religion 159-61; and smooth space, 479; and
|
||
Bifo, Franco Berardi: 572 n. 68 stratification, 56, 159-63; and
|
||
Binary relations: and arborescent schema, subjectification, 134, 159-61; and
|
||
5; and faciality, 176-80; and multiplicity, unconscious, 30; and Wolf-Man, 31. See
|
||
5; and segmentarity, 210 also Organ; Organism
|
||
Biochemistry: and stratification: 45-46, Bolero:271
|
||
49-50 Bolsheviks: 38, 88, 100, 139
|
||
Biology: and stratification, 46-48. See also Bonnard, Pierre: 175
|
||
Science Book: American and European, 19; and
|
||
Bizet, Georges: 269; and refrain, 350 arborescent schema, 5-7; and
|
||
Black English: 93-94, 102-5 assemblage, 22-23; classical, 5;
|
||
Black hole: and assemblage, 333-34; and composition of, 3-4; and
|
||
consciousness, 133; and faciality, 167-91 deterritorialization, 3-4, 11, 126-27;
|
||
passim; and line of flight, 224; and modern, 5-6; and multiplicity, 9; and
|
||
refrain, 312; and segmentarity, 211; and plateau, 22; and representation, 22-23;
|
||
stratification, 40, 56; and and rhizome, 11, 22-23; and signifiance,
|
||
subjectification, 167-68. See also White 126-27; and tracing, 24; and world, 5-6,
|
||
wall 11. See also Writing
|
||
Black Panthers: and becoming, 291 Borderline: and becoming, 245-46, 249-53.
|
||
Blanche, Robert: 570 nn. 54, 60 See also Line
|
||
Blanchot, Maurice: xiii, 265, 538 n. 29, 541 Borges, Jorge Luis: 125, 241
|
||
n. 43, 556 n. 44 Boulez, Pierre: 262, 267, 269, 296, 518 n.
|
||
Bloch, Jules: 562 n. 99 22, 519 n. 8, 527 n. 39, 541 n. 36, 548 n.
|
||
Block: and becoming, 294, 299; and 14, 553-54 n. 20; and smooth and
|
||
content and expression, 299. See also striated space, 477-78
|
||
Flow; Line of flight Bouligand, Georges: 554 n. 21, 556 n. 40,
|
||
"Blumfeld": 169 570 n. 61
|
||
Body: and affect, 256-57; and cartography, Boulte, Nicolas: 537 n. 20
|
||
260-61; and faciality, 115-16, 170-72, Boulvert, Gerard: 569 n. 44
|
||
176, 181; and haeccity, 260-61; and Bourdieu, Pierre: 524-25 n. 13
|
||
language, 80, 86; and machinic Bradbury, Ray: 541 n. 37, 570 n. 57
|
||
assemblage, 89, 90; and number, 391-92; Brain: as population, 64; as rhizome,
|
||
and order-word, 107-8; and 15-16. See also Consciousness; Thought
|
||
representation, 86; and State apparatus, Braudel, Fernand: 434, 468, 558 n. 60,
|
||
366-67. See also Faciality; Organ; 558-59 n. 64, 561 n. 79
|
||
Organism Brehier, Emile: 525 n. 18
|
||
Body without organs: 149-66 passim; and Brekle, Herbert: and linguistic competence,
|
||
assemblage, 4, 157-58; and 92
|
||
592 INDEX
|
||
|
||
Brelet, Gisele: 547 n. 102, 551 n. 50; and Carroll, Lewis: 76, 437
|
||
refrain, 349-50 Cartography: and body, 260-61; and
|
||
Breytenbach, Breyten: 527 n. 38 rhizome, 12-15. See also Map
|
||
Broglie, Louis de: 143 Castaneda, Carlos: 138-39, 227-28, 248-49,
|
||
Bronte, Charlotte: 261 282, 519 n. 7, 556 n. 38; and body
|
||
Brossolet, Guy: 520 n. 15, 563 n. 104, 564 without organs, 161-62
|
||
n. 1ll Castle, The: 132
|
||
Brouwer, L. E. J.: 570 n. 61 Causality: and evolution, 431; and plane of
|
||
Brownian motion: and crowd, 30; as consistency, 283-84
|
||
fractal, 487; and multiplicity, 33. See also Cellular chemistry: and double
|
||
Mathematics; Physics; Science articulation, 42; and stratification,
|
||
Brunhoff, Suzanne de: 538 n. 27 58-60. See also Science
|
||
Brunschvicg, Leon: 554 n. 23 Center: and multiplicity, 17-18; and
|
||
Brunswick, Ruth Mack: and Wolf-Man, 26, segmentarity, 209-10; and stratification,
|
||
31, 35. See also Freud, Sigmund; 50-52. See also Circle
|
||
Psychoanalysis Certeau, Michel de: 527 n. 36
|
||
Buchner, Georg: 25 Cezanne, Paul: 343, 347, 493
|
||
Buddha: and rhizome, 20. See also Religion Chabrier, Emmanuel: and refrain, 350
|
||
Bureaucracy: of East and West, 19-20; and Charles, Daniel: 542 n. 51, 545 n. 87
|
||
segmentarity, 210, 214; and Charriere, Georges: 561 n. 82, 575 n. 37
|
||
subjectification, 132; and tracing, 15. See Chasles, Michel: 554 n. 28
|
||
also State apparatus Chatelet, Francois: 461, 565-66 n. 16
|
||
Burroughs, William S.: 6, 152, 531 n. 14, Chatelet, Gilles: 574 n. 27
|
||
532 n. 8 Chatrian, Alexandre: 246
|
||
Butor, Michel: 546 n. 89 Chaunu, Pierre: 558 n. 60; and smooth
|
||
space, 479-80
|
||
Cage, John: 267, 269, 344, 545 n. 87 Chauvin, Remy: 10, 522 n. 15
|
||
Calame-Griaule, Genevieve: 539-40 n. 21 Chekhov, Anton: 206
|
||
Caldwell, Erskine: 520 n. 18 Cheng, Francois: 280, 542 n. 45
|
||
Calling of Saint Peter and Saint Andrew, Chevalier, Louis: 558 n. 61
|
||
The: 185 Childe, V. Gordon: 563 n. 101; and
|
||
Canetti, Elias: 33-34, 107-8, 214, 525 n. 17 metallurgy, 412, 415; and State
|
||
Canguilhem, Georges: 522 n. 9, 539 n. 13 apparatus, 428-29, 450-51
|
||
Cannibalism: and presignifying regime, Chomsky, Noam: 524 n. 7, 530 n. 38; and
|
||
118 Black English, 102; and grammatical
|
||
Capgras, Joseph: 119-20 tree, 5, 7, 12, 15,91,92, 101, 148; and
|
||
Capitalism: axiomatic of, 454-73 passim; Labov, 93-94; and minor language, 103;
|
||
and deterritorialization, 453-56; and and regime of signs, 141
|
||
rhizome, 20; and social formation, Chopin, Frederic: 271
|
||
436-37; and smooth and striated space, Christ: 124, 301, 533 n. 7; and faciality,
|
||
490-92; and State apparatus, 434-35, 176-79, 182, 184-85, 187, 189; and
|
||
447-48, 452-59; and war, 421. See also incorporeal transformation, 81. See also
|
||
Axiomatic; State apparatus Bible, the; Christianity; Religion
|
||
Capture: and State apparatus, 424-73 Christen, Yves: 518-19n. 5
|
||
passim Christianity: semiotic of, 125; translation
|
||
Cardascia, Guillaume: 568 n. 33 of, 137. See also Christ; Religion
|
||
Carnot, Nicolas: and State science, 363 Chromaticism: and linguistics, 95-100. See
|
||
Carpenter, Edmund: 557 n. 56, 572 nn. 6-7, also Music; Painting
|
||
574 n. 28 Chronochromie: 320
|
||
Carriere, Mathieu: 542 n. 50, 553 n.l 1 Church: and becoming-animal, 247-48;
|
||
INDEX 593
|
||
|
||
and segmentarity, 218. See also Subjectivity; Thought
|
||
Christianity; Religion Consistency: and assemblage, 327-28,
|
||
CIA: and war machine, 403 331-34; and deterritorialization, 336-37;
|
||
Ciguri: 160 and expression, 329-33; and
|
||
Cinema I: 518 n. 21 heterogeneity, 328-31; and music, 343;
|
||
Cinema II: 518 n. 21 and plateau, xiv; and State apparatus,
|
||
Circle: and segmentarity, 208-11; and sign, 431-32, 434-35; and stratification,
|
||
117. See also Center; Geometry 335-37. See also Assemblage;
|
||
City: and smooth and striated space, 481. Heterogeneity;-Multiplicity; Plane of
|
||
See also Town consistency; Stratification
|
||
Cixous, Helene: xii Constant: linguistic, 92, 93-94; and minor
|
||
Clairvaux, Bernard de: 364 language, 101-10. See also Linguistics;
|
||
Classicism: and form and substance, 338 Variation
|
||
Clastres, Helene: 553 n. 15 Content: and abstract machine, 511-12;
|
||
Clastres, Pierre: 528 n. 7, 557 n. 58; and and articulation, 44, 64; and assemblage,
|
||
evolutionism, 429; and war machine, 88-89, 504-5; and block, 299; and
|
||
357-59 deterritorialization, 87-89, 108-10, 307;
|
||
Clausewitz, Karl von: 218, 559 n. 68, 571 and diagrammatic, 142-45; and
|
||
n, 64; and State apparatus, 355; and war, expression, 44-45, 111; and form, 43-44;
|
||
419-21,467 and language, 85-91; molecular nature
|
||
Cleisthenes: and State apparatus, 211-12 of, 57-58; and nomad science, 369; and
|
||
Clement, Catherine: Deleuze's interview sign, 117; and stratification, 43, 57,
|
||
with, 517n. 2 60-73 passim, 502-3; and variation, 94.
|
||
Clement, Pierre: 562 n. 98 See also Expression, Form; Linguistics;
|
||
Clerambault, Gatian: 119-20, 128 Matter; Substance
|
||
Cline, W. B.: 562 n. 98 Cooper, David: 525 n. 16
|
||
Coding: and articulation, 41; and faciality, Coriat, Benjamin: 571 n. 66
|
||
170; and music, 11-12; and rhythm, Cosmos: and deterritorialization, 326-27,
|
||
313-14; and segmentarity, 222-24; and 337; and modernity, 342-43
|
||
State apparatus, 427-28, 434, 448-51, Cotard, Jules: 531 n. 2
|
||
459-60; and stratification, 40, 52-55; and Courtship: and territory, 324-25. See also
|
||
substance, 41; and territory, 322; and Love; Sexuality
|
||
tools, 60-61; and translation, 52-53. See Cousteau, Jacques: 549 n. 26
|
||
also Language; Signifiance "Crack-up, The": 198-200
|
||
Cogito: and subjectivity, 128, 130-32. See Cricket on the Hearth, The: 175
|
||
also Self(Moi) Cromwell, Oliver: 125
|
||
Communication: and language, 75-79, 85. Crowd: and multiplicity, 30; and
|
||
See also Information; Information romanticism, 341
|
||
science Crusades, the: and assemblage, 89; and
|
||
Compars: and royal science, 369-70. See flow, 220-21; and history, 23-24; and war
|
||
also Dispars machine, 383-84. See also Christianity;
|
||
Composition: see Consistency Religion
|
||
Computer science: and arborescent Crystallization: and stratification, 49-50;
|
||
schema, 16. See also Information 57-60
|
||
science; Science; Technology Cuenot, Lucien: 548 n. 21
|
||
Concept: and identity, xi; line as, 22; and Cummings, E. E.: and linguistic variation,
|
||
State philosophy, xii-xiii. See also 99
|
||
Epistemology; Idea; Thought Cuvier, Georges: 46-47, 53, 254
|
||
Consciousness: and subjectification,
|
||
131-32, 134. See also Epistemology; Daisy Miller: 290
|
||
594 INDEX
|
||
|
||
Dalcq, Albert: 531-32 n. 7 141-43, 508; and rhizome, 9-10, 21; and
|
||
Dali, Salvador: 27 science, 372; and segmentarity, 222-24;
|
||
Darien, Georges: 523 n. 2 and semiotic, 135, 138-39; and sign,
|
||
Darius: 122 67-68, 112, 113, 115-17, 121-23; and
|
||
Darwin, Charles: 46-49, 234. See also State apparatus, 432-34; and
|
||
Evolution stratification, 53-57; and
|
||
Daudin, Henri: 538 n. 1 subjectification, 133; and substance, 41;
|
||
Debussy, Claude: 270-71, 299, 319, 341-43, and variation, 99-100; and war machine,
|
||
545 n. 87; and becoming, 308; and 353. See also Line of flight; Nomads;
|
||
faciality, 169; and refrain, 303, 347 Territory
|
||
Decalcomania: and rhizome, 12-15. See Detienne, Marcel: 399, 426, 556 n. 41, 560
|
||
also Map; Tracing n. 78
|
||
Decoding: see Coding Devaux, Emile: 522-23 n. 24, 533 n. 6
|
||
Deconstruction: and feminism, xii Devil, the: and becoming-animal, 239,
|
||
Delage, Roger: 551-52 n. 59 252-53
|
||
Deleuze, Gilles: ix-x; and Guattari, xi-xv Dhorme, Edouard: 529 n. 12
|
||
Deligny, Fernand: 14, 202-3, 547 n. 1 Diaboliques: 194
|
||
Democritus: 361; and smooth space, Diagrammatic: 141 -48. See also Axiomatic
|
||
363-64, 489; and State science, 363. See Dialect: and major language, 101-3
|
||
also Lucretius; Molecule Dialogues: 517
|
||
De Niro, Robert: and becoming-animal, Dickens, Charles: 175
|
||
274 Dieterlen, Germaine: 563 n. 102
|
||
Derrida, Jacques: xi, 555 n. 32; and war Difference et repetition: x, 517 n. 4
|
||
machine, 417 Dillard, J. L.: 527 n. 39
|
||
Desargues, Gerard: 363, 365 Dimension: and becoming, 251-52; of
|
||
Descartes, Rene: 128, 530 n. 32 multiplicity, 8-9. See also Geometry;
|
||
Desire: and assemblage, 399-400; and body Space
|
||
without organs, 154-55, 165; and Discourse: direct, 84; indirect, 76-77, 80,
|
||
psychoanalysis, 13; and segmentarity, 84, 99-100. See also Language;
|
||
215. See also Libido; Love; Sexuality Linguistics
|
||
Despot: as flow, 19-20; and signifying Dislocation, La: 23-24
|
||
regime, 116-17. See also State apparatus Dispars: and nomad science, 370-71. See
|
||
Dessert, Daniel: 555 n. 30 also Compars
|
||
Detective novel: as literary genre, 192-93 DNA: and evolution, 10
|
||
Deterritorialization: and abstract machine, Dobb, Maurice: 537 n. 19, 569 n. 49
|
||
142-45; and assemblage, 333-34, 504-5; Domination: and language, 101, 105-6
|
||
and becoming, 291-92, 306-7; and body Dos Passos, John: 520 n. 18
|
||
without organs, 156-57, 161; and book, Dostoyevsky, Fyodor: 196, 257, 530 n. 29
|
||
126; and capitalism, 453-56; and Double articulation: and diagrammatic,
|
||
consistency, 336-37; and content and 142-43; and stratification, 40-74 passim,
|
||
expression, 87-89, 108-10, 307; and 502-3. See also Content; Expression
|
||
faciality, 172, 174-91 passim; and flow, Doyle, Arthur Conan: 40
|
||
219-21, 226; and language, 61-63; and Dream: and multiplicity, 30; and
|
||
line, 203-5; and line of flight, 510; and representation, 29-30. See also
|
||
map tracing, 15; and multiplicity, 9, 32, Unconscious
|
||
33; and music, 301-3; and nomads, Dreiser, Theodore: 520 n. 18
|
||
381-84; and novella, 195-200; and plane Dreissche, T. van den: 549 n. 29
|
||
of consistency, 70-71, 270, 272; and Drugs: and perception, 282-86
|
||
population, 123-25, 345-46; and refrain, Dualism: and becoming, 276-77; and map
|
||
300-302, 347-48; and regime of signs, tracing, 13-14; and multiplicity, 20. See
|
||
INDEX 595
|
||
|
||
also Double articulation Ethnology: and State apparatus, 429-30
|
||
Duby, Georges: 537 n. 19 Ethology: and consistency, 336
|
||
Duccio: 185 Euclid: and State science, 109, 364; and
|
||
Ducrot, Oswald: 77, 78, 80 striated space, 371, 489
|
||
Duhem, Pierre: 540 n. 29 Euclidean space: and multiplicity, 485-86;
|
||
Dumas, Alexandre: 250 and stratification, 47. See also
|
||
Dumezil, Georges: 556 nn. 41, 43, 559 n. Geometry; Space
|
||
67, 564 n. 8,565 n. 10; and Evans-Pritchard, E. E.: 535 n. 3
|
||
becoming-animal, 242-43; and State Evolution: and becoming, 238-39; and
|
||
apparatus, 351-52, 371, 424-26; and war heterogeneity, 10-11; and representation,
|
||
machine, 354 10; and State apparatus, 429-31; and
|
||
Duns Scotus, John: 540-41 n. 33 stratification, 47-49
|
||
Dupouy, Roger: 532 n. 11, 540 n. 32 Exchange: and assemblage, 437-41; and
|
||
Dupreel, Eugene: and consistency, 328-29 territory, 440. See also Capitalism
|
||
Durkheim, Emile: 218-19, 376 Experimentation: and body without
|
||
Duvignaud, Jean: 237 organs, 149-51, 161-62, 164; and
|
||
interpretation, 162
|
||
Earth: and deterritorialization, 40; and Expression: and abstract machine, 511-12;
|
||
romanticism, 338-42. See also and articulation, 44, 64; and assemblage,
|
||
Deterritorialization; Territory 88-89, 504-5; and block, 299; and
|
||
Ecce Homo: 269 consistency, 329-33; and content, 43-45;
|
||
Ecumenon: and stratification, 50, 52, 55, and deterritorialization, 87-89, 108-10,
|
||
56, 72-73. See also Planomenon 307; and diagrammatic, 142-45; and
|
||
Ego: Freudian, xviii. See also faciality, 179-80; and language, 85-91;
|
||
Psychoanalysis; Self (Moi); Subjectivity molar nature of, 57-58; and nomad
|
||
Eibl-Eibesfeldt, Irenaus: 547 n. 7, 548-49 n. science, 369; and order-word, 108-9; and
|
||
25, 550n.38 regime of signs, 111,140-41; and sign,
|
||
Eichendorff, Joseph: 550 n. 47 117; and stratification, 43, 57, 60-73
|
||
Einstein, Albert: 484, 501, 511 passim, 502-3; and territory, 317-18; and
|
||
Eisenstein, Sergei: 413-14, 533 n. 10, 550 variation, 94. See also Content; Double
|
||
n. 48; and faciality, 184 articulation; Form
|
||
Eliade, Mircea: 548 n. 18, 564 n. 2 Exteriority: and assemblage, 23; and
|
||
Eliot, T. S.: 520 n. 18 multiplicity, 9; and nomad thought,
|
||
Emmanuel, Arghiri: 568 n. 36, 569 n. 49 xii-xii, 377; and stratification, 49-52,
|
||
Emperaire, Jose: 557 n. 54 57-58; and territory, 317-18; and war
|
||
Engels, Friedrich: 427, 566 n. 25, 568-69 n. machine, 24, 351-80 passim. See also
|
||
41 Interiority
|
||
English: as major language, 102
|
||
Enunciation: and assemblage, 7, 22, 37; Fabric: and smooth and striated space,
|
||
and incorporeal transformation, 82-83; 475-77
|
||
and nomadology, 23; and order-word, Faciality: and abstract machine, 168-70,
|
||
107; social character of, 79-80; subject 174-91 passim; and assemblage, 180-81;
|
||
of, 129. See also Linguistics; Statement and becoming, 292-93; and
|
||
Epistemology: and war machine, 361-74 becoming-animal, 176, 187; and body
|
||
passim. See also Concept; Idea; without organs, 171-72; and Christ,
|
||
Subjedification; Subjectivity; Thought 176-79, 182, 184-85, 187, 189; and
|
||
Erckmann, Emile: 246 coding, 170; and deterritorialization,
|
||
Ernst, Max: and faciality, 182 61-62, 172, 174-91; and expression,
|
||
Esquirol, Jean: 119-20 179-80; and language, 60-62; and line of
|
||
Ethics: 153, 257 flight, 188; and multiplicity, 182-83; and
|
||
596 INDEX
|
||
|
||
refrain, 301; and rhizome, 190-91; and passim; and variation, 95. See also
|
||
schizoanalysis, 188;and semiotic, Content; Matter
|
||
180-82; and sign, 117; and signifiance, Fort-Da: and refrain, 299. See also Freud,
|
||
115-16, 179-82; and subjectification, Sigmund; Psychoanalysis
|
||
179-82. See also Body Fortes, Meyer: 535 n. 3, 536 n. 9
|
||
Farachi, Armand: 23 Foucault, Michel: xi, xviii, 517 n. 8, 518 n.
|
||
Fascism: and capitalist axiomatic, 462-63; 20, 528 n. 5, 530-31 n. 39, 536-37 n. 16,
|
||
andsegmentarity, 214-15;and State 538 n. 1, 556 n. 44; and language, 66-67;
|
||
apparatus, 230-31; as suicidal State, 231. and nomad thought, xiii; and
|
||
See also State apparatus; Totalitarianism order-word, 87; and power, xvii, 224; and
|
||
Faulkner, William: 261, 292, 520 n. 18, 572 regime of signs, 140
|
||
n.2 Fourquet, Francois: 566 n. 16
|
||
Faure, Elie: 413 Fractal: and multiplicity, 486-88. See also
|
||
Faye, Jean-Pierre: 82, 139, 536 n.l 1, Mathematics; Number
|
||
5 70-7 I n . 62 Fradin, Jacques: 566 n. 25
|
||
Feminism: and deconstruction, xii; and Francis, Saint: 178
|
||
psychoanalysis, xi Francis Bacon: 518 n. 21
|
||
Ferenczi, Sandor: and becoming-animal, Francois I: 221-22
|
||
259 "Franglais": 102
|
||
Fernandez, Dominique: 303-4, 307 Freud, Sigmund: 5, 14, 18, 29-30, 125, 127,
|
||
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb: and State 241, 284, 519 n. 9, 541 n. 41, 544 n. 78;
|
||
philosophy, xii and becoming-animal, 259; and body
|
||
Fiedler, Leslie: 282-83, 520 n. 18 without organs, 164; and multiplicity, 31;
|
||
Film: and becoming-animal, 233; and and Wolf-Man, 26-38 passim. See also
|
||
faciality, 168, 172, 175, 184; and Psychoanalysis
|
||
movement, 281 Fried, Michael: 546 n. 89, 575 n. 38
|
||
Fitzgerald, F. Scott: 194, 198-200, 206, Friendship theorem: 17
|
||
229, 520 n. 18; and becoming, 248, 260, Fuller, J. F. C.: 560
|
||
279; and smooth space, 482
|
||
Flaubert, Gustave: 541 n. 39 Gaelic: as minor language, 102
|
||
Fleutiaux, Pierrette: 200-202 Galbraith, John Kenneth: 461, 524 n. 12
|
||
Flore, Joachim de: 530 n. 23 Galileo: 511
|
||
Flow: and book, 3-4; and capitalist Galois, Evariste: 142
|
||
axiomatic, 468-69; and Game theory: and State apparatus, 352-53
|
||
deterritorialization, 11; and matter, Gardiner, Alan Henderson: 541 n. 40
|
||
409-10; and nomads, 363, 404-15 Gaulle, Charles de: and May 1968, 216;
|
||
passim; and segmentarity, 217-21, and State apparatus, 424-25
|
||
225-26; and State apparatus, 448-49, Gautier, Emile Felix: 537 n. 23, 557 n. 57
|
||
452-53, 456, 459-60. See also Line of Gavi, Philippe: 274
|
||
flight; Rhizome Gay rights movement: and psychoanalysis,
|
||
Foch, Ferdinand: and war, 416 xi
|
||
Focus: 291-92 Genesis, Book of: 87. See also Bible, the
|
||
Forbes, Robert James: 563 n. 103 Genetics: and stratification, 53; and
|
||
Form: and abstract machine, 511; and language, 62-63
|
||
articulation, 41; and becoming-animal, Genghis Khan: 226; and war machine, 354,
|
||
252-53; and classicism, 338; and content 392-93,417-19
|
||
and expression, 89; and intensity, 253; Genseric: 226
|
||
and language, 85-86; and matter, 407-9; Geoffrey Saint-Hilaire, Etienne: 45-48, 55,
|
||
of State, 448-60 passim; and 254-55, 542 n. 52
|
||
stratification, 43, 51-52, 54, 59-60, 60-73 Geology: and stratification, 40
|
||
INDEX D 597
|
||
|
||
Geometry: and nomad science, 367; and becoming, 276-77, 280; and individual,
|
||
State apparatus, 212, 362-65. See also 253; and linguistics, 263-65; and plane of
|
||
Mathematics; Number; Space consistency, 266-72, 507; and
|
||
Geroudet, Paul: 548 n. 22 psychoanalysis, 264; and science, 369;
|
||
Giotto: 178 and subjectivity, 261-65. See also
|
||
Girard, Claude: 544 n. 78 Individual; Molecule
|
||
Giscard d'Estaing, Valery: 216, 468 Haptic space: and nomad art, 492-99
|
||
Glass, Philip: 542 n. 46 Hardy, Thomas: 186-87, 332
|
||
Glossalalie (Speaking in tongues): 96 Harmand, Jacques: 564 n. 8
|
||
Gluckman, Max: 558 n. 61 Haudricourt, Andre: 18, 533 n. 12
|
||
God: and body without organs, 150, Hegel, G. W. E: 269, 556 n. 42; and
|
||
158-59; and book, 127; as cause, 3; in Deleuze's philosophy, x; and Kleist, 268,
|
||
East and West, 18; and prophetism, 356; and State, 385, 460
|
||
123-24; and stratification, 40, 43-44, 58; Heidegger, Martin: 125, 561 n. 85
|
||
and subjectification, 128, 130. See also Helioglobale: 158
|
||
Religion Helmholtz, Hermann von: 573 n. 14
|
||
Godard, Jean-Luc: 25, 97-98, 267; and Herbert, Frank: 559-60 n. 70
|
||
faciality, 172 Herzog, Werner: 110, 126
|
||
Godelier, Maurice: 530 n. 33 Hess, W. R.: 549 n. 29
|
||
Goethe, Johann von: 269, 540 n. 22, 542 n. Heterogeneity: and becoming, 250; and
|
||
52; and Kleist, 268-69, 356; and smooth consistency, 328-31; of language,
|
||
and striated space, 482; and State 100-101; and nomad thought, xiii, 24,
|
||
apparatus, 378; and war machine, 24 361; and rhizome, 7-8; of social
|
||
Golea, Antoine: 548 n. 11 formation, 435-37. See also Assemblage;
|
||
Gordon, Pierre: 539 n. 21 Consistency; Multiplicity; Plane of
|
||
Gorz, Andre: 215-16 consistency
|
||
Gould, Glenn: 8 Heusch, Luc de: 353, 528 n. 4, 543-44 n. 75
|
||
Grammar: and language instruction, 75-76. Heyting, A.: 570 n. 71
|
||
See also Language; Linguistics Hierarchy: and rhizome, 21
|
||
Grammaticality: and homogeneity, 93-94; Hilbert, David: and diagrammatic, 143
|
||
and power, 101; and variation, 99 Hincker, Francois: 569 n. 45
|
||
Gravity: and striated space, 370 History: and memory, 295-96; natural, and
|
||
Greimas, A. J.: 528 n. 6 evolutionism, 233-34; and nomads,
|
||
Griaule, Marcel: 415, 521 ch. 3 n. 2 23-24, 393-94; and segmentarity, 221-22;
|
||
Griaznov, Mikhail: 430, 560 n. 73 and State apparatus, 23
|
||
Griffith, D. W.: and faciality, 175, 183, 184 Hitchcock, Alfred: 305
|
||
Grohman, Will: 546 n. 92 Hitler, Adolf: 214, 231
|
||
Grousset, Rene: 394, 563 n. 105, 574 n. 30, Hjelmslev, Louis: 523 n. 28, 526 n. 22, 531
|
||
575 n. 37 n. 40; and content and expression, 108;
|
||
Guattari, Felix: x-xi; and Deleuze, xi-xv and double articulation, 45, 402; and
|
||
Guerin, Daniel: 214, 537 n. 24 stratification, 43; and variation, 99
|
||
Gueroult, Martial: 560 n. 77 Hobbes, Thomas: and State apparatus, 357
|
||
Guerrero, Margarita: 539 n. 10 Hocquenghem, Guy: 273
|
||
Guillaume, Gustave: 349, 541 n. 39 Hofmannsthal, Hugo von: and abstract
|
||
Guillerm, Alain: 571 n. 66 machine, 512; and becoming-animal,
|
||
Guillerm, Daniele: 571 n. 66 240, 258, 275; and order-word, 110
|
||
Gulik, Robert van: 532 n. 14 Holderlin, Friedrich: 125, 268, 332, 507,
|
||
550 n. 47
|
||
Habermas, Jiirgen: 518 n. 18 Hoist, E. von: 549 n. 29
|
||
Haeccity: and assemblage, 262-63; and Holstein, Jonathan: 572 n. 3
|
||
598 D INDEX
|
||
|
||
Homogeneity: of language, 92, 100-101; 75-76, 78-79, 85; and signifiance, 79. See
|
||
and smooth and striated space, 488-89. also Communication
|
||
See also Consistency; Heterogeneity Information science: 5, 16, 79, 179-80. See
|
||
Horticulture: East as, 18-19 also Computer science
|
||
Hubac, Pierre: 382 Intensity: and assemblage, 4; and body
|
||
Hugues-le-loup: 246 without organs, 31, 153, 157-58, 161,
|
||
Human beings: and art, 320-21, 498-99; 164-65; and form, 253; and language,
|
||
and becoming-animal, 238, 252-53; 109-10; and map, 15; and multiplicity,
|
||
enslavement of, 456-57; and faciality, 33; and plane of consistency, 70; and
|
||
170-71, 190-91; and music, 309. See also plateau, xiv, 22; and pleasure, 157. See
|
||
Man also Consistency; Plane of consistency
|
||
Humboldt, Wilhelm von: and State Interiority: and pleasure, 156-57; and State
|
||
philosophy, xii philosophy, xii-xiii; and stratification,
|
||
Hume, David: as minor philosopher, x 49-52; and territory, 317-18; of thought,
|
||
Hunt: and war, 395-96 377. See also Exteriority
|
||
Husserl, Edmund: 192-93, 545 n. 85; and Interpretation: and book, 127; and
|
||
geometry, 367; and formed matter, experimentation, 162; and faciality, 115;
|
||
407-8, 410; and multiplicity, 483 and signifiance, 114; and
|
||
Hylomorphic model: see Matter, and form subjectification, 138
|
||
Hyperion: 268 "In the Cage": 195-98
|
||
Irigaray, Luce: xii
|
||
"I": and subjectification, 130. See also Irish English: 102
|
||
Consciousness; Self (Moi); Subjectivity Isakower, Otto: 169
|
||
IBM: and war machine, 403 Isomorphy: and capitalist axiomatic,
|
||
Ibn Khaldun, (Abd al-Rahman: 366, 481, 464-66; and stratification, 46. See also
|
||
557 n. 51 Form
|
||
Icon: and sign, 112; and stratification, 65.
|
||
See also Index; Linguistics; Symbol "Jackals and Arabs": 37
|
||
Idea: and resemblance, 235; and State Jackson, George: 204
|
||
philosophy, xii; and war, 420. See also Jacob, Francois: 10-11, 42, 62, 522 n. 15
|
||
Concept; Thought Jacobs, Jane: 440, 565 n. 11
|
||
Identity: and State philosophy, xii-xiii; and Jakobson, Roman: 531 n. 41
|
||
subject and object, xi; and word, 28 James, Henry: 195-98, 290, 329, 520 n. 18
|
||
Ideology: and assemblage, 4; and content Janequin, Clement: 300
|
||
and expression, 68, 89-90 Jargy, Simon: 547 n. 3
|
||
Iliad: 426 Jaspers, Karl: 556 n. 46
|
||
Illusion: and abstract machine, 63, 65 Jaulin, Robert: 533 n. 12
|
||
Immanence: and faith, 282; and line, 205; Jevons, W. Stanley: 437
|
||
and plane of consistency, 154, 266-67; Jewish people: and becoming, 291-92; as
|
||
and pleasure, 156-57;and rhizome, 18,20 subject, 128, 130. See also Bible, the;
|
||
Immelmann, K.: 548 n. 24 Moses
|
||
Incorporeal transformation: and language, Joan of Arc: 176; and becoming-woman, 277
|
||
85; and order-word, 108-9. See also Jones, LeRoi: 527 n. 39, 530 n. 34. See also
|
||
Transformation Black English
|
||
Index: and sign, 112; and stratification, 65. Joset, Paul Ernst: 539 n. 11, 544 n. 77
|
||
See also Icon; Linguistics; Symbol Jouhandeau, Marcel: 530 n. 28
|
||
Individual: and form, 253, 254; and Jouissance: and body without organs, 154
|
||
haeccity, 261-62; and multiplicity, 254. Journet, Jean-Louis: 555 n. 30
|
||
See also Haeccity Joyce, James: 6, 53, 105, 127, 200, 209
|
||
Information: genetic, 10-11; and language, Judgment: and representational thinking,
|
||
INDEX D 599
|
||
|
||
xi-xii. See also Aesthetics 490-92; surplus, as apparatus of capture,
|
||
Julia, Dominique: 527 n. 36 441-42. See also Capitalism; Capture;
|
||
Julien, Florence: 202 Marx, Karl
|
||
Jung, Carl: 30, 235-36, 238, 241, 259, 411. Laborit, Henri: 535 n. 13
|
||
See also Freud, Sigmund; Psychoanalysis Labov, William: 93-94, 103, 524 nn. 7, 10,
|
||
Jiinger, Ernst: 403, 518 n. 3, 564 n. 6 526 n. 28
|
||
Lacan, Jacques: x, 26, 171, 529 n. 9, 543 n.
|
||
Kafka, Franz: xvii, 15, 36, 37, 76, 97-98, 71. See also Psychoanalysis
|
||
122, 225, 346, 520 n. 22, 529 n. 15,541 Lacarriere, Jacques: 539 n. 20, 566 n. 21
|
||
n. 44, 545 n. 84, 552 n. 5; and abstract La Casiniere, Joelle de: 520 n. 21
|
||
machine, 512; and assemblage, 88-89, Lagache, Daniel: 529 n. 9
|
||
505; and becoming-animal, 243-44; and Laing, R. D.: x
|
||
bureaucracy, 4, 34, 214; and Lalonde, Michel: 527 n. 37
|
||
deterritorialization, 306; and faciality, Lamarck, Chevalier de: 522 n. 8
|
||
169; and subjectification, 132; and Land: and refrain, 347-48. See also
|
||
variation, 94; and war machine, 24 Territory
|
||
Kandinsky, Vasili: 295, 298, 575 n. 38 Landscape: and faciality, 172-73; and
|
||
Kant, Immanuel: x, 367, 376, 417 music, 319; and refrain, 301
|
||
Kaufmann, Arnold: 551 n. 54 Language: and abstract machine, 148; and
|
||
Kerouac, Jack: 19,280 deterritorialization, 61-63; and faciality,
|
||
Kesey, Ken: 520 n. 18 60-62; and genetics, 62-63; and haeccity,
|
||
Keynesian economics: and capitalist 263-65; as heterogeneous reality,
|
||
axiomatic, 462 100-101; and incorporeal
|
||
Kierkegaard, Suren: 197, 279, 281, 282, transformation, 82; and line, 202-3;
|
||
376, 537 n. 17 major and minor, 7-8, 101-10; and map
|
||
Kings of the Road: 482 tracing, 77; and music, 95-97;
|
||
Kipling, Rudyard: 31 philosophy of, 86; and plane of
|
||
Klaatsch, Hermann: 533 n. 6 consistency, 91; and regime of signs,
|
||
Klee, Paul: 295, 298, 303, 304, 310, 312, 140-41, 148; and speech, 78, 92; and
|
||
337, 342, 344, 346, 347, 551 nn. 55, 58 State apparatus, 82-83, 429-30; and
|
||
Klein, Melanie: 13-14, 541 n. 41. See also stratification, 60-70; and subjectivity, 78.
|
||
Freud, Sigmund; Psychoanalysis See also Coding; Linguistics; Semiotic;
|
||
Kleist, Heinrich von: and haeccity, 268; Sign; Signifiance
|
||
and multiplicity, 9; and nomads, 378, Laplanche, Jean: 541 n. 41
|
||
381; and plane of consistency, 507; and Laroche, Emmanuel: 557 n. 51, 572 n. 12
|
||
rhizome, 25; and smooth and striated Larouche, Jean Claude: 546 n. 98
|
||
space, 482; and war machine, 4, 24, Lautman, Albert: 485, 556 n. 39
|
||
355-56, 400 Lautreamont, le Conte de: 236
|
||
Klossowski, Pierre: 131-32, 530 n. 28 Laviosa-Zambotti, Pia: 522 n. 14
|
||
Kojeve, Alexandre: 556 n. 42 Law: and science, 369-70. See also State
|
||
Koran, the: and book, 127. See also apparatus
|
||
Mohammed; Religion Lawrence, D. H.: 186-87, 188-89, 197, 205,
|
||
Kraepelin, Emil: 119 244, 251-52, 276, 546 n. 90
|
||
Krishna: and body without organs, 151. Lawrence, T. E.: 563 n. 104
|
||
See also Religion Leach, Edward: 246-47
|
||
Kristeva, Julia: 523 n. 27, 528 n. 8, 559-60 League of Nations: and State apparatus, 435
|
||
n. 70 Leaves of Grass: 19
|
||
Leclaire, Serge: and Wolf-Man, 26
|
||
La Boetie, Etienne de: 359 Leeuw, Gerardus van der: 574 n. 29
|
||
Labor: and smooth and striated space, Lelart, Michel: 536 n. 15
|
||
600 D INDEX
|
||
|
||
Lenin, V. I.: 83, 100, 563 n. 108 schema, 5; and content and expression,
|
||
Lenz, Friedrich Walther: 25, 378 90-91; and incorporeal transformation,
|
||
Leroi-Gourhan, Andre: 60, 64, 302, 395, 82; and power, 7-8, 18; and pragmatics,
|
||
407,475, 574 n. 33 85, 90-91, 97-98; and rhizome, 6-7; as
|
||
Letter to Hitler: 163-64 science, 100-110. See also Coding;
|
||
Levi-Strauss, Claude: 112, 113, 209, 210, Language; Semiotic; Sign; Signifiance
|
||
236-37, 433, 539 n. 11, 541 n. 40 Liszt, Franz: 319
|
||
Lewin, Kurt: 152-53, 169 Little Hans: 14, 256-59. See also Freud,
|
||
Libidinal economy: of West, xiv Sigmund
|
||
Libido: and body without organs, 37; and Lizot, Jacques: 176, 209, 535-36 n. 5
|
||
flow, 31; and machinic assemblage, 36; Logique du sens: x, 541
|
||
and multiplicity, 31; and unconscious, Logos: and nomos, 369-73; and State
|
||
35. See also Desire; Psychoanalysis; apparatus, xiii
|
||
Sexuality Lombard, Maurice: 558 n. 60, 562 n. 97
|
||
Lied von der Erde, Das (The song of the Lorca, Federico: 261
|
||
earth): 339 Lorenz, Konrad: 34, 239, 315-16, 547 n.
|
||
Life of Saint Francis, The: 178 46, 548 nn. 9, 12,17,23
|
||
Ligers, Z: 5 39-40 n. 21 Lory, G. M.: 527 n. 38
|
||
Limet, Henri: 561 n. 89 Losey, Joseph: 291-92
|
||
Lindon, Jerome: 529 n. 17 Louis XIV: 558 n. 59
|
||
Lindqvist, N.: 527 n. 36 Love: and body without organs, 151; and
|
||
Line: and arborescent schema, 293-94; and marginalism, 438-39; and
|
||
becoming, 279-80; and subjectification, 131-32, 134. See also
|
||
becoming-animal, 245; and body without Desire; Sexuality
|
||
organs, 203; and deterritorialization, Lovecraft, H. P.: 240, 245, 248, 251, 523 n.
|
||
203-5; and diagrammatic, 144-45; and 32
|
||
language, 202-3; and map, 202-3; and Lowie, Robert: 113
|
||
nomad art, 496-98; and novella, Lowry, Malcolm: 533 n. 8
|
||
195-202; and rhizome, 8, 21, 203, 505-6; Loyola, Ignacio de: 533 n. 7
|
||
and schizoanalysis, 202-3; and Luca, Gherasim: 97-98, 530 n. 32
|
||
segmentarity, 9, 202-7, 209, 211-12, 217, Lucretius: x, 361, 489-90. See also
|
||
222-26; and smooth space, 478-79; and Democritus; Molecule
|
||
State apparatus, 204; and Ludendorff, Erich: 563 n. 108
|
||
subjectification, 131-32. See also Luke, Gospel according to: 124. See a/so
|
||
Geometry; Line of flight; Plane; Space Bible, the
|
||
Lineage: and organization, 388, 391-92; Lulu:\S4
|
||
and phylum, 406-7; State apparatus, 393 Luther, Martin: 126
|
||
Line of flight: and assemblage, 88-89; and Luxemburg, Rosa: 537 n. 20
|
||
becoming, 277; and book, 3-4; and Lyotard, Jean-Francois: 518 n. 17,532 n. 14
|
||
deterritorialization, 510; and faciality,
|
||
188; and map tracing, 14-15; and Macciochi, Maria-Antonietta: 538 n. 32
|
||
multiplicity, 9, 32; and plane of Machine: and assemblage, 4, 343-44,
|
||
consistency, 270; and point, 298; and 346-47; and capitalism, 456-59; and
|
||
rhizome, 9, 11,21; and signifying consistency, 330-31; and diagrammatic,
|
||
regime, 116, 121-22; and stratification, 141-48; and multiplicity, 34; and music,
|
||
55; and subjectification, 133-34; and war 343; and organ, 256; and segmentarity,
|
||
machine, 422-23; and writing, 24-25. See 212-13; and social formation, 435-36;
|
||
also Deterritorialization; Line and voice, 303-4, 307-8. See also
|
||
Linguistics: 75-110 passim; and abstract Assemblage; Multiplicity
|
||
machine, 511-12; and arborescent Machinic assemblage: and body, 88-90; and
|
||
INDEX D 601
|
||
|
||
diagrammatic, 145; and enunciation, 7, Mathematics: nomadic nature of, 24; and
|
||
36-37; and multiplicity, 34; and smooth and striated space, xiii, 482-88.
|
||
nomadology, 23; and plane of See also Geometry; Number; Science
|
||
consistency, 71-73; and power, 17; and Matheson, Richard: 279, 540 n. 23
|
||
rhizome, 22; and stratification, 41-42, Matter: and abstract machine, 511; and
|
||
56-57, 68. See also Assemblage; body without organs, 43, 153; of book, 3;
|
||
Multiplicity and now, 409-10; and form, 407-9; and
|
||
McLuhan, Marshall: 360 plane of consistency, 43, 45; and
|
||
Mahler, Gustav: 339 stratification, 43. See also Form;
|
||
Maldiney, Henri: 547 n. 32, 574 n. 31; and Substance
|
||
nomad art, 493, 495 Matthew, Gospel according to: 124. See
|
||
Mallarme, Stephane: 127, 346 also Bible, the
|
||
Malmberg, Bertil: 101, 518 n. 2 Maupassant, Guy de: 193
|
||
Man: as molar entity, 292-93; white, and Maurel, Christian: 543 n. 58
|
||
faciality, 176-79. See also Human beings May 1968: and philosophy, x; and
|
||
Mandelbrot, Benoit: 486-87 psychoanalysis, xi; and segmentarity, 216
|
||
Mann, Daniel: 233 Mayani, Zacharia: 529 n. 14
|
||
Mann, Klaus: 230-31 Mazaheri, A.: 561 n. 88
|
||
Mann, Thomas: and music, 97 Mechanosphere: and stratification, 71, 74
|
||
Mannerism: and territory, 320. See also Meinong, A.: on multiplicity, 32-33, 483
|
||
Painting Mellaart, James: 565 n. 11
|
||
Manual de zoologiafantastica: 241 Melville, Herman: 186-89, 199, 205, 539 n.
|
||
Mao Tse-tung: 5, 20, 226 15
|
||
Map: and body without organs, 163-64; Memory: and becoming, 291-98; and
|
||
and line, 202-3; and regime of signs, 119; deterritorialization, 293-94; and line and
|
||
and representation, 12; and rhizome, point, 293-98; and music, 295-98; and
|
||
12-15, 19-20; and segmentarity, 222; and rhizome, 15-16; and tracing, 16. See also
|
||
tracing, 12-15. See also Cartography; Epistemology; Thought
|
||
Tracing Menaechmus: and State science, 363
|
||
Marcel, Gabriel: 362 Meneur de hups: 250
|
||
Mark, Gospel according to: 124. See also Mephisto: 230-31
|
||
Bible, the Mercier, Jacques: 533-34 n. 14
|
||
Marshall, Alexander James: 550 n. 34 Messiaen, Olivier: 94, 300, 301, 304, 309,
|
||
Marshall Plan: and capitalist axiomatic, 316-17,320,551 nn. 51,57-58
|
||
462 Metallurgy: and flow, 410-11; and nomads,
|
||
Martinet, Andre: 64, 528 n. 46, 530 n. 30 404-15 passim. See also Flow; Science;
|
||
Martino, Ernesto de: 546 n. 97 Technology
|
||
Marx, Karl: 558 n. 61, 567 nn. 27-28, Meunier, Jacques: 358
|
||
31-32, 568 n. 34, 568-69 n. 41, 570 n. 59; Meyer, Francois: 550 n. 40
|
||
and book, 127; and capitalist axiomatic, Michaux, Henri: 283, 285, 286
|
||
454, 463; and capture, 443; and State Michelet, Jules: 221-22
|
||
apparatus, 427-28, 447-48; and Micropolitics: 208-31 passim. See also
|
||
subjectivity, 453; and surplus value, Axiomatic; Molecule; Segmentarity;
|
||
491-92. See also Capitalism; State State apparatus
|
||
apparatus Milieu: definition of, xvii; of rhizome, 21;
|
||
Marxism: and major language, 105; and and rhythm, 313-16; of stratification,
|
||
State apparatus, xi 49-52, 54-55; and territory, 317-18,
|
||
Masochism: and becoming-animal, 155-56, 321-23
|
||
260; and body without organs, 150, 152, Miller, Arthur: 291-92
|
||
155-56 Miller, Henry: 18-19, 147, 166, 186-87,
|
||
602 D INDEX
|
||
|
||
248, 260, 276, 286, 482, 530 nn. 25, 31, Mr. Klein: 291-292
|
||
35, 533 n. 5, 546 n. 89, 551 n. 56 Mrs. Dalloway: 263
|
||
Millet, Jean Francois: 343 Multiplicity: and arborescent schema,
|
||
Millikan, Robert: 327 16-17, 33; and assemblage, 8, 22-23, 34;
|
||
Milovanoff, Annie: 557 n. 49, 572 n. 6 and becoming-animal, 239-52 passim;
|
||
Minority: and capitalist axiomatic, 469-73; and body without organs, 30, 154; and
|
||
and language, 105-6 book, 4-7; and crowd, 30, 33-34; and
|
||
Minor literature: 105 evolution, 48-49; and faciality, 182-83;
|
||
Minor science: 108-9, 361-74 passim, and individual, 254; and intensity, 33;
|
||
485-86 and language, 66-67; and map, 15;
|
||
Moby-Dick: 243-45, 248-50, 304, 305 molecular, 27-28; and music, 11-12; and
|
||
Mohammed: and nomads, 380, 383. See nomad thought, xiii; and proper name,
|
||
also Koran, the; Religion 37-38; and psychoanalysis, 34-35; and
|
||
Moiroux, Jacques: 537 n. 20 rhizome, 6-9, 22, 30, 33, 505-6; and
|
||
Molecule: and articulation, 34; and smooth space and striated space, 371,
|
||
becoming, 248-50, 272-86 passim; and 482-88; and stratification, 43, 52-53; and
|
||
deterritorialization, 345-46; and music, unconscious, 35; and unity, 8-9, 32-33.
|
||
308-9; and rhizome, 328-29; and See also Assemblage; Consistency;
|
||
stratification, 45, 52, 57-60. See also Machine; Plane of consistency
|
||
Becoming Mumford, Lewis: 428, 457, 570 n. 58
|
||
Mondrian, Piet: 295, 301, 305, 546 n. 89 Murard, Lion: 566 n. 16
|
||
Monet, Claude: 298 Music: and becoming, 299-309; and
|
||
Money: and capture, 442-43; and flow, consistency, 329-33, 343; and
|
||
226-27. See also Capitalism deterritorialization, 296-97, 301-3; and
|
||
Monge, Gaspard: 363, 554 n. 28, 556 n. 36 faciality, 186; and line of flight, 11-12;
|
||
Monod, Jacques: 49, 521 ch. 3 n. 3, 522 n. and metallurgy, 411; and molecule,
|
||
21, 549 n. 30, 550 n. 41 308-9; and painting, 300-303; and plane
|
||
Monsieur Zero: 279 of consistency, 267, 270-72; and refrain,
|
||
Montesquieu: 564 n. 9 347-50; and rhizome, 11-12; and smooth
|
||
Montmollin, Robert: 570 n. 56 and striated space, xiii, 477-78; and
|
||
Morand, Paul: 279 subjectification, 137; and territory,
|
||
More, Marcel: 304, 552 n. 60 318-19; and variation, 95-97, 104. See
|
||
Morgenstern, Laura: 574 n. 34 also Refrain
|
||
Moritz, Karl Philipp: 240, 512 Mussel, Lucien: 558 n. 62, 561 n. 83
|
||
Morphogenesis: and double articulation, Mussorgsky, Modest: 342, 550 n. 48; and
|
||
42. See also Form refrain, 300
|
||
Moses: 122-24, 226; and book, 127; and M'uzan, Michel de: 531 n. 5
|
||
nomads, 118, 383; as subject, 128, 130; Myrdal, Gunnar: 571 n. 62
|
||
and taxation, 394; and war machine, Myth: and becoming, 237
|
||
388, 390, 392-93, 417. See also Bible,
|
||
the; Religion Napoleon: 47, 558 n. 59
|
||
Moulier, Yann: 469, 527 n. 40, 571 n. 66 NASA: and capitalism, 455
|
||
Movement: and becoming, 280-81; and Nash, Paul: 546 n. 89
|
||
deterritorialization, 282, 326-27; and Nature: and multiplicity, 5, 254; and plane
|
||
nomads, 381; and plane of consistency, of consistency, 266; and resemblance,
|
||
281-82; and smooth and striated space, 234-35. See also Spinoza, Baruch;
|
||
498-99; and State apparatus, 386. See Substance
|
||
also Slowness; Speed Nef, John Ulric: 564 n. 109
|
||
Mozart, Wolfgang: 297, 304, 309, 350, 546 Negri, Antonio: and capitalist axiomatic,
|
||
n. 92; and refrain, 300, 347 469
|
||
INDEX D 603
|
||
|
||
Nelli, Rene: 532 n. 13 Optical space: and nomad art, 493-99
|
||
Nicolai, J.: 550 n. 37 Order-word: and content and expression,
|
||
Nietzsche, Friedrich: 23, 125, 227, 257, 108-9; and death, 107-8, 110; and
|
||
296, 342-43, 345, 541 n. 44, 552 n. 5, incorporeal transformation, 80-81,
|
||
555 n. 35; and book, 6; and 108-9; and indirect discourse, 84; and
|
||
deterritorialization, 510; and haeccity, major and minor language, 106; and
|
||
268, 269; as minor philosopher, x; and sign, 87; and speech acts, 79; and
|
||
nomad thought, xiii, 376-77; and power, statement, 107; and variation, 94-95. See
|
||
xvii; and plane of consistency, 507; and also Linguistics
|
||
refrain, 350 Oresme, Nicholas: 540 n. 29
|
||
Nijinsky, Vaslav: 169, 257 Organ: and becoming-animal, 258-59; and
|
||
Noailles, Pierre: 565 n. 10 machine, 256. See also Body; Body
|
||
Nomadology: 315-423 passim; and history, without organs
|
||
23-34; and stratification, 43 Organism: and assemblage, 4; and body,
|
||
Nomads: and art, 492-99; and 41; and body without organs, 4, 30,
|
||
deterritorialization, 53-54, 381-84; and 158-63; and double articulation, 41-42;
|
||
evolutionism, 48-49; and flow, 404-15 and faciality, 171-72; and nomad art,
|
||
passim; and religion, 382-84; and 498-99; and State apparatus, 366-67; and
|
||
semiotic, 118; and smooth space, 380-81, stratification, 43-44, 50-54. See also
|
||
384-85, 410, 413-15, 474-500passim; Body; Body without organs
|
||
and State apparatus, 384-85, 430-31; and Organization: see Stratification
|
||
war machine, 351-423passim. Seealso Orgasm: as orientation of Western thought,
|
||
Deterritorialization; Smooth space; War xiv, 22. See also Sexuality
|
||
machine Orient, the: as rhizome, 18-19; and State
|
||
Nomad science: and royal science, 367-69, apparatus, 384-85; 450-51
|
||
373-74; and war machine, 361-74 Orlando: 294.
|
||
passim. See also Pragmatics; Science Ortigues, Edmond: 564 n. 2
|
||
Nomos: and logos, 369-73; and nomad, xiii, Oury, Jean: x
|
||
370-71, 380-81; and number, 388; and Overcoding: and language, 62; and novella,
|
||
polls, 353 200-201; and rhizome, 8-9; and
|
||
Noology: and war machine, 374-80. See stratification, 63. See also Coding;
|
||
also Thought Language; Linguistics
|
||
Novel: and faciality, 173-74; as literary
|
||
genre, 192-93 Pacotte, Julien: 519 n. 13, 544 n. 82
|
||
Novella: as literary genre, 192-207 passim Painting: and deterritorialization, 301; and
|
||
Number: and measurement, 8; and faciality, 172-73, 178-79, 184-85; and
|
||
multiplicity, 484-85; semiotic of, 118; line and point, 298; and memory, 295;
|
||
and war machine, 387-94. See also and music, 300-303; and refrain, 347-48.
|
||
Geometry; Mathematics See also Faciality
|
||
Numbers, Book of: 388. See also Bible, the Parain, Brice: 523 n. 4
|
||
Parain, Charles: 569 n. 43
|
||
Object: and book, 3; in Western Parant, Jean-Luc: 534 n. 16
|
||
metaphysics, xi. See also Epistemology; Pareto, Vilfredo: 439
|
||
Subjectivity Paris, Jean: 184-85
|
||
Omnes, Roland: 521 ch. 3 n. 1 Parnet, Claire: 517 nn. 1, 4
|
||
"On Slogans": 83 Pasolini, Pier Paolo: 106,523 n. 5,527n. 39
|
||
"On the Gradual Formation of Ideas in "Passionement" (Passionately): 98
|
||
Speech" ("Uber die allmahliche Peirce, C. S.: 531 n. 41
|
||
Verfertigung der Gedanken beim Pelleas et Melisande: 299
|
||
Reden"): 378 Pelliot, Paul: 561 n. 81
|
||
604 D INDEX
|
||
|
||
Penthesilea: 355 Point: and arborescent schema, 293-94;
|
||
Perrier, Edmond: 46, 255, 522 n. 8 and line of flight, 298; and nomads, 380;
|
||
Perronet, Jean: and State science, 363, 365 and rhizome, 8; of subjectification, 129.
|
||
Petitot, Jean: 16-18, 544 n. 82 See also Geometry; Line; Plane; Space
|
||
Phallogocentrism: as model of identity, xii Politics: and axiomatics, 461; and
|
||
Phantasy: and body without organs, 151; language, 82-83, 100-110; and line, 204;
|
||
and psychoanalysis, 154-55 and war, 419-21, 467. See also
|
||
Philebus: 306 Axiomatic; Capitalism; State apparatus
|
||
Philosophy: modern, 128, 342-43; and Pollock, Jackson: 546 n. 89, 575 n. 38
|
||
nomad thought, x, xiii; and State Polyvocality: and faciality, 179-81
|
||
apparatus, ix-x, 375-76. See also Thought Pompidou, Georges: and May 1968, 216;
|
||
Phylum: machinic, 409-10; and weapon, and State apparatus, 424-25
|
||
406-7 Poncelet, Jean: 363, 554 n. 23
|
||
Physics: and smooth and striated space, Pontalis, J.-B.: 541 n. 41, 544 n. 79
|
||
488-92. See also Science Popelin, Claude: 522 n. 18
|
||
Pingaud, Bernard: 544 n. 79 Population: and deterritorialization,
|
||
Pinhas, Richard: 551 n. 53, 562 n. 94 345-46; and stratification, 52-53. See
|
||
Pink Panther. 11,25 also Crowd; Multiplicity
|
||
Pirenne, Henri: 222 Fortes du paradis, Les: 23-24
|
||
Pirou, Gae'tan: 566 n. 24 Poststructuralism: and State philosophy,
|
||
Plane: definition of, xvii; and haeccity, xi-xii
|
||
265-72 passim; of organization, 265-66. Potemkin: 184
|
||
See also Geometry; Line; Point; Space Pettier, Rene: 560 n. 72
|
||
Plane of consistency: and abstract Pound, Ezra: 105, 176, 200, 520 n. 18
|
||
machine, 70-73, 513-14; and becoming, Power (pouvoir): arborescent structure, of,
|
||
251-52; and becoming-animal, 258-59; 17; definition of, xvii; and faciality, 175;
|
||
and body without organs, 154-55, 158, and language, 7, 75-76, 95, 101, 105-6;
|
||
159, 165-66, 270, 506-8; and book, 4; of and minor philosophy, x; and
|
||
brain, 15; and deterritorialization, 70-71, psychoanalysis, x-xi; and segmentarity,
|
||
270, 272; and diagrammatic, 144-45; and 224-27; and State apparatus, 227,
|
||
haeccity, 266-72; and intensity, 70; and 431-32. See also State apparatus
|
||
language, 65, 91, 109; and line of flight, Power (puissance): and capitalist axiomatic,
|
||
270; and map, 12; and machinic 466-67; definition of, xvii; and faciality,
|
||
assemblage, 71-73; and multiplicity, 9; 175; and language, 95, 106; and war
|
||
and music, 270-71; and regime of signs, machine, 392. See also Consistency; War
|
||
141-42; and rhizome, 21; and machine
|
||
stratification, 40, 49-50, 56-57, 69-73, Pragmatics: and becoming, 251; generative
|
||
269-70; and subjectification, 134; and and transformational, 139-40; and
|
||
war machine, 422-23; and writing, incorporeal transformation, 82-83; and
|
||
268-69. See also Assemblage; language, 77-78, 92; and linguistics, 85,
|
||
Consistency; Heterogeneity; Line; 90-91, 97-98; and map, 15, 146-47; and
|
||
Rhizome nomad thought, xiii; as schizoanalysis,
|
||
Planomenon: and stratification, 50, 56, 73. 146; and State philosophy, xv; and
|
||
See also Ecumenon stratification, 43. See also Nomad
|
||
Plateau: and body without organs, 158; and science; Schizoanalysis
|
||
book, ix; and chapter, 22; and rhizome, Preaux, Claire: 563 n. 106
|
||
21-22; and smooth space, xiv-xv. See also Primitive society: and segmentarity,
|
||
Intensity; Nomads; Rhizome 209-13; and State apparatus, 357-61,
|
||
Plato: xi, xii, 559 n. 66; and royal science, 429-31, 433. See also Evolution
|
||
361,369,475 Princesse de Cleves, La: 173-74
|
||
INDEX D 605
|
||
|
||
Prison: and language, 66-67 apparatus, 375-76
|
||
Proclus: 554 Recherches: 517 n. 11
|
||
Profit: as apparatus of capture, 441-42. See Refrain: 310-50 passim; and assemblage,
|
||
also Capitalism 312, 323-27; and becoming, 350; and
|
||
Proper name: and abstract machine, 142; deterritorialization, 300-302; and music,
|
||
and body without organs, 35; and 299-302; and plateau, xiv-xv; and
|
||
haeccity, 263-64; and intensity, 27-28; territory, 317, 321. See also Music
|
||
and multiplicity, 27-28, 37-38; and Regime of signs: and abstract machine,
|
||
order-word, 84; and variation, 100; of 141-42; and assemblage, 119, 121-22,
|
||
Wolf-Man, 26-27. See also Subjectivity 140-41; authoritarian and despotic,
|
||
Property: and deterritorialization, 388; and 121-22; and deterritorialization, 141-43,
|
||
State apparatus, 428, 449. See also 508; and enunciation, 7; and incorporeal
|
||
Capitalism transformation, 88; and map, 119; and
|
||
Propp, Vladimir: 194 order-word, 83-84; and plane of
|
||
Proust, Marcel: 196, 266, 358, 526 n. 27, consistency, 141-42; and rhizome, 21;
|
||
541 n. 39, 542 n. 47, 545 n. 84, 548 nn. and semiotic, 11, 136; and stratification,
|
||
15, 19, 550 n. 46; and becoming-woman, 63, 68; and subjectification, 130. See
|
||
277; and deterritorialization, 306; and also Language; Linguistics; Semiotic;
|
||
faciality, 185-86; and haeccity, 271-72; Sign
|
||
and marginalism, 438-39; and music, Regis, Emmanuel: 529 n. 11
|
||
319; and proper name, 37; and refrain, Regnault, Francois: 526 n. 32
|
||
347; and secret, 290; and variation, 98 Reich, Steve: 542 n. 46
|
||
Proust and Signs: 518 n. 25, 526 n. 27 Reich, Wilhelm: 534 n. 22
|
||
Psychanalyse et transversalit'e: 517 n. 10 Reinberg, A.: 549 n. 29
|
||
Psychiatry: and delusion, 119-21, 128 Religion: and State apparatus, 382-84; and
|
||
Psychoanalysis: and arborescent schema, territory, 321-22
|
||
17-18; and becoming-animal, 259-60; Rent: as apparatus of capture, 440-41
|
||
and body without organs, 151, 165; and Representation: and arborescent schema,
|
||
causality, 283-84; and haeccity, 264; and 12; and assemblage, 23; and body, 86;
|
||
multiplicity, 34-35, 38; and phantasy, and book, 5-7; and heterogeneity, 10
|
||
154-55; and politics, x-xi; as priesthood, Reterritorialization: see
|
||
154-55; and schizoanalysis, 17-18; and Deterritorialization
|
||
secret, 288-89; semioticof, 125; and Reuleaux, Franz: 457
|
||
subjectification, 130-31; as tracing, Revel, Jacques: 527 n. 36
|
||
12-15. See also Freud, Sigmund; Revolution moleculaire, La: 517-18 n. 12
|
||
Schizoanalysis; Unconscious Rhizome: as antigenealogy, 10-11, 21; and
|
||
Public sphere: and private property, 451-52 arboresent schema, xii, 6-7, 20, 34,
|
||
328-29, 506; and becoming, 25, 238-39,
|
||
Quebecois: as minor language, 101-2, 104 294; and book, 6-7, 11, 22-23; and
|
||
Querrien, Anne: 364-66,556 n. 36,573 n. 24 evolution, 10-11; and faciality, 190-91;
|
||
Quinet, Edgar: 452 and language, 109-10; and line, 203,
|
||
505-6; and linguistics, 7-8, 91, 92; and
|
||
Race: and faciality, 178; and nomad map, 20; and multiplicity, 6-9, 30, 505-6;
|
||
thought, 379-80. See also Man and nomads, 415; and novella, 199; and
|
||
Ravel, Maurice: 270-71 segmentarity, 211; and smooth and
|
||
Ray, Jean: 29, 569 n. 50 striated space, 371, 506; and
|
||
Reality: and representation, 23; and stratification, 53, 74; and
|
||
subjectification, 129-30. See also subjectification, 134; as unconscious, 18;
|
||
Epistemology and variation, 95-96; and writing, 24-25.
|
||
Reason: as law, xii-xiii; and State See also Arborescent schema; Flow;
|
||
606 D INDEX
|
||
|
||
Nomads; Plane of consistency Scherer, Rene: 273
|
||
Rhythm: and consistency, 328-29; and Schizoanalysis: and abstract machine, 513;
|
||
milieu, 313-16; and refrain, 313-14; and and becoming, 251; and body without
|
||
territory, 318-20. See also Music organs, 165; and faciality, 188; and line,
|
||
Ricardo, David: 567 nn. 27-28, 30-31 202-3; and map, 13; and nomad thought,
|
||
"Rideau cramoisi, Le": (The crimson xiii; and pragmatics, 146; and
|
||
curtain): 193 psychoanalysis, 17-18; and stratification,
|
||
Riegl, Alois: 574 n. 32; and nomad art, 43. See also Pragmatics; Psychoanalysis
|
||
492-93, 495 Schleiermacher, August: xii
|
||
Riemann, Georg: 142, 573 n. 16; and Schmitt, Bernard: 445-46, 536 n. 14, 567 n.
|
||
multiplicity, 32, 482-83 32
|
||
Riemannian space: 476, 485-86. See also Schnebel, Dieter: 96
|
||
Geometry; Space Schoenberg, Arnold: and refrain, 350
|
||
Rimbaud, Arthur: 379 Schopenhauer as Educator: 376
|
||
Riviere, Jacques: Artaud's correspondence Schreber, Daniel Paul: 5, 120, 288-89, 531
|
||
with, 377-78 n. 3
|
||
Robert, Jean: 565 n. 11, 568 n. 40 Schumann, Robert: 270, 297-98, 304,
|
||
Romanticism: and territory, 338-42 307-8, 550 n. 47; and refrain, 300, 303,
|
||
Ronai, Maurice: 533 n. 13 347, 350
|
||
Rorschach test: and faciality, 180 Schwob, Marcel: 23-24
|
||
Rose, Steven: 519 n. 12 Science: and assemblage, 22-23; and
|
||
Rosenstiehl, Pierre: 16-18, 544 n. 82 axiomatic, 461; and deterritorialization,
|
||
Rossini, Gioacchino: 307 372; and diagrammatic, 143-44; major
|
||
Roth, Karl Heinz: 57 I n . 66 and minor, 108-9, 361-74; and nomads,
|
||
Rouget, Gilbert: 526 n. 29 24. See also Mathematics; Nomad
|
||
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques: 81-96 science; Technology
|
||
Roussel, Raymond: 288-89 Searle, John: 524 n. 9
|
||
Rovini, Robert: on Holderlin, 268 Secret: and content and form, 286-89; and
|
||
Royal science: and nomad science, 367-68, line, 205; and novella, 193-94, 196-97;
|
||
373-74. See also Science; State and paranoia, 288-89; and perception,
|
||
apparatus 286-87; and sexuality, 289-90; and war
|
||
"Ruse, Une" (An artifice): 193 machine, 287-88
|
||
Rush, J. H.: 522 n. 12 Sedentary: and nomad, 414-15
|
||
Russell, Bertrand: and logic, 148; and Segmentarity: and coding, 222-24; and
|
||
multiplicity, 33, 483 deterritorialization, 222-24; and line,
|
||
Ruwet, Nicolas: 99 206-7, 209, 211 -12, 217, 222-26; and line
|
||
Ruyer, Raymond: 332, 521 ch. 3 n. 3, 550 of flight, 216, 223-24; molar and
|
||
n. 36 molecular, 213, 215-17, 224-25, 228; and
|
||
Ryan, Michael: 571 n. 66 novella, 195-202; and rhizome, 211;
|
||
rigid, 212; and State apparatus, 218,
|
||
Sadock, J. M.: 525 n. 22 222-27; supple, 213. See also
|
||
Sahlins, Marshall: 573 n. 25 Consistency; State apparatus;
|
||
Saint-Geours, Jean: 569-70 n. 52 Stratification; Striated space
|
||
Salle, J. B. de la: 533 n. 7 Self (Moi): definition of, xvii-xviii; and
|
||
Samson, Joseph: 547 n. 3 order-word, 84; and subjedification,
|
||
Samuel, Claude: 548 n. 13 132, 133; and war machine, 356. See also
|
||
Sarraute, Nathalie: 196-97,267 Subjectivity
|
||
Sartre, Jean-Paul: and faciality, 171 Semantics: and speech acts, 77-78. See also
|
||
Saumjan, S. K.: 525-26 n. 22 Linguistics
|
||
Saussure, Ferdinand de: 524 n. 7 Semiology: and regime of signs, 111-12.
|
||
INDEX D 607
|
||
|
||
See also Language; Linguistics; Sign; Smith, Patti: 19
|
||
Signifiance Smooth space: and aesthetics, 492-99; and
|
||
Semiotic: and deterritorialization, 135; and body without organs, 479; and
|
||
faciality, 180-82; and regime of signs, capitalism, 490-92; and minor science,
|
||
136; and State apparatus, 135; 361-62; and multiplicity, 482-88; and
|
||
transformation of, 136-39. See also nomads, 380-81,384-85, 410,413-15;
|
||
Language; Linguistics; Regime of signs; and number, 389; and thought, xiii,
|
||
Sign; Signifiance 379-80; and plateau, xiv-xv; and
|
||
Sephiha, Vidal: 527 n. 35 rhizome, 506; and State apparatus,
|
||
Serieux, Paul: 119-20 489-92; and striated space, 353, 369-73,
|
||
Serres, Michel: 361, 371-72, 489-90, 519 n. 387, 474-500 passim; and war machine,
|
||
13, 554 n. 24, 555 n. 32 363-64, 422-23, 489-92. See also
|
||
Sexuality: and becoming, 246, 275-79; and Consistency; Nomads; Plane of
|
||
rhizome, 18. See also Desire; Love consistency; Rhizome; Space; Striated
|
||
Shakespeare, William: 125-26, 354 space
|
||
Shestov, Leon: 206, 376 Society: and segmentarity, 208-31 passim.
|
||
Shrinking Man: 279 See also Politics; State apparatus
|
||
Sign: and assemblage, 504; and book, 4; Solomon: 122, 123, 534 n. 14. See also
|
||
and content and expression, 117; and Bible, the; Jewish people
|
||
deterritorialization, 67-68, 87, 112-13, Solon: 557 n. 51
|
||
115-17, 121; and faciality, 123; and Songs and Dances of Death: 300
|
||
order-word, 87; and Signifiance, 112; "Son of Sam": 80
|
||
signifying regime of, 112; and State Sorcery: and becoming-animal, 239-52
|
||
apparatus, 118; and stratification, 64-69; passim
|
||
and thing and word, 66-67; and tool, Space: and haeccity, 261-63; holey, 413-15;
|
||
400-402. See also Language; Linguistics; and refrain, 311-12; and State apparatus,
|
||
Regime of signs; Semiotic; Signifiance 388-89. See also Geometry; Smooth
|
||
Signature: and territory, 316 space; Striated space
|
||
Signifiance: and abstract machine, 91; and Spaier, Albert: 573 n. 15
|
||
arborescent schema, 16; and body Speech: and action, 77-78; and language,
|
||
without organs, 159-61; definition of, 78, 92. See also Language; Linguistics
|
||
xviii; and faciality, 179-82; and Speed: and becoming-animal, 258-59; and
|
||
information, 79; and interpretation, 114; body, 260-61; and book, 3-4; and form,
|
||
and regime of signs, 68; and subjectifi- 254; and haeccity, 261-62; and nomads,
|
||
cation, 167-68; and writing, 22. See also 381, 499; and plane of consistency,
|
||
Language; Linguistics; Semiotic; Sign 270-71; and science, 371-72; and State
|
||
Signified: see Sign apparatus, 386; and stratification, 56.
|
||
Signifier: see Sign See also Movement; Slowness
|
||
Simmel, Georg: 544 n. 76 Speed: 152
|
||
Simondon, Gilbert: 408-10, 522 nn. 11, 19, Spengler, Oswald: 76
|
||
523 n. 31, 555 n. 33 Spinoza, Baruch: x, xiii, xvi, 123, 153-54,
|
||
Simpson, George Gaylord: 522 n. 10 158, 253-54, 256-57, 260-61, 507
|
||
Sin: and segmentarity, 218 Spinozism: 253-60
|
||
Sinacoeur, Hourya: 551 n. 54 Spirit: Hegelian, and Cosmos, 342
|
||
Sirens: 308 Spitz, Rene: 169-70
|
||
Slepian, Vladimir: and becoming-animal, Ssu-ma Ch'ien: 559 n. 69
|
||
258-60, 274 Stalin, Joseph: 525 n. 21
|
||
Slowness: and form, 254; and science, Stalinism: and segmentarity, 214-15. See
|
||
371-72; and stratification, 56. See also also State apparatus; Totalitarianism
|
||
Movement; Speed Starobinski, Jean: 552 n. 10
|
||
608 D INDEX
|
||
|
||
State apparatus: and abstract machine, 369-73, 413-15, 474-500 passim; and
|
||
223; and assemblage, 513; and State apparatus, xiii, 385-87, 489-92; and
|
||
axiomatic, 460-73 passim; and thought, 379-80; and war machine,
|
||
becoming-animal, 242-43, 247-48; and 489-92. See also Nomads; Smooth space;
|
||
book, 24; and capitalism, 434-35, Space; State apparatus; Stratification
|
||
452-59; and capture, 444-45; and coding, Strike: 413-14
|
||
434, 448-51, 459-60; and consistency, Strindberg, August: 115,132, 278
|
||
431-32, 434-35; and deterritorialization, Structuralism: and binary logic, 5; and
|
||
432-34; and flow, 448-49, 452-53, resemblance, 235-36; and rhizome, 12.
|
||
459-60; form of, 448-60 passim; and See also Linguistics
|
||
history, 23; and line, 204; and nomads, Structure: and linguistics, 92-101
|
||
384-85; and number, 388-94; and Subjectification: and abstract machine,
|
||
philosophy, ix-xii, 375-76; poles of, 134; and arborescent schema, 16; and
|
||
424-26; and power, 227; and primitive body without organs, 134, 159-61; and
|
||
society, 357-61; and religion, 382-84; and deterritorialization, 133, 134; and
|
||
segmentarity, 208-31 passim; and sign, faciality, 179-82; and interpretation, 138;
|
||
116-18, 135; and smooth and striated and line of flight, 134; and plane of
|
||
space, 385-87, 489-92; and social consistency, 134; and postsignifying
|
||
formation, 435-37; and stratification, regime, 119; and regime of signs, 130,
|
||
68-69, 433; and subjectivity, 375-76, 132-33; and signifiance, 167-68; and
|
||
460; and thought, 24; and violence, stratification, 134; and writing, 22. See
|
||
447-48; and war machine, 24, 229-31, also Signifiance
|
||
351-423 passim, 416-27, 430-31; and Subjectivity: and assemblage, 264-65; and
|
||
writing, 401-2. See also Axiomatic; book, 3-4; and capitalism, 456-59; and
|
||
Capitalism; Nomads; Stratification; haeccity, 261-65; and language, 78; and
|
||
Striated space; War machine multiplicity, 8-9; and property, 451-53;
|
||
Statement: and action, 77, 79, 86; and representation, 23; and State
|
||
definition of, xviii; and order-word, 107; apparatus, 375-76, 460; and State
|
||
and speech act, 79; subject of, 129. See philosophy, xii-xiii; and thought, 379-80;
|
||
also Enunciation; Linguistics in Western metaphysics, xi
|
||
Sternberg, Josef von: 532 n. 1 Substance: and abstract machine, 511; and
|
||
Stockhausen, Karlheinz: 266,342,551 n. 53 articulation, 41; and body without
|
||
Stoics: and incorporeal transformation, 86 organs, 153-54; and form, 43; and
|
||
"Story of the Abyss and the Spyglass, The": stratification, 43, 52. See also Form;
|
||
200-202 Matter; Spinoza, Baruch
|
||
Stratification: 40-74 passim; and Sue, Eugene: 358
|
||
assemblage, 503-5; and body without Swann's Love (L'Amour de Swann): 185-86
|
||
organs, 159-63; and book, 3-4; and Symbol: and sign, 112, and stratification,
|
||
consistency, 335-37; and content and 65. See also Icon; Index; Linguistics
|
||
expression, 502-3; and diagrammatic, Synge, J. M: 526 n. 32
|
||
142-45, 148; and plane of consistency, Synthesizer: and language, 109; and
|
||
269-70; and State apparatus, 433; and machine, 343; and musical variation,
|
||
subjectification, 134. See also 95-96. See also Music
|
||
Segmentarity; State apparatus; Striated Sznycer, Evelyne: 548 n. 16
|
||
space Szondi test: and faciality, 180
|
||
Stravinsky, Igor: 545 n. 87
|
||
Striated space: and aesthetics, 492-99; and Tale: as literary genre, 192-95
|
||
capitalism, 490-92; and minor science, Tales of Power: 162
|
||
361-62; and multiplicity, 482-88; and Tamerlane: and war machine, 419
|
||
rhizome, 506; and smooth space, 353, Tao: and pleasure, 157. See also Religion
|
||
INDEX a 609
|
||
|
||
Tarahumaras, Les: 158 Tournier, Michel: 261
|
||
Tarde, Gabriel: 216, 218-19, 548 n. 10, 575 Town: and State apparatus, 432-34. See
|
||
n. 34 also City
|
||
Taxation: as apparatus of capture, 442-43; Toynbee, Arnold J.: and nomads, 381, 482
|
||
and number, 394. See also Money; State Tracing: and arborescent schema, 20; book
|
||
apparatus as, 24; and map, 12-15; and rhizome,
|
||
Technology: and stratification, 60-61; and 12-15. See also Map
|
||
weapon, 404-7. See also Science Transfiguration, The: 17.8
|
||
Tel Quel: xi Transformation: analogical, 136-37; and
|
||
Territory: and art, 316-17, 320-21; and becoming, 250-53; incorporeal, 80-83,
|
||
assemblage, 323-27, 332-34, 503-5; and 85-88; and pragmatics, 139-40. See also
|
||
coding, 322; and expression, 317-18; and Incorporeal transformation
|
||
milieu, 317-18, 321-23; and multiplicity, Translation: and multiplicity, 486; of
|
||
33; and novella, 195; and organization, semiotic, 136-39; 486; and stratification,
|
||
388-89; and refrain, 312, 317, 321; and 62-63. See also Language
|
||
rhythm, 314-16, 320; and segmentarity, Tree: see Arborescent schema
|
||
212-13; and stratification, 40, 53-57; and Trial, The: xvii
|
||
substance, 41; and war machine, 419. See Tronti, Mario: 571 n. 66, 571-72 n. 67
|
||
also Deterritorialization Troyes, Chretien de: 174, 533 n. 8
|
||
Tetry, Andre: 547 n. 101 Troyes, Garin de: 364
|
||
Theology: and becoming-animal, 252-53. Trudaine: 365
|
||
See also Religion Truffaut, Francois: 546 n. 96
|
||
Thesiger, Wilfred: 557 n. 55-56, 572 n. 7 TV: and machinic enslavement, 458. See
|
||
Third World: and capitalist axiomatic, 465, also Technology
|
||
468-69 Typee: 188-89
|
||
Thorn, Rene: 481,539 n. 16
|
||
Thorpe, W. H.: 333, 548 n. 8, 550 n. 33 Uexkull, Jacob von: 51, 257, 315
|
||
Thought: and arborescent schema, 15-17; Unconscious: and arborescent schema, 18;
|
||
and smooth and striated space, 379-80; and body without organs, 30; and
|
||
and State apparatus, 374-80; and causality, 284; and multiplicity, 29-32,
|
||
subjectivity, 379-80; and war machine, 35; and pack, 35; and resemblance, 235;
|
||
376-78 as rhizome, 12-15, 18. See also Freud,
|
||
Timaeus: 361, 369 Sigmund; Psychoanalysis
|
||
Time: and haeccity, 261-63; and literary "Unconscious, The": 27-28
|
||
genre, 193-94 United Nations: and State apparatus, 435
|
||
Time and Free Will: 483 Universal History of Infamy, A: 241
|
||
Tinbergen, Nikolaas: 327
|
||
Titian: and faciality, 173 Vallier, Dora: 575 n. 38
|
||
Titorelli, Painter: 529 n. 15 Varese, Edgar: 309, 343, 344, 551 n. 56
|
||
To Be Done with the Judgment of God: 163 Variation: and abstract machine, 511-12;
|
||
Todaro, G. J.: 10 and deterritorialization, 99; in language,
|
||
Tokei, Ferenc: 449, 565 n. 9 93-95, 97-100; and matter, 408-9; and
|
||
Tool: and machinic assemblage, 90; and minor language, 101-10; and royal
|
||
sign, 400-402; and State apparatus, science, 369-70. See also Constant;
|
||
400-403; and stratification, 60-61; and Linguistics
|
||
weapon, 395-403. See also Technology Varron: 565 n. 10
|
||
Totalitarianism: and capitalist axiomatic, Vauban, Marquis de: 363
|
||
462; and segmentarity, 214-15; and State Vendryes, Pierre: 521 n. 3
|
||
apparatus, 230-31. See also Fascism; Verdi, Giuseppe: 307-8, 341-42
|
||
State apparatus Vergez, Raoul: 554 n. 3
|
||
610 a INDEX
|
||
|
||
Vergopoulos, Kostas: 570 n. 53 Weapon: and nomads, 403-15 passim; and
|
||
Vermeer, Jan: 347 tool, 395-403. See also Technology; War
|
||
Vernant, Jean-Pierre: 236, 536 n. 7, 543 n. Weber, Max: 5 56 n. 42
|
||
61, 559 n. 66, 564 nn. 7-8, 573 n. 21, 574 Webern, Anton von: 142, 511
|
||
n. 29 Weinreich, U.: 7
|
||
Veyne, Paul: 569 n. 44 Wenders, Wim: 482
|
||
Vialleton, Louis: 46-47 What Maisie Knew: 290
|
||
Vidal-Naquet, Pierre: 565 n. 9 White, Kenneth: 379
|
||
Virilio, Paul: 231, 395-96, 520-21 n. 24, White, Lynn Townsend, Jr.: 560 n. 79, 561
|
||
536 nn. 8, 12, 554 n. 22, 564 n. 10; and n. 86
|
||
capitalist axiomatic, 462; and White wall: and faciality, 167-91; and
|
||
deterritorialization, 345; and smooth signifiance, 167-68. See also Black hole
|
||
space, 480; and State apparatus, 212, Wilf, Herberts.: 519 n. 14
|
||
386-87; and war machine, 467 Will, Edouard: 442, 568 n. 35
|
||
Visage (Face): 96, 302 Will to Power, The: 269
|
||
Vivier,Odile:551n. 52 Willard: 233, 243
|
||
Vladimirtsov, Boris: 394, 560 n. 71 William the Conqueror: 19
|
||
Vuillard, Jean Edouard: 175 Wilson, Robert: 98
|
||
Vuillemin, Jules: 573 n. 14 Wittfogel, Karl: 19, 363, 565 n. 9
|
||
Wolf-Man, the: 26-38 passim, 239, 249,
|
||
Wagenbuch, Klauss: 527 n. 39 250. See also Freud, Sigmund
|
||
Wagner, Richard: 127, 142, 269, 270, Wolfson, Louis: 273
|
||
307-8,319,341-42 Woolf, Virginia: 29, 239, 252, 263, 276-77,
|
||
Wahl, Jean: 526 n. 32 280, 294, 329
|
||
War: and capitalism, 421, 466, 467; and Worringer, Wilhelm: 411, 575; and nomad
|
||
hunt, 395-96; and politics, 467; and war art, 415, 492-93, 495-99
|
||
machine, 416-23. See also State Wozzeck: 339
|
||
apparatus Writing: and abstract machine, 65; and
|
||
War machine: and assemblage, 406-7, 513; becoming-animal, 240; and
|
||
and becoming, 277-78; and deterritorialization, 11; and dualism, 20;
|
||
becoming-animal, 242-43, 247-48, 396; and measurement, 4-5; and memory, 16;
|
||
and body, 366-67; and capitalist and nomad art, 497; and plane of
|
||
axiomatic, 466-67, 471-73; and consistency, 268-69; and rhizome, 23*25;
|
||
diagrammatic, 144; and line of flight, and State apparatus, 401-2; and
|
||
422-23; and nomads, 351-423 passim; subjectification, 22. See also Book;
|
||
and plane of consistency, 422-23; and Language
|
||
religion, 383-84; and secret, 287-88; and Wunderlich, Dieter: 519 n. 11, 525 n. 22,
|
||
segmentarity, 218, 222-27; semiotic of, 526 n. 24
|
||
118; and smooth and striated space,
|
||
363-64, 422-23, 489-92; and State
|
||
Yoga: and body without organs, 151
|
||
apparatus, 24, 229-30, 351-427 passim,
|
||
Young, La Monte: 344
|
||
430-31; and thought, 376-78. See also
|
||
Nomads; Smooth space; State apparatus
|
||
Watt, W. Montgomery: 557 n. 50 Zavin, Fanny: 543 n. 64
|
||
Waves, The: 252, 513 Zola, Emile: 523 n. 2
|
||
Illustrations
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
|
||
Sylvano Bussoti, Five Pieces for Piano for David Tudor. By permission of
|
||
G. Ricordi, Milan. Copyright 1970 by G. Ricordi E. C. SPA. 3
|
||
Photo Boyer, Wolf Tracks on Snow. Viollet Collection. 26
|
||
Photo Boyer, Lobster. Collection Viollet. 39
|
||
Fritz Lang, The Testament of Doctor Mabuse (bullet-ridden dummie of
|
||
Dr. Mabuse). 75
|
||
The Ark of the Covenant with the Column of Fire and the Cloud. Musee
|
||
des Arts Decoratifs, Paris, Viollet Collection. 111
|
||
M. Griaule and G. Dieterlan, The Pale Fox. Institut d'ethnologie,
|
||
Musee de 1'Homme, Paris (the first Yala of Amma's egg). 149
|
||
Duccio, The Calling of Saint Peter and Saint Andrew. Bulloz Collection,
|
||
New York. 167
|
||
Faces from Jacques Mercier, Rouleaux magiques ethiopiens. Seuel. 183
|
||
R. F. Outeceault, Buster Brown, le petit facteur. Librairie Hachette. 192
|
||
Fermand Leger, Men in the Cities, 1919. Copyright 1987 by ARS,
|
||
N.Y./SPADEM. 208
|
||
Wolf-Man, Cerveteri Etruscan Amphora. Musee du Louvre, Paris. Photo
|
||
by Chuzeville. 232
|
||
Etruscan Plate. Etruscan National Museum, Rome. 232
|
||
Paul Klee, Twittering Machine, 1922. Water color, pen and ink, 16'A x
|
||
12". Collection, The Museum of Modern Art, New York.
|
||
Copyright 1987 by Cosmopress, Geneva. 310
|
||
Drawing of a Wooden Chariot. Hermitage Museum, Leningrad. 351
|
||
Chomel, Dictionnaire economique, 1732. Entry for "Perdrix" Partridge. 424
|
||
Crazy in Stripes, Vermont 1865. From Jonathan Holstein, American
|
||
Pieced Quilts (New York: Viking, 1973). 474
|
||
Computer Einstein. 501
|
||
Gilles Deleuze was a professor of philosophy at the University of Paris
|
||
at Vincennes. English translations of Deleuze's work include Kant's
|
||
Critical Philosophy: The Doctrine of the Faculties, Cinema I: Image/
|
||
Movement (both published by Minnesota) and Nietzsche and Philoso-
|
||
phy. Felix Guattari, a practicing psychoanalyst and lifelong political
|
||
activist, worked since the mid-1950s at La Borde, an experimental
|
||
psychiatric clinic. He was an active participant in the European
|
||
Network for alternatives to Psychiatry. Together, Deleuze and Guattari
|
||
coauthored Anti-Oedipus and Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature, also
|
||
available in translation from Minnesota.
|
||
|
||
Brian Massumi received his Ph.D. in French at Yale University, and is
|
||
currently a Mellon Postdoctoral Fellow at Stanford University. Massumi
|
||
translated Jacques Attali's Noise, Michel de Certeau's Heterologies,
|
||
and (with Geoff Bennington) Jean-Francois Lyotard's Postmodern
|
||
Condition—all published by Minnesota.
|
||
|